07.04.2013 Views

Philosophy, - Interpretation

Philosophy, - Interpretation

Philosophy, - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

111<br />

Winter 1990-91 Volume 18 Number 2<br />

Chaninah Maschler Some Observations About Plato's Plaedo<br />

David Roochnik The Serious Play<br />

of Plato's Euthydemus<br />

Charles Salman The Wisdom of Plato's Aristophanes<br />

Roger M. Barrus David Hume's Theology<br />

Greg<br />

of Liberation<br />

Russell Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs<br />

Daryl McGowan Tress Feminist Theory<br />

Discussion<br />

313 Christopher A. Colmo Reply<br />

Book Review<br />

to Lowenthal<br />

and Its Discontents<br />

317 Maureen Feder-Marcus Time, Freedom, and the Common Good: An<br />

Essay in Public <strong>Philosophy</strong> , by Charles<br />

Sherover


Editor-in-Chief Hilail Gildin<br />

General Editors<br />

Consulting Editors<br />

Editors<br />

Manuscript Editor<br />

Subscriptions<br />

Inquiries:<br />

<strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Seth G. Benardete Charles E. Butterworth<br />

Hilail Gildin Robert Horwitz (d. 1987)<br />

Howard B. White (d. 1974)<br />

Christopher Bruell Joseph Cropsey<br />

Ernest L. Fortin John Hallowell Wilhelm Hennis<br />

Harry<br />

Harvey C. Mansfield, Jr. Arnaldo Momigliano<br />

(d. 1987) Michael Oakeshott Ellis Sandoz<br />

V. Jaffa David Lowenthal Muhsin Mahdi<br />

Leo Strauss (d. 1973) Kenneth W. Thompson<br />

Wayne Ambler Maurice Auerbach Fred Baumann<br />

Michael Blaustein Mark Blitz Patrick Coby<br />

Christopher A. Colmo Edward J. Erler Maureen<br />

Feder-Marcus Joseph E. Goldberg Pamela K.<br />

Jensen Grant B.Mindle James W. Morris Will<br />

Morrisey<br />

Gerald Proietti Charles T. Rubin<br />

Leslie G. Rubin John A. Wettergreen (d. 1989)<br />

Bradford P Wilson Hossein Ziai Michael Zuckert<br />

Catherine Zuckert<br />

Lucia B. Prochnow<br />

Subscription rates per volume (3 issues):<br />

individuals $21<br />

libraries and all other institutions $34<br />

students (five-year limit) $ 1 2<br />

Single copies available.<br />

Postage outside U.S.: Canada $3.50 extra;<br />

elsewhere $4 extra by surface mail (8 weeks or<br />

longer) or $7.50 by air.<br />

Payments: in U.S. dollars and payable by<br />

a financial institution located within the U.S.A.<br />

(or the U.S. Postal Service).<br />

contributors should follow The Chicago Manual<br />

of Style, 13th ed. or manuals based on it; place<br />

references in the text or follow current journal style<br />

in printing references. To ensure impartial judgment<br />

of their manuscripts, contributors should omit<br />

mention of their other work; put, on the title page<br />

only, their name, any affiliation desired, address<br />

with postal/zip code in full, and telephone. Please<br />

send three clear copies.<br />

Composition by Eastern Graphics, Binghamton,<br />

N.Y. 13901<br />

Printed and bound by Wickersham Printing Co.,<br />

Lancaster, PA 17603<br />

Patricia D'Allura, Assistant to the Editor,<br />

interpretation, Queens College, Flushing, N.Y.<br />

11367-0904, U.S.A. (718)520-7099


<strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Winter 1990-91 A Volume 18 Number 2<br />

