10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Introduction xxiii<br />

one who judges with evidence does not constitute <strong>the</strong> meaning of <strong>the</strong>se words. <strong>The</strong> point<br />

is, ra<strong>the</strong>r, that <strong>the</strong> locutions in which <strong>the</strong>se words are used cannot be understood without<br />

thinking of one who judges with evidence.<br />

What do we mean when we speak of “one who is judging truly”? <strong>The</strong> concept of<br />

“justified in itself”—or, what comes to <strong>the</strong> same thing, “completely correct”, “perfectly<br />

right”, “judgement of insight”, “insightful judgement”, or “knowing judgement”—is drawn<br />

immediately from intuition. In analogy with what is generally true of <strong>the</strong> acquisition of<br />

concepts, <strong>the</strong> distinguishing mark of such judgements st<strong>and</strong>s out when <strong>the</strong>y are contrasted<br />

with judgements which lack this mark. No psychologistic investigation of <strong>the</strong> natural<br />

causes of judgement <strong>and</strong> no “transcendental” investigation of <strong>the</strong> logical presuppositions<br />

of judgement can reveal to us <strong>the</strong> nature of knowledge. <strong>The</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of knowledge must be<br />

based upon <strong>the</strong> concept of <strong>the</strong> evident judgement.<br />

But it is essential to recognize this distinction: although all insightful judgements are<br />

true, not all true judgements are evident. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, no two judgements having <strong>the</strong><br />

same object can contradict each o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> same time be such that both of <strong>the</strong>m are<br />

evident. 5 Here we have an ultimate insight—one that is axiomatic, a priori, <strong>and</strong> apodictic.<br />

No evident judgement can contradict ano<strong>the</strong>r evident judgement; hence <strong>the</strong> general validity<br />

of out knowledge is secured, absolutely <strong>and</strong> a priori.<br />

But we say that <strong>the</strong>re are “true” judgements which are not evident. For <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

judgements which resemble those that are evident in <strong>the</strong> following respects: <strong>the</strong>y can never<br />

be brought into contradiction with an insight; we may accept what follows from <strong>the</strong>m; <strong>and</strong><br />

so <strong>the</strong>y have <strong>the</strong> same practical value as do judgements which are evident. We may thus<br />

consider <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>se judgements cannot contradict what is evident <strong>and</strong> look upon it<br />

fictitiously as though it constituted a characteristic of <strong>the</strong> judgements <strong>the</strong>mselves. We may<br />

<strong>the</strong>n construct a term—a denominatio extrinseca—which applies not only to insightful<br />

judgements but also to those blind judgements which cannot be brought into contradiction<br />

with any insightful judgement. Both types of judgement, nei<strong>the</strong>r of which can contradict<br />

what is evident, may be said to be true. And from this it follows that, although all insightful<br />

judgements are true, not all true judgements are evident.<br />

We can now see why it is that <strong>the</strong> truth of a judgement is generally taught to be a matter<br />

of logic <strong>and</strong> not a matter of psychology. For <strong>the</strong> grammatical predicate “true” does not<br />

indicate any real property of <strong>the</strong> judgement; hence it does not indicate any psychological<br />

property, such as that of being evident. <strong>The</strong>re is no act of judgement which refers directly<br />

to any so-called true judgement. 6<br />

One may see <strong>the</strong> justification of what we have said if one notes that a judgement, without<br />

itself being altered in <strong>the</strong> slightest, may change from true to false. Thus I may judge “it is<br />

raining” <strong>and</strong> continue so to judge after <strong>the</strong> rain has ceased. But if in saying, “<strong>The</strong> judgement<br />

A is true”, we are not in fact predicating anything of <strong>the</strong> judgement A, what is it that we<br />

are saying? We are rejecting <strong>the</strong> possibility of <strong>the</strong>re being an evident judgement which has<br />

<strong>the</strong> same object as <strong>the</strong> judgement called “true” but which does not have <strong>the</strong> same quality<br />

as <strong>the</strong> judgement called “true”. 7 We are apodictically denying or rejecting any judging<br />

consciousness which is judging with evidence but which is not making a judgement of <strong>the</strong><br />

same quality as <strong>the</strong> one that we are calling “true”.*<br />

* See <strong>the</strong> references under “richtig” in Vol. 2 of <strong>Brentano</strong>’s Psychologie.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!