10.04.2013 Views

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Conover Bribery in Classical Athens Chapter Two<br />

Creon delegitimizes the dōrodokos by problematizing the monies used to<br />

negotiate his relations with others. While timē marks a relationship between philoi, silver<br />

or money marks relations among kakoi like the dōrodokos, at least from Creon’s<br />

perspective. 60 After all, silver money is that “bad institution” (kakon nomisma) that has<br />

arisen among men (Soph. An. 295-6). Creon is certain that a misthos or ‘wage’ of silver<br />

caused someone to bury Polynices (Soph. An. 293-4), but his language is telling, for he<br />

envisions a misthos of silver as the reward for a heinous ergon like Polynices’ burial (cf.<br />

ei)rga/sqai, Soph. An. 294), just as timē had been the reward for the good deeds of a<br />

euergetēs only a few lines prior. In effect, money replaces the timē doled out by king and<br />

polis alike, as Creon sets up two different reciprocal relationships, one negotiated by<br />

good works and civic honor (timē), the other by a misthos and dōrodokia. 61<br />

For Creon, silver money is more than a medium transacted by the dōrodokos; it is<br />

a conceptual frame for understanding their relations. There are, then, major problems<br />

with this substitution of money for timē in exchange relationships. First, as the ‘wrong’<br />

medium, silver itself symbolizes the corruption of proper relations between citizen and<br />

king. The king warns, “money by its teaching perverts men’s good minds so that they<br />

take to evil actions” (Soph. An. 298-9). It is important here that Creon does not presume<br />

that the crime was perpetrated by people who were already kakoi; instead, he infers that<br />

kakoi led astray perfectly good citizens to join their ranks (e)k tw=nde<br />

tou/touj…/parhgme/nouj, Soph. An. 293-4). It is in this sense that the money is thought<br />

60 For a fuller treatment of Creon’s views on money, see Seaford (1998: 131-8). It should be noted,<br />

however, that whereas I assume that Creon’s silver functions as a money, Seaford must argue that it<br />

specifically constitutes general all-purpose money, in the modern use of the term. The difference stems<br />

from my adoption of a relational view of economics, on which see Chapter One above.<br />

61 Creon’s use of misthos here only underscores this point. Insofar as a misthos is a payment—in cash or<br />

kind—from a superior to an inferior, it is directly analogous to the hierarchy posited when king or polis<br />

bestows honors upon a citizen. Recall that the Eion epigrams, in honor of soldiers who died in battle, were<br />

also called a misthos (Plut. Cim. 7.4).<br />

106

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!