Chaninah Maschler Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 177<br />

David Roochnik The Serious Play<br />

of Plato's Euthydemus 211<br />

Charles Salman The Wisdom of Plato's Aristophanes 233<br />

Roger M. Barrus David Hume's Theology of Liberation 251<br />

Greg<br />

Russell Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs 273<br />

Daryl McGowan Tress Feminist Theory<br />

Discussion<br />

and Its Discontents 293<br />

Christopher A. Colmo Reply to Lowenthal 313<br />

Book Review<br />

Maureen Feder-Marcus Time, Freedom, and the Common Good: An<br />

Essay in Public <strong>Philosophy</strong> , by Charles<br />

Sherover 317<br />

Copyright 1991 interpretation<br />

ISSN 0020-9635


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo<br />

Chaninah Maschler<br />

St. John's College<br />

The essay below falls into four unequal parts:<br />

1 .<br />

An<br />

introduction that places the Phaedo among the other dialogues con<br />

cerning the last days of Socrates,<br />

2. A section analyzing and appraising the first of the dialogue's four major<br />

arguments for the soul's not dying,<br />

3. A section in which the similes of the cloak and the lyre are studied in<br />

some detail,<br />

4. A concluding section about Platonic Forms.<br />

1. INTRODUCTION<br />

The Apology, Crito, and Phaedo, all three, purport to be "apologies,"<br />

accused man's formal reply to a plaintiff's charge against him), albeit before<br />

different<br />

audiences.1<br />

In the dialogue that bears the name Apology, Socrates is in court. The for<br />

mal charge against him is impiety and corruption of the young. Roughly, this<br />

seems to mean that by questioning the authority<br />

(an<br />

of those who shape public<br />

opinion in Athens these were the poets, craftsmen, and politicians he un<br />

dermined civic solidarity to such a degree as to have harmed the body politic.<br />

The jurymen who hear and judge him represent the city of Athens entire. Here,<br />

in court, it is his life as a public personage that he is explaining and, in that<br />

sense, defending. He is also exhibiting it.<br />

In the Crito Socrates is in jail. The accusation, brought by<br />

the friend and<br />

agemate after whom the dialogue is named, is that Socrates, in accepting the<br />

Athenian jurymen's verdict and staying in jail to await execution, is acting<br />

irresponsibly toward his family and intimates. It is his death, or rather, his<br />

acceptance of death at the city's instance, that Socrates is explaining and justi<br />

fying<br />

to Crito.<br />

In the Phaedo we are made to overhear an<br />

Socrates conducted himself the day<br />

of that eyewitness.<br />

eyewitnes<br />

account of how<br />

he drank the hemlock. Phaedo is the name<br />

Phaedo reports that even on his last day, in the midst of friends who might<br />

be expected decently to still their own grief and to try<br />

interpretation, Winter 1990-1991. Vol. 18, No. 2<br />

to support Socrates'


178 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

equanimity in the face of death, Socrates still is "defending<br />

against the "accusation"<br />

interest. Or at least,<br />

himself,"<br />

this time<br />

that in choosing death he is acting against his own<br />

as Socrates'<br />

of sense ought to be troubled at dying (62,63),<br />

Cebes'<br />

young Theban friend Cebes puts it, that a man<br />

as Socrates appears not to be.<br />

remark, to be fair to the young man, actually takes the mild form of<br />

wondering how the various things said by Socrates hang<br />

stung by<br />

Socrates'<br />

together. He feels<br />

strange dictum that, while it would be wrong for a man to<br />

do violence to himself because he is not his own, but the god's property, nev<br />

ertheless, if he is a philosopher, he will die gladly.<br />

Socrates'<br />

saying<br />

would not be strange if it meant that philosophers do cheer<br />

fully and without groaning what we all must willy-nilly, or if it meant that,<br />

once a man sees clearly that death must soon come because he has made certain<br />

choices (98e), he becomes resigned to the outcome and, if he is the type of<br />

human being who derives pleasure from seeing why things are and must be as<br />

they are, he will not be bitter in his resignation. He may even, intermittently,<br />

experience a fierce joy at seeing the curve of his career with such utter clarity.<br />

