10.04.2013 Views

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

19791 HUMAN RIGHTS 1431<br />

the general place of mens rea as a predicate of criminal liability,<br />

because one of the forms of excuse is to negative the culpable mental<br />

state (mens rea) associated with a particular actus reus. The moral<br />

theory of the criminal law here proposed clarifies both the place of<br />

mens rea and the excuses, and suggests how morally to analyze<br />

proposals to recognize novel excuses, like that of socioeconomic deprivation.<br />

Eventally, this discussion shall turn to the analysis of defenses<br />

by way of justification.<br />

In general, the first principle of just punishment-equal liberty,<br />

capacity, and opportunity-justifies the general mens rea requirement<br />

as a predicate of criminal liability. As we earlier observed,<br />

forms of mental state (intent, knowledge, and an individualized<br />

standard of negligence)IB6 would be required as necessary moral conditions<br />

of just punishment because the presence of these mental<br />

states (mens rea) insures that the person may fairly be said to have<br />

the capacity and opportunity to conform conduct to law. Accordingly,<br />

forms of strict liability are disfavored in the criminal law:<br />

residual pockets of strict liability are ~ontracting;'~~ and arguably,<br />

those that remain should be regarded as constitutionally suspect.168<br />

Similar considerations justify the place of the excuses as defenses<br />

to criminal liability-for example, the insanity defense and duress.<br />

If persons lack normal capacities to conform conduct to law as the<br />

product of mental disease or defect, they are not justly the subject<br />

of criminal penalties whose propriety rests, inter alia, on respect for<br />

the presence of capacities of autonomous choice and de1iberati0n.l~~<br />

Persons under extreme duress are justly afforded a defense on the<br />

ground that their action is not free (as the principle of equal liberty<br />

requires) and, concurrently, on the ground that conformity to law<br />

here rpquires an extreme sacrifice of basic interests (for example, a<br />

Ian See note 111 supra.<br />

IR7 See e.g., People v. Hernandez, 61 Cal. 2d 529, 393 P.2d 673, 39 Cal. Rptr. 361 (1974)<br />

(good faith belief that consenting party was not underage held to constitute defense to statutory<br />

rape charge); Director of Public Prosecutions v. Morgan [I9751 2 W.L.R. 913 (House of<br />

Lords allows that belief in consent of rape victim, even though unreasonable, is defense to<br />

rape charge). On felony murder, see G. FLETCHER, RETHINKING CRIMINAL <strong>LAW</strong> 274-321 (1978).<br />

IRB See D. RICHARDS, THE MORAL CRITICISM OF <strong>LAW</strong> 203-09 (1977). A vexing contemporary<br />

problem is the use of strict liability standards as a way of developing corporate responsibility<br />

which, otherwise, will be avoided by techniques of bureaucratic impersonality. See, e.g,,<br />

United States v. Park, 421 U.S. 658 (1975). Arguably, the use of strict liability on the terms<br />

specified in cases like Park is, in effect, a standard of negligence sub silentio, applied in order<br />

to ease the prosecution's burden of proof in cases where negligence, in the circumstances,<br />

seems patent.<br />

lap See D. RICHARDS, THE MORAL CRITICISM OF <strong>LAW</strong> 209-16 (1977).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!