10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

28<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>True</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Evident</strong><br />

logicians, fails to follow <strong>the</strong> lead of Aristotle on this point. He does not say that <strong>the</strong> existent<br />

comprises everything of which <strong>the</strong> affirmative judgement is true. Instead of this, he goes<br />

into a lengthy discussion of <strong>the</strong> concept of being <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> existential proposition. But<br />

Sigwart is on <strong>the</strong> wrong track altoge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> his views on <strong>the</strong>se questions—which he sets<br />

forth again in <strong>the</strong> second edition of his Logik (pp. 88–95)—do not throw light on anything<br />

at all.<br />

“To be”, according to Sigwart, expresses a relation (pp. 88, 95). What kind of a relation?<br />

At first consideration (see p. 92), one might suppose it to be a “relation to me as one who is<br />

thinking”. But this will not do, for <strong>the</strong> existential proposition is said to assert precisely <strong>the</strong><br />

fact that “that which has being exists apart from its relation to me or to any o<strong>the</strong>r thinking<br />

being”. But if <strong>the</strong> relation in question is not “a relation to me as one who is thinking”, what<br />

could it be? We do not find out until page 94. Here we are told that <strong>the</strong> relation is (to be sure,<br />

Sigwart adds: “in <strong>the</strong> first place”) an “agreement of <strong>the</strong> thing thought about with a possible<br />

perception”; he also says it is an “identity” of <strong>the</strong> thing thought about with something<br />

“perceivable”, or with “something which can be perceived by me” (pp. 94, 90n.).<br />

We can see at once that his concept of existence is too narrow. For much of what<br />

exists cannot be perceived; for example, a past <strong>and</strong> a future, an empty space, any kind of<br />

deprivation, a possibility, an impossibility, <strong>and</strong> so on. 43 It is not surprising, <strong>the</strong>refore, that<br />

Sigwart himself makes an effort to widen his concept. But what he does is very difficult<br />

for me to underst<strong>and</strong>. First, he seems to say that, in order for a thing to be counted as<br />

existing, <strong>the</strong> thing need not be capable of being perceived by me; it is necessary only that<br />

it be capable of being perceived by someone or o<strong>the</strong>r. At least this seems to be what he<br />

means when, after saying that existence is an agreement between <strong>the</strong> thing thought about<br />

<strong>and</strong> a possible perception, he goes on to say: “That which exists bears this relation not<br />

only to me but also to everything else that has being.” Surely Sigwart does not mean to say<br />

that everything that <strong>the</strong>re is has <strong>the</strong> capability of perceiving everything. Perhaps he means<br />

only that everything that exists st<strong>and</strong>s in <strong>the</strong> relation of existence to every o<strong>the</strong>r being, in<br />

which case his empty-sounding phrase might be taken to say that existence expresses <strong>the</strong><br />

judgement with that which is judged negatively. So, too, <strong>the</strong> correctness of <strong>the</strong> affirmative<br />

judgement is correlated with <strong>the</strong> existence of that which is affirmatively judged, <strong>and</strong> that of <strong>the</strong><br />

negative judgement with <strong>the</strong> non-existence of that which is negatively judged. One may say that<br />

an affirmative judgement is true, or one may say that its object is existent; in both cases one would<br />

be saying precisely <strong>the</strong> same thing. Similarly for saying that a negative judgement is true, <strong>and</strong><br />

saying that its object is non-existent. We may say that, for every (simple) affirmative judgement,<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r it or <strong>the</strong> corresponding negative judgement is true; <strong>and</strong> we may express precisely <strong>the</strong> same<br />

logical principle by saying that, for every such affirmative judgement, ei<strong>the</strong>r its object is existent<br />

or its object is non-existent.<br />

<strong>The</strong> assertion of <strong>the</strong> truth of <strong>the</strong> judgement, that <strong>the</strong>re is a learned man, is thus correlative to<br />

<strong>the</strong> assertion of <strong>the</strong> existence of its object, viz., a learned man. <strong>The</strong> assertion of <strong>the</strong> truth of <strong>the</strong><br />

judgement, that no stone is alive, is similarly correlative to <strong>the</strong> assertion of <strong>the</strong> non-existence of<br />

its object, viz., a living stone. Correlative assertions, here as elsewhere, are inseparable. Compare<br />

such correlatives as “A is greater than B” <strong>and</strong> “B is less than A”, or “A produces B” <strong>and</strong> “B is<br />

produced by A”.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!