10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

10<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>True</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Evident</strong><br />

of certain features, obtains between, say, Peter <strong>and</strong> Paul. If <strong>the</strong> judgement asserting Peter’s<br />

existence corresponded no more closely to Peter than Peter corresponds to Paul, <strong>the</strong>n it<br />

would not be true, or at least it would not be a truth about Peter. But if <strong>the</strong> judgement<br />

completely corresponded to Peter, it would be identical with him <strong>and</strong> would be Peter<br />

himself. Yet Peter is outside my mind, not in it. Thus Professor Dil<strong>the</strong>y of Berlin uses this<br />

position to argue against <strong>the</strong> possibility of our knowledge of <strong>the</strong> external world as it really<br />

is. In his Einleitung in die Geisteswissenschaften* he justifies this <strong>the</strong>sis in <strong>the</strong> following<br />

words: “For an idea or presentation [Dil<strong>the</strong>y conceives judgement as a connection of<br />

ideas] can never be identical with a thing, inasmuch as <strong>the</strong> thing is conceived as a reality<br />

independent of <strong>the</strong> idea. <strong>The</strong> idea is not <strong>the</strong> thing brought inside <strong>the</strong> mind, <strong>and</strong> it cannot<br />

be made to coincide with an object. If one weakens <strong>the</strong> concept of sameness to that of<br />

similarity, <strong>the</strong>n this concept too, in its precise meaning, cannot be employed: thus <strong>the</strong> idea<br />

of correspondence vanishes into <strong>the</strong> indefinite.”<br />

But, surprisingly enough, Dil<strong>the</strong>y does not deny <strong>the</strong> possibility of our knowing <strong>the</strong><br />

intentions <strong>and</strong> convictions of o<strong>the</strong>rs, as <strong>the</strong>se are in <strong>the</strong>mselves. A critic has shrewdly<br />

remarked that, in order to remain consistent, Dil<strong>the</strong>y would have to maintain <strong>the</strong><br />

impossibility of <strong>the</strong> knowledge of someone else’s error. 4 “In order to recognize <strong>the</strong> error of<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r person, this error would have to be put into my mind. But this is impossible. And<br />

even if it were possible, we could hardly notice <strong>the</strong> error, since we would have participated<br />

in it ourselves.” If this reasoning were correct, it would be better to reject altoge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

definition of truth in terms of <strong>the</strong> correspondence of thought <strong>and</strong> its object. As a matter of<br />

fact, if Sigwart in his Logic seems prepared to reject <strong>the</strong> definition, he is compelled by a<br />

consideration of this sort—one which seems to have influenced Windelb<strong>and</strong> himself.<br />

29. But <strong>the</strong> argument is completely fallacious. It stems from a failure to recognize <strong>the</strong><br />

distinction, which Descartes had described as <strong>the</strong> distinction between formal <strong>and</strong> objective<br />

reality, but which had been brought fully to light long before by Aristotle, who used it<br />

in overcoming <strong>the</strong> absurdities <strong>and</strong> sophistries of Parmenides, Gorgias, Protagoras, <strong>and</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs.<br />

If I believe something, <strong>the</strong>n this belief is “formally” in me. When I later recall <strong>the</strong> belief,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n, according to Descartes’ way of speaking, <strong>the</strong> value is “objectively” in me. In each<br />

case <strong>the</strong> same particular act of belief is involved; but in <strong>the</strong> one case it is my act itself <strong>and</strong><br />

in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r it is only <strong>the</strong> immanent object of my remembering. Similarly for every o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

mental function—volition, desire, aversion, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like. Every mental act, in itself given<br />

formally, has its immanent object which, in Descartes’ terms, is given objectively. To avoid<br />

misunderst<strong>and</strong>ings, we might express this better by saying that <strong>the</strong> immanent object is<br />

given intentionally. It is obvious that no contradiction is involved in saying that something<br />

is in me intentionally but not formally, or vice versa, a fact that can be illustrated by <strong>the</strong><br />

example of remembering, <strong>and</strong> by thous<strong>and</strong>s of o<strong>the</strong>rs. A mistake on this point would be a<br />

relapse into <strong>the</strong> crudest stages of <strong>the</strong> development of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of knowledge.<br />

* Dil<strong>the</strong>y’s Gesammelte Schriften, Leipzig 1922, Vol. I, p. 318.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!