10.04.2013 Views

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

Franz Brentano_The True and the Evident.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Notes 107<br />

has lifted <strong>the</strong> veil only enough for us to see some of <strong>the</strong> paradoxical consequences of this <strong>the</strong>ory.”<br />

Meanwhile, however, <strong>Brentano</strong>’s suggestions enabled Hillebr<strong>and</strong> to write <strong>the</strong> book on Die neuen<br />

<strong>The</strong>orien der kategorischen Schlüsse (Vienna 1891). J.P.N.L<strong>and</strong>, who was not at all close to <strong>Brentano</strong><br />

as a philosopher, understood <strong>the</strong> new <strong>the</strong>ory of judgement <strong>and</strong> inference much better than Windelb<strong>and</strong><br />

did. See J.P.N.L<strong>and</strong>, “<strong>Brentano</strong>’s Logical Investigations”, Mind, I (1876), pp. 284–292; compare also<br />

Anton Marty’s Gesammelte Schriften, Halle a. S. 1916–1920.<br />

<strong>Brentano</strong> discussed L<strong>and</strong>’s criticism in a letter dated 15 April, 1876, which is reproduced in large<br />

part in Vol. II of <strong>the</strong> Psychologie (p. 288). L<strong>and</strong> had said that all categorical statements—<strong>and</strong> hence<br />

those beginning with “all”—presuppose <strong>the</strong> existence of a subject. <strong>Brentano</strong> had originally held that<br />

A-statements have only one possible interpretation <strong>and</strong> that this is purely negative, as explained in <strong>the</strong><br />

previous note. He conceded to L<strong>and</strong>, however, that <strong>the</strong>re are also A-statements which may be interpreted<br />

as affirming <strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong>ir subjects, in which case such moods as Bamalip <strong>and</strong> Darapti<br />

remain valid. But L<strong>and</strong> was entirely mistaken if he intended to deny that <strong>the</strong>re are A-statements which<br />

serve only to express pure <strong>and</strong> often apodictic denials. Geometric statements in no way presuppose<br />

<strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong> structures or forms with which <strong>the</strong>y are concerned. For fur<strong>the</strong>r details see Vol. II<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Psychologie, p. 248 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> notes on pp. 284–6 of that work.<br />

L<strong>and</strong> had defended his view in this way: When we say “No stone is alive” or “All men are mortal”<br />

we presuppose <strong>the</strong> existence of stones or of men; in making <strong>the</strong>se statements we are not concerned<br />

with <strong>the</strong> possible properties of purely problematic men or stones (op. cit., p. 291). It is true, as indicated<br />

above, that in <strong>the</strong> natural sciences statements of this sort do include an affirmation. “All men<br />

are mortal” says (1) that <strong>the</strong>re are men <strong>and</strong> (2) that <strong>the</strong>re is nothing which is a man <strong>and</strong> not mortal.<br />

Similarly for those statements of geometry which are concerned with <strong>the</strong> three-dimensional space<br />

in which we live, but such statements—e.g., those that speak of ideal tetrahedrons—can be applied<br />

only approximately. But we are also acquainted with geometries which are concerned with manifolds<br />

having more than three dimensions, <strong>and</strong> we do not know, <strong>and</strong> cannot know, whe<strong>the</strong>r such manifolds<br />

are actual; <strong>the</strong> objects of non-Euclidean geometry, moreover, are entirely problematic.<br />

<strong>Brentano</strong> had added <strong>the</strong> following lines to <strong>the</strong> letter referred to above: “And what of statements<br />

which contradict each o<strong>the</strong>r—‘Some angels are damned by God’ <strong>and</strong> ‘No angel is damned by God’?<br />

According to all logic up to now, one of <strong>the</strong>se must be true. But if <strong>the</strong>re are no angels, <strong>the</strong>n, according<br />

to L<strong>and</strong>’s view, both would be false.”<br />

It should be noted that it is L<strong>and</strong>’s view <strong>and</strong> not <strong>Brentano</strong>’s which conflicts with <strong>the</strong> traditional<br />

doctrine that, of two contradictory statements, one must be true. According to L<strong>and</strong>’s view <strong>the</strong> statement<br />

“No angel is damned by God” would be false if <strong>the</strong>re were no angels, for on his interpretation<br />

<strong>the</strong> statement is equivalent to “<strong>The</strong>re are angels <strong>and</strong> none of <strong>the</strong>se is damned by God”.<br />

39 Except for <strong>the</strong> footnote on Miklosich, I have omitted <strong>the</strong> critique of Sigwart from <strong>the</strong> second<br />

edition of Vom Ursprung sittlicher Erkenntnis; for <strong>the</strong> critique has no direct relevance to <strong>the</strong> problems<br />

of value <strong>the</strong>ory with which <strong>the</strong> Ursprung is concerned <strong>and</strong>, as will be seen in what follows, <strong>Brentano</strong><br />

was later to give up some of <strong>the</strong> views which <strong>the</strong> note expresses. <strong>The</strong> note is not without value,<br />

however, for it contains a telling criticism of Sigwart’s doctrine <strong>and</strong> it is essential for underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

those earlier views of <strong>Brentano</strong> which still survive in <strong>the</strong> writings of most of his followers.<br />

40 Now republished in Anton Marty, Gesammelte Schriften (Halle 1918), edited by J.Eisenmeier,<br />

A.Kastil, <strong>and</strong> O.Kraus, Vol. II, Part I.<br />

41 <strong>Brentano</strong>’s remarks are taken from note 25 of <strong>the</strong> first edition of Vom Ursprung sittlicher<br />

Erkenntnis; this part of <strong>the</strong> note does not appear in <strong>the</strong> second edition, for reasons that are explained<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Introduction to that edition. What is said in <strong>the</strong> note is not relevant to <strong>the</strong> context of that<br />

work, nor does it correspond to <strong>Brentano</strong>’s later point of view. But it is relevant to <strong>the</strong> present work.<br />

42 <strong>Brentano</strong> here defines <strong>the</strong> “existent” as that in relation to which <strong>the</strong> affirmative judgement is true<br />

or correct. His later <strong>the</strong>ory gives us a more exact formulation of <strong>the</strong> thought behind this definition.<br />

According to <strong>Brentano</strong>’s later <strong>the</strong>ory, such expressions as “existence”, “being”, “existing”, are<br />

synsemantic, having no meaning by <strong>the</strong>mselves; that is to say, “existence” <strong>and</strong> “being” do not name

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!