10.04.2013 Views

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>GEORGIA</strong> <strong>LAW</strong> <strong>REVIEW</strong> [Vol. 13: 1395<br />

point when he argued that the "essential difference between persons<br />

and other creatures is to be found in the structure of a person's<br />

will."61 Frankfurt correctly argued that contemporary discussions of<br />

personal identity are not properly discussio,ns of the concept of a<br />

person at all, for many animals of lower species can have both<br />

predicates ascribing corporeal characteristics and states of con-<br />

sciousness whose unity is the problem of personal identity. Such<br />

animals are not, however, persons. The difference between persons,<br />

who happen to be also human, and animals is, Frankfurt argued,<br />

neither having desires or motives, nor engaging in deliberation and<br />

making decisions based on prior thought, for certain lower animals<br />

may have these properties. Rather, besides wanting and choosing<br />

and being moved to do this or that, persons, as such, also may want<br />

to have or not to have certain desires. As Frankfurt put it, persons<br />

are capable of wanting to be different, in their preferences and<br />

purposes, from what they are. Many animals appear to have<br />

the capacity for . . . "first-order desires" or "desires of the first<br />

order," which are simply desires to do or not to do one thing or<br />

another. No animal other than man, however, appears to have<br />

the capacity for reflective self-evaluation that is manifested in<br />

the formation of second-order desiresep2<br />

The second-order desires and plans of action, constitutive of<br />

autonomy, mark the capacity of a person, as such, to develop, want<br />

to act on, and to act on plans of action that take as their object<br />

changes in the way one lives one's life. For example, persons estab-<br />

lish various kinds of priorities and schedules for the satisfaction of<br />

first-order desires. The satisfaction of certain wants (for example,<br />

hunger) is regularized; the satisfaction of others is sometimes post-<br />

poned (for example, delays in sexual gratification in order to de-<br />

velop and educate certain <strong>com</strong>petences). Indeed, persons sometimes<br />

gradually eliminate certain self-criticized desires (smoking) or over<br />

time encourage the development of others (cultivating one's still<br />

undeveloped capacities for love and tender mutual response) .63<br />

Sometimes, the exercise of such capacities of autonomy is irrational<br />

@' Frankfurt, Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person, 68 J. OF PHIL. 5, 6 (1971).<br />

For a related account, see Dworkin, Autonomy and Behavior Control, THE HASTINGS CENTER<br />

REPORT, vol. 6, no. 1, at 23-28; Acting Freely, 4 Nous 367 (1970).<br />

O2 Frankfurt, supra note 61, at 7.<br />

63 On the relation of the person to rational choice, including choices of these kinds, see D.<br />

RICHARDS, supra note 60, ch. 3.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!