10.04.2013 Views

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

GEORGIA LAW REVIEW - StephanKinsella.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CORPORATIONS AND RIGHTS<br />

I want to proceed, then, by simply assuming that just as "being<br />

there first" seems to generate a property right in the status quo, so<br />

"getting there first" generates a similar right as individuals move<br />

out of the status quo. At the very least one could add that no one<br />

else has a better claim to what has been "staked out" than the<br />

person who has made the effort to do that; certainly those who have<br />

done nothing have no claim. Let us assume also that boundary<br />

problems will work themselves out with reference to economic considerations,<br />

economies of scale, and so forth. As our individuals<br />

move out of the status quo, then, property will arise, claims will be<br />

staked out, and the world will eventually get divided up-all of<br />

which can happen, in principle, without anyone's rights being violated.<br />

Or can it? Are there limits to what an individual can claim<br />

(or to what he can claim in <strong>com</strong>bination with others), after which<br />

any further claiming will violate the rights of others? (Antitrust<br />

theorists take note!)<br />

The tradition, at this point, is to invoke some version of Locke's<br />

proviso, that we can acquire provided there is "enough and as good<br />

left in <strong>com</strong>mon for others."95 Thus Nozick pursues, with some invention,<br />

"the crucial point," which is "whether appropriation of an<br />

unowned object worsens the situation of others."" For Locke, " 'tis<br />

very clear, that God, as King David says, Psal. CXV, xvi, has given<br />

the Earth to the Children of Men, given it to Mankind in <strong>com</strong>m~n."~<br />

The problem before Locke, then, is to show how private<br />

property arises out of this <strong>com</strong>mon property. For it would appear<br />

that all must give their consent before such acquisitions can occur.<br />

At the least, the proviso would seem justified in this setting in that<br />

it insures that the situation of others is not "worsened," as Nozick<br />

puts it.<br />

It is at this important juncture, I should argue, that the theory<br />

or rights must bite the bullet: the dis<strong>com</strong>forting conclusions must<br />

In the ordinary world, of course, we get around the difficulty that arises from everyone's<br />

having an equal right to control the public spaces by establishing rules of conduct for such<br />

spaces, which we determine according to some decision procedure. But this is a practical<br />

expedient only; i. e., the conduct set by these rules cannot be seen as a direct manifestation<br />

of our individual wishes-as is possible in our own private spaces-but is rather a reflection,<br />

in our society, of majority opinion (e.g., nude bathing prohibited in San Diego, California)<br />

or earlier-affirmed rules (e.g., Nazi marching permitted in Skokie, Illinois). The democratic<br />

device, in short, gives us nothing like the liberty insured by the private device. See Berlin,<br />

Two Concepts of Liberty, in FOUR ESSAYS ON LIBERTY 118-72 (1969).<br />

O5 J. LOCKE, supra note 58, § 27.<br />

B6 R. NOZICK, supra note 11, at 175.<br />

O7 J. LOCKE, supra note 58, 5 25.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!