07.04.2013 Views

foucault-and-the-iranian-revolution-janet-afary

foucault-and-the-iranian-revolution-janet-afary

foucault-and-the-iranian-revolution-janet-afary

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

280<br />

Notes to Pages 9-2 3<br />

6. We would like to thank Michael Uiwy for helping us to clarify this point.<br />

7 . Georg Stauth (199 1 ) has written that, ra<strong>the</strong>r than supporting <strong>the</strong> Iranian Islamists,<br />

Foucault was merely analyzing <strong>the</strong>ir movement (see also Olivier <strong>and</strong> Labbe 1991). Ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

Foucault supporter, Keating, pointed out that "Foucault turned out to be horribly wrong<br />

about <strong>the</strong> Iranian Revolution ," but that, none<strong>the</strong>less, his Iran writings offered something<br />

important. This was because <strong>the</strong>y revealed a "largely unarticulated <strong>the</strong>ory of.resistance"<br />

(Keating 199 7, 181, 182). For very helpful critical analyses of <strong>the</strong> relationship of Foucault's<br />

thought to matters of cultural aiterity involving Japan, Iran, <strong>and</strong> Islam, see Fuyuki Kurasawa<br />

(1999) <strong>and</strong> Ian Almond (2004).<br />

Chapter 1<br />

1. Of course, as discussed below, both Foucault <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Islamists deployed numerous<br />

elements of modernity. For <strong>the</strong> Islamists, this meant utilizing ail <strong>the</strong> levers of power of a<br />

modern state after <strong>the</strong> <strong>revolution</strong>.<br />

2. Two decades earlier, <strong>the</strong> neo-Marxist Herbert Marcuse expressed a somewhat<br />

similar view in his Eros <strong>and</strong> Civilization: "There is no freedom from administration <strong>and</strong><br />

its laws because <strong>the</strong>y appear as <strong>the</strong> ultimate guarantors of liberty. The revolt against<br />

<strong>the</strong>m would be <strong>the</strong> supreme crime again-this time not against <strong>the</strong> despotic animal who<br />

forbids gratification but against <strong>the</strong> wise order which secures <strong>the</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> services for<br />

<strong>the</strong> progressive satisfaction of human needs. Rebellion now appears as <strong>the</strong> crime against<br />

<strong>the</strong> whole of human society <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore as beyond reward <strong>and</strong> beyond redemption.<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> very progress of civilization tends to make this rationality a spurious<br />

one. The existing liberties <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> existing gratifications are tied to <strong>the</strong> requirements of<br />

domination; <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>mselves become instruments of repression. " Unlike Foucault, Marcuse<br />

believed that <strong>the</strong> system maintained itself through <strong>the</strong> manipulation of <strong>the</strong> individual's<br />

consciousness, including <strong>the</strong> promotion of "thoughtless leisure activities" <strong>and</strong> a relaxation<br />

of sexual taboos (1962, 85-86).<br />

3. Foucault adopts two seemingly contradictory attitudes toward <strong>the</strong> concept of<br />

silence in volume 1 of <strong>the</strong> History of Sexuality. In one place, as above, he praises <strong>the</strong><br />

premodern culture of silence, "where secrets of sex are not forced out" (1978a, 59), in<br />

contrast to <strong>the</strong> "regime of truth " established after <strong>the</strong> seventeenth century in Europe. In<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r place, however, he criticizes <strong>the</strong> silence imposed upon children conceming <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

own sexuality in <strong>the</strong> modern era, which results in parents <strong>and</strong> educators speaking for<br />

children in such matters (27). What he misses is that premodern silences are also imposed<br />

<strong>and</strong> forced, especially on women.<br />

4. Michael Gillespie makes a valuable point when he writes that Heidegger's rejection<br />

of categorical reason in favor of pure intuitionism runs <strong>the</strong> danger of "mistaking <strong>the</strong><br />

subrational for <strong>the</strong> suprarational" (1984, 174).<br />

5. As we will see below, Foucault did explore <strong>the</strong> regulation of fertility in <strong>the</strong> West<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> racist views about genetics <strong>and</strong> colonized peoples that accompanied it. Here again,<br />

his emphasis was on <strong>the</strong> West.<br />

6. Foucault often leaves out facts that could undermine his <strong>the</strong>sis. For example, he<br />

does not mention that after <strong>the</strong> French Revolution, <strong>the</strong> penal code of 1791 decriminalized<br />

h omosexuality <strong>and</strong> only recognized one type of sexual crime, <strong>the</strong> rape of a woman. France<br />

thus became <strong>the</strong> first European country to abrogate antisodomy laws. This did not mean

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!