10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Introduction xvii<br />

5. <strong>The</strong> basis of epistemology is <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of <strong>the</strong> evident—<strong>the</strong> insightful judgement, <strong>the</strong><br />

judgement which is justified in itself <strong>and</strong> which constitutes knowing. This is <strong>the</strong> topic of<br />

<strong>the</strong> final dictations in Part Four. I shall anticipate two of <strong>the</strong> more frequent objections <strong>and</strong><br />

misunderst<strong>and</strong>ings.<br />

It has been argued that, since one can be mistaken about what is evident, an epistemology<br />

or <strong>the</strong>ory of knowledge which is based upon <strong>the</strong> concept of <strong>the</strong> evident is impossible. But<br />

from <strong>the</strong> fact that we are capable of insightful judgements—judgements which are seen to<br />

be correct—it does not follow that every erroneous or incorrect judgement is seen to be<br />

erroneous or incorrect!<br />

It has also been noted that we sometimes fail to recognize insightful judgements as<br />

such <strong>and</strong> that we sometimes mistake erroneous judgements for those that are insightful.<br />

But this very argument presupposes that <strong>the</strong>re is a distinction between <strong>the</strong> two types of<br />

judgement <strong>and</strong> indeed that we are able to make <strong>the</strong> distinction. For if we did not know, with<br />

respect to some judgements, that <strong>the</strong>y are insightful, <strong>and</strong> with respect to o<strong>the</strong>rs, that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are erroneous, how could we know that <strong>the</strong> one type of judgement is sometimes mistaken<br />

for <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r? <strong>The</strong> fact that we are able to tell that some judgements are insightful <strong>and</strong> some<br />

are not assures us that we are able to guard against such mistakes, or to correct <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

<strong>Brentano</strong> has shown, repeatedly <strong>and</strong> in detail, that it is “an absurd undertaking to try to<br />

use reasoning to guarantee <strong>the</strong> evidence of what is self-evident”.* He has been reproached<br />

for “never having considered <strong>the</strong> problem of <strong>the</strong> logical presuppositions of his so-called<br />

a priori evident judgements”. If he is guilty of this charge, at least he may be said to have<br />

asked why anyone should suppose that <strong>the</strong>re is such a problem. Presumably <strong>the</strong>se mysterious<br />

“logical presuppositions” are <strong>the</strong>mselves known. What is <strong>the</strong> nature of this knowledge,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n? Does this knowledge also have “logical presuppositions”, or is it ultimate—that is to<br />

say, directly evident <strong>and</strong> justified in itself? Surely one is not blind to <strong>the</strong> fact that ei<strong>the</strong>r (i)<br />

we should give up all talk about knowledge, or (ii) we may reason in a vicious circle, or<br />

(iii) we must admit that <strong>the</strong>re is ultimate knowledge—i.e., that <strong>the</strong>re are judgements which<br />

are self-evident <strong>and</strong> justified in <strong>the</strong>mselves. If <strong>the</strong>re is anyone who doesn’t see this, <strong>the</strong>n, as<br />

Aristotle put it, we can only leave him behind.<br />

But our <strong>the</strong>ory of <strong>the</strong> evident is not to be held responsible for <strong>the</strong> transformation it<br />

has undergone in Husserl’s Ideen (with its “adequate” <strong>and</strong> “inadequate” evidence <strong>and</strong> its<br />

“perceptual explosion”); nor is it compatible with Meinong’s “evident surmises”.<br />

6. Kant’s “Copernican revolution” contains a faint suggestion of <strong>the</strong> truth, as I have<br />

indicated elsewhere.* But Kant did not overthrow <strong>the</strong> correspondence <strong>the</strong>ory. He shifted<br />

<strong>the</strong> system of coordinates from <strong>the</strong> object to <strong>the</strong> subject: our knowledge is not a function<br />

of <strong>the</strong> things; <strong>the</strong> things—to <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong>y are our phenomena—are a function of our<br />

knowledge. Using <strong>the</strong> terminology of practical reason, we could say that Kant transforms our<br />

knowledge from something heteronymous to something autonomous. But <strong>the</strong> correct point<br />

* <strong>Franz</strong> <strong>Brentano</strong>, Versuch über die Erkenntnis, edited by Alfred Kastil (Felix Meiner, Leipzig<br />

1925).<br />

* O.Kraus, “Die ‘kopernikanische Wendung’ in <strong>Brentano</strong>s Erkenntnis- und Wertlehre”,<br />

Philosophische Hefte, Vol. I, No. 3 (Berlin 1929).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!