But, as we all know, Socrates'<br />

He declares that "<br />

dying and being dead, nought<br />

What can he mean?<br />

words are much harsher and darker than this.<br />

those who pursue philosophy aright keep rehearsing<br />

else"<br />

(64a, epiteedeuousin).<br />

A first and moderately clear answer is.given at 64c-69e. In the eyes of those<br />

whose sense of life derives from such pleasures as eating, drinking, sex, fancy<br />

clothes, people who do not exert themselves to obtain such goods,<br />

who even<br />

despise their momentary selves (and others) for taking them seriously, look "as<br />

good as dead<br />

already."<br />

I am not at all sure that people who spend much time or money on fine food,<br />

or try the role of Don Juan, or devote their holiday time off to shopping sprees,<br />

experience the goods on which they gorge themselves as mere pleasures of the<br />

body, since even in the case of the pleasures of eating and drinking, and mani<br />

festly in the other cases, other people, their look of approval or envy, and thus<br />

their fellowship, are normally involved. Frequently some modicum of skill and<br />

connoisseurship enter as well. Still, it is probably fair to say that to a Spinoza<br />

or a Newton the majority of human beings look as though their lives were<br />

oriented toward finding opportunity for indulging their body.<br />

A second interpretation of the philosophic life's being a regimen of dying is<br />

given at 66d. Philosophers do not, according to Socrates, lack all acquisitive<br />

impulses. They<br />

want to "acquire"<br />

wisdom and knowledge. But they find, so he<br />

reports, that fellowship with their body and what their body gives them direct<br />

access to interferes with their obtaining what they are after. So, as much as<br />

possible, they dissociate themselves from its lusts and passions; they despise<br />

and sit in judgment on the deliveries of eyes and ears, allying themselves in<br />

stead to reasoning and calculating and all such powers of the soul as transcend<br />

the bodily.


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 179<br />

One may (and should) protest that philosopher-scientists are hardly the only<br />

ones who, when they find their concentration broken by a headache or hunger<br />

pangs or too great heat or cold, resent their embodied condition. The same<br />

holds for generals, poets, painters, businessmen. And isn't it absurd to reserve<br />

reasoning and calculating strictly for philosopher-scientists? Why is it the phi<br />

losopher more than other men that gets singled out as a despiser of the body?<br />

The question might not seem relevant to the purposes of the Phaedo, except<br />

that we do not as yet know exactly what the dialogue's objectives are. Now we,<br />

and the immediate, named audience for Phaedo's narrative, namely Echecrates<br />

and his fellow citizens from Phlius (cf. Diogenes Laertius viii. 46),<br />

are ex<br />

pressly told by Phaedo that philosophy is the dialogue's theme (59a).<br />

Philosophers, says Socrates, differ from other men in terms of what they<br />

desire and what they say they are lovers of (hou epithoumen te kai phamen<br />

erastai einai). They are not men who lack passion but men mastered by a<br />

different passion than are the majority. Now no matter how devoted to his<br />

enterprise a general, a poet, a businessman is, no matter how hard he drives<br />

himself, he cannot, in Socrates'<br />

terms, long for separation from the body, be<br />

cause the things that are real to him the troops, terrain, supplies, the risk of<br />

defeat, the hope for victory; the lyric, the ode, the play; the factory, the busi<br />

ness partnership, the money owed to him or by him though I believe not one<br />

of them is simply bodily (here I want to quarrel with what Socrates says at<br />

66d), do all involve things that can be touched, seen, heard. What is more,<br />

these enterprises, even if engaged in by people who believe in plain living and<br />

high thinking, call for some sort of love and respect for the bodily.<br />

At least according to the section of the Phaedo now under examination (66<br />

ff.), the philosopher, intent upon truth, has no such love and respect, whether<br />

for his own body, bodily desires, and sensory faculties, or for the bodily and<br />

perceptually accessible features of things other than himself, including his<br />

friends .<br />

"When, then, does the soul encounter truth? Because when it tries to consider<br />

anything with the body it is evidently deceived by it. In thought or reasoning,<br />

is becomes manifest to it. . But it<br />

then, if at all, something of what genuinely .<br />

thinks best when none of these [bodily] things troubles it, neither hearing nor sight,<br />

