10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Contents of Judgement, Propositions, Objectives, States of Affairs 57<br />

<strong>the</strong> ens rationis, i.e. it becomes a fiction cum fundamento in re, a fiction which, although<br />

erroneous, is so firmly related to truth that it may be of help in leading us to <strong>the</strong> truth.<br />

<strong>The</strong> difference between our views is considerable. Let us see what seem to be clear <strong>and</strong><br />

decisive considerations in favour of mine.<br />

1. It is impossible to have an idea without having an idea of something. <strong>The</strong> term<br />

“something” here signifies what is a thing. If <strong>the</strong> thinking is a compound thought, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

things are what one has compounded. 14<br />

It is because of this fact that <strong>the</strong> concept of an idea—of having something before <strong>the</strong><br />

mind—is a simple, unequivocal concept.<br />

Every observation confirms <strong>the</strong> point. No one can be said to think of <strong>the</strong> being of a tree,<br />

of <strong>the</strong> non-being of a tree, or of <strong>the</strong> impossibility of a round square, in <strong>the</strong> way in which<br />

one can be said to think of a tree. A careful psychological analysis shows that <strong>the</strong> former<br />

cases involve not only ideas but judgements. Suppose, for example, I reject a apodictically<br />

<strong>and</strong> that I think of a as identical with b (merely thinking, but not judging, I predicate a of<br />

b). In such a case, language may mislead one into supposing that <strong>the</strong> impossibility of that b<br />

is here <strong>the</strong> object of our thought. 15<br />

To say that, in <strong>the</strong> strict sense of <strong>the</strong> term “thinking”, one may think of an impossibility,<br />

or <strong>the</strong> like, is just as much of a mistake as to say that an impossibility may be <strong>the</strong> object of<br />

a correct affirmative judgement, or that <strong>the</strong>re is such an impossibility.<br />

2. Confirmation of what I have said may be found in this fact: even you must admit that<br />

every assertion affirming your entia rationis has its equivalent in an assertion having only<br />

realia as objects. Thus “<strong>The</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> impossibility of a” is equivalent to <strong>the</strong> judgement “a is<br />

impossible”, which rejects a apodictically. What I have shown, with respect to <strong>the</strong> temporal<br />

modes of thinking, indicates that <strong>the</strong> temporal entia rationis are also no exception. 16<br />

Not only are judgements about things equivalent to your judgements about entia rationis;<br />

wherever <strong>the</strong>re is an instance of <strong>the</strong> latter <strong>the</strong>re is also an instance of <strong>the</strong> former. Hence <strong>the</strong><br />

entia rationis are entirely superfluous <strong>and</strong> not in accord with <strong>the</strong> economy of nature. 17<br />

But all this fits in neatly with my conception of entia linguae—that <strong>the</strong>y are fictions<br />

resulting from an improper underst<strong>and</strong>ing of <strong>the</strong> multiplicity of linguistic forms which we<br />

happen to have.<br />

3. Perhaps you will say: <strong>The</strong> entia rationis corresponding to <strong>the</strong> contents of correct<br />

judgements do have <strong>the</strong>ir use. For <strong>the</strong>y render <strong>the</strong> important service of distinguishing<br />

judgements which are correct from judgements which are incorrect. And <strong>the</strong> correctness<br />

of a judgement (you may continue) consists in <strong>the</strong> agreement of <strong>the</strong> judgement with such<br />

entities <strong>and</strong> not with any thing: a correct affirmative judgement will agree with <strong>the</strong> real<br />

being of <strong>the</strong> thing <strong>and</strong> a correct negative judgement with <strong>the</strong> real non-being of <strong>the</strong> thing.<br />

I reply: <strong>the</strong> distinction between correct <strong>and</strong> incorrect judgements, so far as I can see,<br />

does not provide us with <strong>the</strong> slightest justification for conjuring up <strong>the</strong>se entia rationis.<br />

Where some might say, “In case <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> being of A, <strong>and</strong> someone says that A is, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

he is judging correctly”, I would say, “In case A is <strong>and</strong> someone says that A is, he judges<br />

correctly”. Similarly instead of “If <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> non-being of A <strong>and</strong> someone rejects A, he<br />

judges correctly”, I would say “If A is not <strong>and</strong> someone rejects A, he judges correctly”, <strong>and</strong><br />

so on. 18

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!