10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

On <strong>the</strong> <strong>Evident</strong> 39<br />

<strong>the</strong>n he is mistaken. Given that on <strong>the</strong> basis of certain data one thinker is compelled to<br />

make a certain judgement, why should it be that every thinker on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong> same<br />

data would have a similar compulsion? One may be tempted, in this connection, to appeal<br />

to <strong>the</strong> general causal law according to which, if all <strong>the</strong> relevant conditions are <strong>the</strong> same,<br />

<strong>the</strong> effects will also be <strong>the</strong> same. But this general law is not applicable in <strong>the</strong> present case.<br />

For <strong>the</strong> relevant causal conditions will include all those psychical dispositions which may<br />

not enter directly into consciousness at all but which will exercise <strong>the</strong>ir effects upon one’s<br />

judging; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>se dispositions are different for different people.<br />

Misled by paralogisms, Hegel <strong>and</strong> his school have even denied <strong>the</strong> law of contradiction;<br />

<strong>and</strong> Trendelenburg, who opposes Hegel, has at least restricted its validity (see his<br />

Abh<strong>and</strong>lungen über Herbarts Metaphysik). Hence we can no longer say, as Aristotle did,<br />

that it is impossible for anyone inwardly to deny <strong>the</strong> principle. But for Aristotle himself, to<br />

whom <strong>the</strong> principle was clearly evident, its denial was certainly impossible.<br />

But it is true that anything that is seen to be evident by one person is certain, not only for<br />

him, but also for anyone else who sees it in a similar way. Moreover, any judgement which<br />

is thus seen by one person to be true is universally valid; its contradictory cannot be seen<br />

to be evident by any o<strong>the</strong>r person; <strong>and</strong> anyone who accepts its contradictory is ipso facto<br />

mistaken. What I am here saying pertains to <strong>the</strong> nature of truth: anyone who thus sees into<br />

something as true is also able to see that he is justified in regarding it as true for all. 58 But<br />

it would be a gross confusion to suppose that this awareness of something being true for<br />

everyone implies an awareness of a universal compulsion to believe.<br />

(3) Sigwart entangles himself in a multiplicity of contradictions. He says—as he must<br />

if he is not to give in to scepticism or to ab<strong>and</strong>on his entire logic—that judgements which<br />

are evident may be distinguished from judgements which are not, <strong>and</strong> that we can make <strong>the</strong><br />

distinction in our own consciousness. Thus <strong>the</strong> one class of judgements, but not <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

must appear as normative <strong>and</strong> universal. But he also says that both classes of judgements—<br />

those which are evident <strong>and</strong> those which are not—are made with a consciousness of universal<br />

validity. <strong>The</strong> two types of judgement, <strong>the</strong>refore, would seem to present <strong>the</strong>mselves in<br />

precisely <strong>the</strong> same way. If this were true, <strong>the</strong>n one could make out <strong>the</strong> distinction between<br />

<strong>the</strong> two types of judgement only by means of reflection—supplementary <strong>and</strong> possibly later<br />

than <strong>the</strong> judgement itself—in <strong>the</strong> course of which one would appeal to some criterion or<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r which would <strong>the</strong>n be a kind of measuring rod. <strong>The</strong>re are actually passages in which<br />

Sigwart says that <strong>the</strong>re is an awareness of agreement with universal rules <strong>and</strong> that this<br />

awareness accompanies every perfectly evident judgement (op. cit., 2nd edn., Section 39,<br />

p. 311). But this is hardly in agreement with our experience—it was possible to reason<br />

syllogistically with perfect evidence long before <strong>the</strong> discovery of <strong>the</strong> rules of <strong>the</strong> syllogism.<br />

And in any case, we cannot be content with what Sigwart is here saying, for <strong>the</strong> rule to<br />

which he appeals is itself something that must be assured. Given Sigwart’s view, such<br />

assurance would require ei<strong>the</strong>r an infinite regress or a vicious circle.<br />

(4) Sigwart is involved in still ano<strong>the</strong>r contradiction (but one which, it seems to me,<br />

he could have avoided even after arriving at his erroneous conceptions of <strong>the</strong> nature of<br />

judgement <strong>and</strong> of evidence); this concerns his view of self-awareness. What is expressed by<br />

“I exist” is said to be just evident <strong>and</strong> not to be accompanied by any feeling of compulsion or<br />

of universal necessity. (At any rate, this is <strong>the</strong> only way I am able to interpret <strong>the</strong> following<br />

passage from his Logik, 2nd edn., Vol. I, p. 310: “<strong>The</strong> certainty that I exist <strong>and</strong> that I think

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!