10.04.2013 Views

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CORPORATIONS AND RIGHTS<br />

"public good" criterion.204 If governments are not justified in using<br />

individuals for the public good, then certainly private corporations<br />

are not.<br />

Such straightforward examples of forced association are too obvious<br />

to require elaboration here. What I want to do instead is touch<br />

briefly upon the two more subtle forms of interference (or potential<br />

interference) that have generated so much discussion in recent<br />

years, endangerment and nuisance, especially as this last involves<br />

environmental issues. Once again, these are large subjects; my purpose<br />

here is simply to draw the general outline that is prescribed by<br />

the theory of rights, which might then serve as background for more<br />

detailed legal analysis.<br />

As we saw earlier,205 the problem of endangerment arises in principle<br />

whenever individuals perform positive acts in the proximity of<br />

others. (I will use "endangerment" and "risk" rather than the more<br />

subjective "fear" in order to suggest that I am talking here about a<br />

phenomenon with some real basis in fact.) In the corporate context,<br />

the acts that endanger often do so by creating conditions or products<br />

that endanger, conditions affecting workers, say, or homeowners<br />

living near industrial <strong>com</strong>plexes, or products that may harm consumers.<br />

Thus the causal sequence is often <strong>com</strong>plex, involving an<br />

intervening act of the victim, or of some thi~d party, or of nature<br />

(which may or may not serve to negative liability, depending upon<br />

the <strong>com</strong>plex rules of liability in such cases). Yet we allow a good<br />

many of these individual and corporate acts and the risky conditions<br />

they create; otherwise, life in reasonable proximity with each other<br />

would cease. What we want to know, then, at least in general outline,<br />

is how the theory of rights orders this problem. Just what rights<br />

and obligations are there in the matter?<br />

What is required in general, recall, is that acts or conditions not<br />

take what others own. As the acts of one person increasingly involve<br />

risk for others, these others are to some corresponding degree unable<br />

to make peaceful use of what they own, even if the risk does not in<br />

fact materialize. But there is a large subjective element in all of this;<br />

moreover, the issues are context-specific, varying greatly from, say,<br />

nuclear power plant risks to products liability cases (and greatly in<br />

turn within this last category). We are faced, then, with a very<br />

difficult and <strong>com</strong>plex line-drawing problem: in principle there are<br />

m4 Cf, Eldridge v. Smith, 34 Vt. 484, 492-93 (1861).<br />

205 See notes 85 & 86 and ac<strong>com</strong>panying text supra.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!