10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Introduction xxi<br />

<strong>the</strong> developments <strong>and</strong> deviations of so-called “phenomenology”. To call <strong>Brentano</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

of knowledge “psychologism”, on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong>se remarks of Husserl, is fantastic <strong>and</strong><br />

contrary to all historic truth.<br />

Let us compare certain passages from <strong>the</strong> first edition of <strong>Brentano</strong>’s Vom Ursprung<br />

sittlicher Erkenntnis (1889) with certain characteristic statements from <strong>the</strong> second edition<br />

of Husserl’s Logische Untersuchungen.<br />

<strong>Brentano</strong> (pp. 80–81): “Any judgement which is seen by one person to be true is<br />

universally valid; its contradictory cannot be seen to be evident by any o<strong>the</strong>r person; <strong>and</strong><br />

anyone who accepts its contradictory is ipso facto mistaken. What I am here saying pertains<br />

to <strong>the</strong> nature of truth: anyone who thus sees into something as true is also able to see that he<br />

is justified in regarding it as a truth for all.”<br />

Husserl (Vol. I, p. 191): “And accordingly we have <strong>the</strong> insight that if we have a genuine<br />

insight, <strong>the</strong>n no one else can have a genuine insight which conflicts with it.”<br />

<strong>Brentano</strong> (p. 79): “<strong>The</strong> peculiar nature of insight—<strong>the</strong> clarity <strong>and</strong> evidence of certain<br />

judgements—which is inseparable from <strong>the</strong>ir truth—has little or nothing to do with a<br />

feeling of compulsion…. We can underst<strong>and</strong> what distinguishes it from o<strong>the</strong>r judgements<br />

only if we look for it in <strong>the</strong> inner peculiarity of <strong>the</strong> act of insight itself.”<br />

Husserl (Vol. I, p. 189): “Evidence is not a concomitant feeling which, accidentally or<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rwise, connects itself with certain judgements. It is not at all a psychical characteristic<br />

which simply happens to be attached to a given judgement of some particular class (such<br />

as <strong>the</strong> class of so-called ‘true judgements’).”<br />

<strong>Brentano</strong> (paragraph 11): “<strong>The</strong> precepts of logic are naturally valid rules of judging; that<br />

is to say, we must adhere to <strong>the</strong>m, since <strong>the</strong> judgement which accords with <strong>the</strong>m is certain<br />

<strong>and</strong> that which does not is exposed to error. Thus we are concerned here with <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

thought processes which conform to rules are naturally superior to those which do not.”<br />

Husserl (Vol. I, p. 157): “<strong>The</strong> general conviction that <strong>the</strong> propositions of logic are norms<br />

of thinking cannot be entirely unfounded; <strong>the</strong> self-evidence with which it enlightens cannot<br />

be pure deception. Thought which is in accordance with rules has a certain inner superiority<br />

which distinguishes <strong>the</strong>se propositions from o<strong>the</strong>rs.”<br />

It is also noteworthy that, in <strong>the</strong> polemic against psychologism in Volume 1 of <strong>the</strong><br />

Logische Untersuchungen, Husserl does not attack <strong>Brentano</strong> himself. Nor does he cite<br />

<strong>Brentano</strong> as <strong>the</strong> source of his critique.<br />

11. This comparison of passages is relevant to <strong>the</strong> first two of <strong>the</strong> psychologistic <strong>the</strong>ses<br />

referred to above. <strong>Brentano</strong>’s views on <strong>the</strong>se points are made abundantly clear in <strong>the</strong><br />

selections that follow. As for <strong>the</strong> third <strong>the</strong>sis, which Husserl opposes by appeal to <strong>the</strong><br />

so-called correspondence <strong>the</strong>ory, Husserl’s argument is taken directly from <strong>the</strong> writings<br />

<strong>and</strong> lectures of <strong>Brentano</strong>, who had extended <strong>and</strong> modified <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian tradition. This<br />

is also true of <strong>the</strong> fourth point: <strong>Brentano</strong> had made <strong>the</strong> assumption of irrealia—of states<br />

of affairs (existences <strong>and</strong> non-existences)—in <strong>the</strong> first of <strong>the</strong> selections published here <strong>and</strong><br />

modified <strong>the</strong> principle of adaequatio rei et intellectus by saying that our judgements must<br />

be adequate to <strong>the</strong>se irrealia. At <strong>the</strong> time of <strong>the</strong> lecture, he thus taught that <strong>the</strong>re are certain<br />

entities that are not things; his pupils were later to introduce new technical terms. Where<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs spoke of “states of affairs” or “truths”, Meinong, for example, spoke of “objectives”.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!