10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Notes 109<br />

48 This critique constitutes a definite rejection of <strong>the</strong> correspondence, or “adaequatio”, <strong>the</strong>ory;<br />

<strong>Brentano</strong> now seems to be preparing <strong>the</strong> way for <strong>the</strong> transition from <strong>the</strong> lecture on truth to his later<br />

views. In any case, he here anticipates a criticism of Marty’s later version of <strong>the</strong> correspondence<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory. This passage is also of interest in connection with Leonard Nelson’s “Unmöglichkeit der<br />

Erkenntnis<strong>the</strong>orie”, in Abh<strong>and</strong>lungen der Fries’schen Schule, Vol. III (Göttingen, 1911).<br />

49 Now reprinted in Marty’s Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. II, Part I.<br />

50 <strong>Brentano</strong> here refers to <strong>the</strong> views which he defended in <strong>the</strong> main text of Vom Ursprung sittlicher<br />

Erkenntnis.<br />

51 Instead of saying “<strong>the</strong> fact that a given negative judgement is justified…”, it would have been<br />

better to have said, “<strong>the</strong> fact that a given negative judgement would be justified if it were made…”<br />

52 One might doubt whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se comparative judgements are real predications, in which case ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

example would have been preferable. But this is of minor significance in relation to <strong>the</strong> question at issue.<br />

53 Sigwart contends that if we think of <strong>the</strong> negative judgement as a species co-ordinate with<br />

<strong>the</strong> affirmative judgement, we are committed to this consequence: since <strong>the</strong> affirmation of a man<br />

is included in <strong>the</strong> proposition “Some man is sick”, <strong>the</strong> denial or rejection of a man should be<br />

included in “Some man is not sick”. But <strong>Brentano</strong> replies: in <strong>the</strong> affirmation (“in <strong>the</strong> existence”)<br />

of a sick man (which follows from <strong>the</strong> assertion that some man is sick) <strong>the</strong> affirmation of a<br />

man <strong>and</strong> of something sick is included. Hence to deny <strong>the</strong> whole it suffices ei<strong>the</strong>r to deny that<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is anything sick or to deny that <strong>the</strong>re is a man. For if <strong>the</strong>re is nothing sick, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

no sick man. <strong>The</strong>refore <strong>the</strong> subject of “Some man is sick” need not be denied in order to deny<br />

<strong>the</strong> whole. <strong>The</strong> proposition “Some man is not sick” would be false if <strong>the</strong>re were no men, but if<br />

<strong>the</strong>re are men, <strong>the</strong>n “Some man is not sick” would be true provided <strong>the</strong>re is nothing that is sick.<br />

54 What we have here is an argumentatio ad hominem, not an explication of <strong>the</strong> terms “true” <strong>and</strong> “false”.<br />

55 In my opinion, <strong>Brentano</strong>’s criticism of Sigwart at this point is correct insofar as it is directed<br />

against <strong>the</strong> contention that every positive judgement must be accompanied by a negative judgement<br />

which is an “awareness of <strong>the</strong> impossibility of <strong>the</strong> opposite”. It is certain that such negative judgements<br />

do not always accompany positive judgements; consider in particular <strong>the</strong> positive judgements of<br />

inner <strong>and</strong> outer perception. But one may still ask whe<strong>the</strong>r our assertions of <strong>the</strong> form “A is”, “A is<br />

not”, A is B”, “A is not B”, do not in fact express certain convictions in addition to <strong>the</strong> judgements<br />

directed upon A <strong>and</strong> upon B. It would seem to be <strong>the</strong> case that <strong>the</strong>se linguistic formulations also<br />

contain <strong>the</strong> assertion of <strong>the</strong> correctness of <strong>the</strong> judgements about A <strong>and</strong> about B. Any such assertion<br />

of correctness, as <strong>Brentano</strong> shows here, is a negative judgement, which denies <strong>the</strong> possibility of<br />

<strong>the</strong> contradicting judgement being correct. What Sigwart thought to hold of judgements <strong>the</strong>mselves<br />

actually holds only of <strong>the</strong> linguistic expressions of judgements; <strong>the</strong>se linguistic formulations do bring<br />

several judgements to expression, of which one is necessarily negative. Thus if I say “<strong>The</strong>re is a<br />

God”, not only do I express my belief in God, but I also express my belief that it is correct to believe<br />

in God; in o<strong>the</strong>r words, I express my belief (as will be seen more clearly later) that a judgement<br />

contradicting my belief cannot possibly be correct. Analogously for <strong>the</strong> negative assertion “<strong>The</strong>re<br />

is no God”. In this case, <strong>the</strong> negative judgement that <strong>the</strong>re is no God is <strong>the</strong> primary judgement; <strong>the</strong><br />

secondary judgement is a second negative judgement to <strong>the</strong> effect that <strong>the</strong>re cannot possibly be a<br />

correct judgement contradicting <strong>the</strong> primary judgement. But from <strong>the</strong> fact that this second judgement<br />

in every case is apodictic, Sigwart is not entitled to infer that <strong>the</strong> first judgement is always apodictic.<br />

If I say, for example, “I am thinking”, my assertion expresses an assertoric judgement <strong>the</strong> correctness<br />

of which may also be affirmed in an apodictic judgement. For fur<strong>the</strong>r details, see George Katkov,<br />

“Bewusstsei n, Gegenst<strong>and</strong>, Sachverhalt’, in Archiv für Psychologie, Vol. 75 (1930). It may be that<br />

Felix Weltsch has something similar in mind in saying that every judgement contains <strong>the</strong> “intention<br />

of its own correctness”; in “Kann die Evidenz Sanktion der Ethik sein?”, Ruch Filosoficky, Vol. III.<br />

56 Compare <strong>the</strong> second edition of Vom Ursprung sittlicher Erkenntnis, Note 34, p. 59. <strong>Brentano</strong> here<br />

criticizes those modern philosophers who contend that every evident judgement depends upon <strong>the</strong><br />

application of some criterion. If this contention were true, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> criterion itself would first have to be

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!