10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

66<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>True</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Evident</strong><br />

degree of abstraction is what it is that Marty dared to reject. I cannot forbear expressing my<br />

surprise <strong>and</strong> regret that Marty permitted himself to deviate from long-established usage.<br />

He transformed <strong>the</strong> concept of thing into <strong>the</strong> concept of that which is capable of causal<br />

efficacy; in this way, a term which has traditionally been <strong>the</strong> most simple <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> most<br />

general of all our terms has been transformed into one designating a sophisticated <strong>and</strong><br />

complex concept which has been a matter of controversy since <strong>the</strong> time of Hume. Given<br />

Marty’s sense of <strong>the</strong> term “thing”, we would have to say that according to Hume <strong>and</strong> Mill<br />

<strong>and</strong> many o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>the</strong>re are no things at all! 41 Could anything show more clearly that Marty<br />

has permitted himself to alter terminology in an entirely arbitrary way? And if we go back<br />

from modern times to <strong>the</strong> Middle Ages <strong>and</strong> to antiquity, we are equally struck by Marty’s<br />

deviation from what has been a consistent usage throughout all times. Thus, according to<br />

Thomas, <strong>the</strong> concept of a thing, of being in <strong>the</strong> sense of <strong>the</strong> real, is <strong>the</strong> most general concept<br />

to which reason can attain. Could he have imagined that one would think of a “thing” as<br />

being equivalent to that which is capable of causal efficacy? And in antiquity Aristotle had<br />

declared <strong>the</strong> concept of thing to be included in <strong>the</strong> concepts of substance <strong>and</strong> of accident.<br />

Note he would have contradicted himself if he had identified thing with <strong>the</strong> concept of<br />

causal efficacy, for he cites as a special category which falls under <strong>the</strong> accidental!<br />

I think I may say that Marty’s highly irregular deviation from traditional usage has o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

unfortunate consequences. A good many of <strong>the</strong> misguided corrections which he was led<br />

to make in his views about space <strong>and</strong> time <strong>and</strong> contents, <strong>and</strong>, what I especially regret, in<br />

his views about God, would have been avoided had he not revised his terminology in such<br />

an arbitrary <strong>and</strong> misleading way—<strong>and</strong> in a way which does not correspond at all with our<br />

thinking. <strong>The</strong> drive <strong>and</strong> zeal with which Marty tirelessly pursued his investigations will<br />

continue to make us marvel; <strong>and</strong> so it is all <strong>the</strong> more to be regretted that <strong>the</strong> road leading<br />

to <strong>the</strong> goal has been missed entirely, with <strong>the</strong> result that each step leads far<strong>the</strong>r away from<br />

<strong>the</strong> truth instead of closer to it. 42<br />

VIII<br />

To Oskar Kraus<br />

16 November, 1914<br />

I am pleased to note, in connection with my argument appealing to <strong>the</strong> unity of <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

of thought, that Marty attempted to answer it by taking <strong>the</strong> concept of “something” to be<br />

<strong>the</strong> concept of “that which is thinkable” ra<strong>the</strong>r than “that which is thought”. But I would<br />

ask you to consider carefully <strong>and</strong> without prejudice whe<strong>the</strong>r this distinction really bears<br />

upon our question. Could it be that, after appropriate modifications, my argument will<br />

remain just as cogent as before? If it is necessary to concede that our thinking does not<br />

have “that which is thought” as its object, <strong>the</strong>n it is equally clear that our thinking does not<br />

have “that which is thinkable” as its object. Who would want to take “being thinkable” as<br />

a generic characteristic, common to stone, horse, forest? My comparison with denying or<br />

rejecting something may be made to apply equally well here. For if <strong>the</strong> a<strong>the</strong>ist cannot be<br />

said to deny God as something denied, <strong>the</strong>n he cannot be said to deny God as something<br />

capable of being denied; in each case he would be contradicting what is intuitively obvious

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!