09.04.2013 Views

Teaching and the Decline of Liberty at Credulity and Curiosity in A ...

Teaching and the Decline of Liberty at Credulity and Curiosity in A ...

Teaching and the Decline of Liberty at Credulity and Curiosity in A ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Theaetetus <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Possibility <strong>of</strong> False Op<strong>in</strong>ion 183<br />

first. The argument won't allow us to choose nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. But why does<br />

Socr<strong>at</strong>es suggest, <strong>in</strong>stead, th<strong>at</strong> <strong>the</strong> argument won't permit both altern<strong>at</strong>ives? In<br />

particular, if we admit <strong>the</strong> second altern<strong>at</strong>ive, or <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>in</strong> general <strong>of</strong> not<br />

know<strong>in</strong>g wh<strong>at</strong> one knows, why should <strong>the</strong> argument compel us to reject <strong>the</strong> first<br />

altern<strong>at</strong>ive, or to affirm <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> false op<strong>in</strong>ion? Why should it tell us not<br />

merely<br />

th<strong>at</strong> false op<strong>in</strong>ion hasn't been shown to be impossible s<strong>in</strong>ce it would<br />

belong, if it exists, to a class whose possibility <strong>in</strong> general has been admitted<br />

but also th<strong>at</strong> it does exist, <strong>and</strong> exists by a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> logical necessity? To be sure,<br />

our ord<strong>in</strong>ary experience suggests th<strong>at</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> false op<strong>in</strong>ion is an obvious<br />

fact, but experience can't tell us th<strong>at</strong> this fact, if it is a fact, emerges by any ne<br />

cessity. Couldn't <strong>the</strong>re be a world <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> only know<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs are able not<br />

to know, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>deed do not know, wh<strong>at</strong> <strong>the</strong>y know, without <strong>the</strong>ir ever hold<strong>in</strong>g<br />

false op<strong>in</strong>ions? Couldn't <strong>the</strong>y have partial knowledge, for example, <strong>of</strong> some sub<br />

ject, like ma<strong>the</strong>m<strong>at</strong>ics, which <strong>the</strong>y would both know <strong>and</strong> not know, <strong>in</strong> a sense,<br />

<strong>and</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y could learn more <strong>and</strong> more about, without <strong>the</strong>ir ever mistak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

one number for ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> without any falsity <strong>in</strong> any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir op<strong>in</strong>ions (144<br />

b3-4)? Socr<strong>at</strong>es apparently believes th<strong>at</strong> such a case is impossible, or <strong>at</strong> least<br />

impossible as <strong>the</strong> only <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> not know<strong>in</strong>g wh<strong>at</strong> one knows, <strong>and</strong> we must<br />

wonder why. But for now, it is less important to see <strong>the</strong> grounds for this judg<br />

ment than to see its implic<strong>at</strong>ions for <strong>the</strong> argument as a whole. False op<strong>in</strong>ion will<br />

necessarily exist, accord<strong>in</strong>g to this stronger suggestion, if it is possible not to<br />

know wh<strong>at</strong> one knows. Socr<strong>at</strong>es is not, <strong>the</strong>n, tre<strong>at</strong><strong>in</strong>g this possibility merely as a<br />

condition <strong>of</strong> false op<strong>in</strong>ion though it is th<strong>at</strong> but also as a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> cause, for it<br />

entails th<strong>at</strong> false op<strong>in</strong>ion must necessarily exist. And if someone were to under<br />

st<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> not know<strong>in</strong>g wh<strong>at</strong> one knows, <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong> it as en<br />

tail<strong>in</strong>g false op<strong>in</strong>ion, he would have a firmer trust <strong>in</strong> his very experience th<strong>at</strong><br />

false op<strong>in</strong>ion exists. For by underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g why false op<strong>in</strong>ion must necessarily<br />

exist, he would also know better th<strong>at</strong> it does <strong>in</strong>deed exist. And he would <strong>the</strong>n be<br />

more truly free <strong>of</strong><br />

Protagoras'<br />

claim th<strong>at</strong> all op<strong>in</strong>ions are true.<br />

Theaetetus, however, didn't notice this subtlety <strong>in</strong> Socr<strong>at</strong>es'<br />

response to him,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>deed he could hardly have been expected to, <strong>at</strong> least not without read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> record <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir convers<strong>at</strong>ion th<strong>at</strong> Socr<strong>at</strong>es will l<strong>at</strong>er help Eucleides to write.<br />

And for <strong>the</strong> time be<strong>in</strong>g, Socr<strong>at</strong>es apparently thought it unwise to <strong>in</strong>sist upon this<br />

h<strong>in</strong>t. Instead, he <strong>the</strong>n <strong>of</strong>fered his suggestion about knowledge be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> us as <strong>in</strong> an<br />

aviary a suggestion, as we have seen, which led back to <strong>the</strong> difficulty th<strong>at</strong><br />

Theaetetus had already understood, namely, th<strong>at</strong> false op<strong>in</strong>ion cannot exist un<br />

less it is possible not to know wh<strong>at</strong> one knows. Now Theaetetus'<br />

trust <strong>in</strong> his ex<br />

perience <strong>of</strong> false op<strong>in</strong>ion, toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong>ir earlier refut<strong>at</strong>ion <strong>of</strong> Protagoras, pre<br />

vent him from deny<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>at</strong> false op<strong>in</strong>ion exists. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, his youthful<br />

concern for truth protects him from <strong>the</strong> facile "common<br />

sense"<br />

th<strong>at</strong> would grant<br />

th<strong>at</strong> we can not know wh<strong>at</strong> we know, though this seems self-contradictory to<br />

him, merely <strong>in</strong> order to reta<strong>in</strong> his belief <strong>in</strong> false op<strong>in</strong>ion. While he won't deny <strong>the</strong><br />

existence <strong>of</strong> false op<strong>in</strong>ion, nei<strong>the</strong>r will he say th<strong>at</strong> we can know wh<strong>at</strong> we don't

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!