10.04.2013 Views

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

19791 CORPORATIONS AND RIGHTS 1291<br />

one line of argument would have it,lL6 then all the arbitrariness we<br />

want to avoid can enter. And indeed, if the object of acceptance is<br />

in subsequent disagreement, then the original act of agreement itself<br />

is called into question.<br />

In order to avoid these difficulties, then, we have to do what we<br />

did in the case of general relationships, viz., look to the property<br />

foundations of the agreement. Not only will this give empirical and<br />

hence objective content to the interaction, but it will capture the<br />

transfer aspect of a contract as well. Expectations fit un<strong>com</strong>fortably<br />

here at best; while it is true that we create expectations in others<br />

when we act, these can hardly be objects of transfer. (In truth, they<br />

describe only our views about what has in fact been transferred.) I<br />

suggest, therefore, that we treat each contractor as having transferred<br />

to the other the title to something he owns, some future act<br />

or course of action, some piece of tangible property. What each<br />

party accepts, then, is the exchange of titles between the parties,<br />

not the subjective expectations that this exchange may have created.<br />

For the transfer to be morally legitimate, however, and hence for<br />

the rights and obligations that result from it to be justified, it is<br />

imperative that the acceptance that consummates it be voluntary.<br />

Thus the process must be free from duress, which occurs when one<br />

of the parties uses or threatens to use force in order to extract the'<br />

agreement, thereby vitiating the act of acceptance itself. With duress<br />

we have two distinct takings: the use or threat of force in such<br />

a situation is an intentional taking; and the involuntary transfer of<br />

the object thus extracted amounts to a further taking. While it is<br />

possible, with care, to include "undue influence" under the concept<br />

of duress-for here it is arguable that consent is vitiated by the acts<br />

of one of the parties-it is not possible to include so-called<br />

"economic duress." That A was "<strong>com</strong>pelled" by his own private<br />

necessity to enter into an agreement with B is no reason to set that<br />

agreement aside. (Necessity of one kind or another is what leads to<br />

all exchanges.) If B has a perfect right to make no offer-and of<br />

course he does-then he has a right to make the offer that A accepts.<br />

To be sure, A could accept B's offer and then have it adjusted by<br />

the court on a finding of "substantive unconscionability"; but in<br />

- -<br />

5 88, at 162-63 (1959). These disagreements in<br />

LLVee, eg., 3 R. POUND, JURISPRUDENCE<br />

contract theory often relate as much to questions of evidence or proof as to substantive<br />

questions about the nature of the contractual agreement. But these are distinct issues, and<br />

should be kept so, however closely related they may be.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!