10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

On <strong>the</strong> Existence of Contents <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Doctrine 75<br />

whoever rejects or denies A judges correctly. <strong>The</strong> formula does not at all require that, if<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no A, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re has to be something else— <strong>the</strong> non-being of A—to function in its<br />

place. A itself is <strong>the</strong> thing with which our judgement is concerned.<br />

If A is to be affirmed, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> affirming judgement may be said to be true <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> negative<br />

judgement false, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> one who accepts or affirms A may be said to judge correctly <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> one who rejects or denies it to judge incorrectly. Similarly for <strong>the</strong> case where A is not:<br />

<strong>the</strong> judgement affirming A may be said to be false <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> judgement denying it may be<br />

said to be true; <strong>the</strong> one who affirms A judges incorrectly <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> one who denies A judges<br />

correctly. 7 <strong>The</strong>re is not <strong>the</strong> slightest justification for supposing that <strong>the</strong> term “adaequatio”,<br />

or “correspondence”, designates a relation which, in order to hold, requires <strong>the</strong> existence of<br />

two terms. <strong>The</strong> object of a correct denial or rejection is not something which exists, except<br />

in <strong>the</strong> sense in which one says, improperly, that whatever is thought “exists in <strong>the</strong> mind”.<br />

<strong>The</strong> principle of <strong>the</strong> adaequatio rei et intellectus does not require that a negative judgement<br />

correspond to an object (viz., <strong>the</strong> non-being of something) which exists. <strong>The</strong> adaequatio<br />

consists precisely in <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> object of <strong>the</strong> judgement does not exist <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> one<br />

who judges denies its existence. 8<br />

12. Some have even gone so far as to say that, whoever thus rejects <strong>the</strong> existence of a nonbeing,<br />

is guilty of subjectivism <strong>and</strong> psychologism. 9 Nothing could be less justified. For <strong>the</strong><br />

subjectivist, <strong>the</strong>re is no “A is” or “A is not”; one says only, “A is for me (or for someone<br />

or o<strong>the</strong>r)”. Nei<strong>the</strong>r acceptance nor rejection of <strong>the</strong> doctrine that <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> being of A, or<br />

<strong>the</strong> non-being of A, commits anyone to subjectivism. <strong>The</strong> proponent of psychologism, on<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, goes wrong in confusing a judgement’s being evident with <strong>the</strong> fact that it<br />

is natural for all, or almost all, of <strong>the</strong> members of a certain species to judge in a certain<br />

way. 10 He does not distinguish what one “ought” to do from what one is “compelled” to<br />

do, <strong>and</strong> in consequence he plays into <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s of subjectivism. But nothing of this sort is<br />

implied when we say that <strong>the</strong> objects of affirmation <strong>and</strong> denial are always only things <strong>and</strong><br />

never <strong>the</strong> being or <strong>the</strong> non-being of things. We say, of those who affirm or deny a thing,<br />

that some do it, not blindly, but with evidence. Judging with evidence excludes not only <strong>the</strong><br />

possibility of error, but also <strong>the</strong> possibility that <strong>the</strong>re be anyone judging to <strong>the</strong> contrary who<br />

is not in error. 11 <strong>The</strong>re is no being of A <strong>and</strong> no non-being of A, but ei<strong>the</strong>r A is or A is not;<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore, of two people who judge that A is, it is not possible that <strong>the</strong> one is judging<br />

correctly <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r incorrectly. And similarly for any two people who judge that A is<br />

not.<br />

So <strong>the</strong> entire objection is based upon a misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing.<br />

13. We have said that those who oppose our view have misinterpreted <strong>the</strong> statement,<br />

“Veritas est adaequatio rei et intellectus”. If <strong>the</strong>ir interpretation were correct, <strong>the</strong>n in order<br />

to know that a certain thing exists, one would have to know that <strong>the</strong>re is a certain equality<br />

or similarity holding between something that is in <strong>the</strong> mind <strong>and</strong> something that is outside<br />

it. Knowledge of this equality or similarity would <strong>the</strong>n presuppose that one had compared<br />

<strong>the</strong> two. But how does one compare something that is in <strong>the</strong> mind with something that is<br />

not in <strong>the</strong> mind? Our knowledge of what is not in <strong>the</strong> mind is certainly not acquired as a<br />

result of making a comparison. Where such knowledge is immediately given, it is a matter<br />

of a simple <strong>and</strong> evident apprehension. 12

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!