10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

14<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>True</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Evident</strong><br />

be given an interpretation quite different from <strong>the</strong> one offered by those who think <strong>the</strong>re is a<br />

relation of identity, or of sameness, or of similarity, between a true thought <strong>and</strong> a thing.<br />

47. Of <strong>the</strong>se last two possibilities, <strong>the</strong> second is <strong>the</strong> one which is correct. 14 And now it<br />

should be easy for us to give <strong>the</strong> proper sense of that formula which has been so long<br />

unclear.<br />

To do this we must pay proper attention both to <strong>the</strong> limits of <strong>the</strong> area to which judging<br />

is applicable, <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> contrast between those judgements which affirm <strong>and</strong> those which<br />

deny.<br />

48. <strong>The</strong> area to which our judgements may be applied is unlimited, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> content of<br />

judgement may be as we like. But our judgement always pertains to some entity or o<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

And what does “entity” signify? It is a term that can be applied to God or to <strong>the</strong> world, to<br />

anything whatever, <strong>and</strong> to any non-thing. 15<br />

49. Now this limitless area can be divided into two parts. <strong>The</strong> opposition between <strong>the</strong><br />

affirmative <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> negative judgement implies, as we know, that in any given case one, <strong>and</strong><br />

only one, of <strong>the</strong> two modes of judging is appropriate <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r is inappropriate. 16<br />

This fact is ordinarily expressed by saying that, of two contradictory judgements, one <strong>and</strong><br />

only one is true <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r false.<br />

50. Let us say that <strong>the</strong> area to which affirmative judgement is appropriate is <strong>the</strong> area of <strong>the</strong><br />

existent, a concept to be sharply distinguished from that of thing; <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> area to which<br />

<strong>the</strong> negative judgement is appropriate is <strong>the</strong> area of <strong>the</strong> non-existent.<br />

51. Following Aristotle’s statement that a judgement is true if it takes as combined what<br />

is combined, <strong>and</strong> so on, we can say: a judgement is true if it asserts of some object that<br />

is, that <strong>the</strong> object is, or if it asserts of some object that is not, that <strong>the</strong> object is not—<strong>and</strong> a<br />

judgement is false if it contradicts that which is, or that which is not. 17<br />

we have heard so much. To correspond does not mean to be <strong>the</strong> same or to be similar;<br />

but it does mean to be adequate, to fit, to be in agreement with, to be in harmony with, or<br />

whatever equivalent expressions one may choose to apply. 18<br />

52. And this is all <strong>the</strong>re is to <strong>the</strong> correspondence of true judgement <strong>and</strong> object about which<br />

53. We may make this concept clearer by drawing ano<strong>the</strong>r obvious parallel. In <strong>the</strong> area of<br />

emotion we also find an opposition—that between loving <strong>and</strong> hating. Of everything that<br />

may be considered, one of <strong>the</strong>se two attitudes may be said to be appropriate <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

inappropriate. Accordingly, everything that can be thought about belongs in one of two<br />

classes—ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> class of things for which love is appropriate, or <strong>the</strong> class of things for<br />

which hate is appropriate. Whatever falls into <strong>the</strong> first class we call good, <strong>and</strong> whatever<br />

falls into <strong>the</strong> second we call bad. Thus we can say that love <strong>and</strong> hate are correct if we love<br />

what is good <strong>and</strong> if we hate what is bad, <strong>and</strong> that love <strong>and</strong> hate are not correct if we love<br />

what is bad <strong>and</strong> hate what is good. We can also say that in those cases where our attitude is<br />

correct <strong>the</strong> emotion corresponds with <strong>the</strong> object, that it is in harmony with <strong>the</strong> value of <strong>the</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!