nor pain nor any pleasure, when the soul is, to the extent possible, alone by itself<br />

and takes leave of the body.<br />

"<br />

(65b)<br />

Since the opening thesis of the present section of the dialogue was that being<br />

dead can be defined as the state in which body and soul are severed from one<br />

another, each having reached a condition of being alone and by itself (auto kath<br />

hauto), we have, verbally, justified Socrates'<br />

philosopher "does what he<br />

dark saying that in dying the<br />

wishes,"<br />

obtains a good long sought (67d, 68a).<br />

Fortunately, the dialogue arranges for Cebes to protest in our behalf. Being<br />

the well-bred youth he is, he doesn't put the question quite so rudely. Still, he


180 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

in effect asks what all along we have been muttering to ourselves: Doesn't<br />

Socrates'<br />

opening definition of death suppose the very thing that we least be<br />

lieve, namely, that when, as people say, the soul leaves a man's body, it con<br />

tinues to be something independent and coherent that has power and intel<br />

ligence (dunamis kai phronesis)! The form which Cebes'<br />

he reminds Socrates of a familiar "model"<br />

protest takes is that<br />

for the soul, namely, that it is what<br />

we, today, would call a gas, like air, which, when it is released from the bodily<br />

container that held it in, becomes an unidentifiable part of the atmosphere. The<br />

word Cebes uses to express this thought is the Greek stand-in for our Latinate<br />

word "spirit,"<br />

viz. pneuma (70a).<br />

Here is how Socrates responds to what the dialogue describes as the com<br />

mon fear that no integral soul will be left over upon death, only<br />

an integral<br />

body, the corpse:<br />

According to many folk traditions, the souls of grandparents or great grand<br />

parents wait in Hades for rebirth in their descendants (Jews and ancient Greeks<br />

both often name their sons after deceased grandparents). Socrates is no funda<br />

mentalist about these old stories. Still, if it could be established that the living<br />

have nothing else to come from except what has died, then (says Socrates) the<br />

folk tradition might gain support and, in turn, give support to the philosopher's<br />

hope that death brings, not extinction, but consummation of his deepest de<br />

sire an interval at least of complete independence from the body.<br />

We have set the stage for the first argument for the soul's immortality, the<br />

argument "from<br />

opposites"<br />

(70c-72e).<br />

Opposites, or contrariety, have, of course, been with us from the beginning<br />

(58e, 60b). Notice also that we are told by Phaedo, our eyewitness, that he and<br />

his friends assembled in jail at daybreak and that Socrates died as the sun was<br />

going down (61e, 116b, e).<br />

2. ARGUMENTS<br />

Isn't it the case, says Socrates, that change and generation always proceed<br />

from opposite to opposite, the noble from the shameful, the just from the in-<br />

just, the greater from the smaller, the weaker from the stronger, the slower<br />

from the quicker, the worse from the better? If this holds true universally, then<br />

it holds also for life, at least, if to live (zcn) has an opposite, as being awake<br />

has the opposite being asleep. Manifestly<br />

there is an opposite to life (whether<br />

we consider the infinitive, the participle, or the adjective of the word root), the<br />

very thing we are all waiting for, death.<br />

Now in all the enumerated instances of paired opposites the extremes are<br />

linked by a genesis between them: Between the greater and the lesser thing<br />

(pragma) there is increase and diminution which, as they go on (there is a<br />

verbal substitution of infinitive for noun), amount to being-on-the-increase or


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo -181<br />

being-on-the-decrease. That is to say, not only are there opposite poles, there<br />

are also opposite processes of moving between the poles, (cf. Aristotle's defini<br />

tion of motion as "the actuality of the potential qua potential.) The person now<br />

asleep wakes up and continues in a wakeful state; next falls asleep<br />

tinues in a sleeping state. And we have seen this cycle repeat itself.<br />

and con<br />

Admittedly, we have not actually observed returning to life as we have ob<br />

served dying. But don't considerations of symmetry make the inference that<br />

there is such a process of returning from Hades plausible?<br />

And if, just as the man awake comes from the man asleep, the man alive<br />

comes from the man dead, then we seem to have demonstrated what we wanted<br />

to establish, namely, that dead men's souls do not after separation from their<br />

