10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

III<br />

LANGUAGE<br />

(Fragment of 16 November, 1905)<br />

1. Whoever asserts anything gives expression to what he thinks. Language is thus primarily<br />

a sign of thoughts, but indirectly a sign of events outside us.<br />

2. This does not mean, however, that for each sound <strong>the</strong>re is a corresponding thought or<br />

for each thought a corresponding sound. Individual sounds, <strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong> combinations of<br />

sounds which make up words, often have no meaning by <strong>the</strong>mselves; <strong>and</strong> often <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

signs of a multiplicity of thoughts. 19<br />

Thus individual syllables, particles, casus obliqui, have no meaning by <strong>the</strong>mselves.<br />

But <strong>the</strong> same cannot be said of statements or of names (substantives, adjectives).<br />

<strong>The</strong>se latter denote objects by means of concepts. <strong>The</strong>y signify that <strong>the</strong> concepts are<br />

being thought <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y evoke <strong>the</strong> same concepts in <strong>the</strong> one who is listening.<br />

3. But it may well happen that a word which has <strong>the</strong> grammatical form of a noun or adjective<br />

actually denotes nothing at all <strong>and</strong> is <strong>the</strong>refore not a name in <strong>the</strong> logical sense.<br />

For example: <strong>the</strong> abstracta (“colour” <strong>and</strong> “thinking”), also <strong>the</strong> negativa <strong>and</strong> modalia<br />

(such as “<strong>the</strong> necessary” <strong>and</strong> “<strong>the</strong> impossible”);<br />

Again, <strong>the</strong> objectiva (“an object of thought”, “an object of love”).<br />

Again, “good” <strong>and</strong> “evil”, as well as “truth” <strong>and</strong> “falsehood” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like. Strictly<br />

speaking, <strong>the</strong>re is no concept of <strong>the</strong> good, or of <strong>the</strong> beautiful, or of <strong>the</strong> true. 20<br />

4. Nor is <strong>the</strong>re a concept of a thing’s being. One erroneously assumes that <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>and</strong><br />

defines it thus: “A being is that which is”. But what one is thinking when one says “A is a<br />

being” is an acknowledgement or acceptance of A. And when one says “A is not a being”,<br />

one is thinking of a denial or rejection of A. If one were to say simply “a being” one would<br />

be thinking of a person who is accepting or acknowledging something. But this thought is<br />

not itself <strong>the</strong> concept of being, for if it were, <strong>the</strong> word “being” would have to denote one<br />

who asserts or acknowledges something.<br />

5. But <strong>the</strong>re is a concept of thing, even if <strong>the</strong>re is no concept of <strong>the</strong> being of a thing, or of a<br />

thing’s having being. And <strong>the</strong> concept of thing applies to everything.<br />

For everything is a thing or entity—a Usie.<br />

6. Here we have <strong>the</strong> most general concept. But only individual things correspond to it.<br />

Everything that does correspond to it must be subject to still o<strong>the</strong>r determinations fixing<br />

<strong>the</strong> concept of <strong>the</strong> thing more precisely.<br />

7. If <strong>the</strong>se more precise determinations specify <strong>and</strong> individuate <strong>the</strong> concept of <strong>the</strong> thing,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y are called “essential”. 21

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!