bodies disintegrate but abide somewhere.<br />

try:<br />

Moreover, consider the consequences of denying<br />

the inference from symme<br />

"If generation did not proceed from opposite to opposite and back again, going<br />

round, as it were in a circle, but always went forward in a straight line, without<br />

turning back or curving, then, you know, in the end all things would have the same<br />

shape and be in the same condition and stop being<br />

generated.<br />

(72b)<br />

How good an argument is this? How seriously is it being offered?<br />

I find these questions much harder to answer than do some other readers of<br />

the dialogue whose comments 1 have heard or read. My<br />

kinds at least:<br />

1 .<br />

difficulties are of four<br />

Unless one settles precisely what conclusion is to be established by what<br />

premises and what degree and kind of cogency the author of the argument<br />

claims for it, how can one decide the goodness or badness of the argument?<br />

What I mean becomes evident if one considers that if one disregards the fabric<br />

of the given premises and conclusion,<br />

a Democritean materialist argument can<br />

be seen in or culled from the various things Socrates says, e.g. that round soul-<br />

atoms must abide to be available for reintegration with other atoms so as to<br />

constitute some new living being.<br />

being<br />

2. Mustn't one clear up the ambiguity of my phrase "how seriously is it<br />

Socrates' "offering"<br />

offered"<br />

by disentangling<br />

one go about doing this?<br />

from Plato's? How does<br />

3. Supposing that one has articulated what the argument is and what strength<br />

infer that<br />

it purports to have and one finds fault with it, can one now safely<br />

Socrates and/or Plato knew that the argument was weak?<br />

4. Again, supposing<br />

and/or Plato were knowingly offering<br />

that one has somehow satisfied oneself that Socrates<br />

poor arguments for the soul's immor<br />

tality, what do they stand to gain? What is the point?<br />

True enough, where I humorlessly insist on premises, conclusion, logical<br />

cogency, and all that sort of thing, the dialogue has Socrates talk gaily of being


182 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

far from impartial as to the outcome of arguments for the soul's immortality,<br />

thus not a kosher witness. And I would immediately join the reader who ac<br />

cuses me of obtuseness in not taking into account that Socrates'<br />

friends (both in<br />

the dialogue the ones with him in jail as well as the ones who assemble with<br />

Phaedo to call Socrates to mind after his death; and outside it ourselves, who<br />

are reading what Plato wrote)<br />

need consolation and might receive it even from<br />

poor arguments. Moreover, when Plato, later in the dialogue (85d), makes<br />

Cebes'<br />

friend Simmias speak of arguments (or speeches or accounts) of the soul<br />

and its fate as life rafts, we are told in so many words that anything like<br />

mathematical cogency is foresworn. Still, the fact remains that Socrates is por<br />

trayed as spending his last day amidst his friends laying out very elaborate<br />

arguments to prove that his soul will live on. To treat these as mere divertisse<br />

ment,<br />

them.<br />

cannot be right. Therefore I feel obliged to state what fault I find with<br />

My chief difficulty with the reasoning<br />

so far is this: As we learn from a later<br />

section of the dialogue (103), Socrates means to be speaking of opposite things<br />

(pragmata) rather than of opposite qualities (auto to enantion)<br />

when he refers<br />

to the poles between which the processes that carry from one extreme to the<br />

other stretch. We know that the waking Socrates, who, early in the dialogue<br />

(60e), told his friends of a recurring dream that commanded him to make mu<br />

sic, dreamt this dream while in a condition of sleeping. Our lives on earth are<br />

cycles the arcs of which are living wakefully and living<br />

sleepingly. Other peo<br />

ple who watch us and, more mysteriously, we ourselves, through memory,<br />

know that the same individual traverses these two arcs. The question under<br />

discussion, namely, whether the state of being<br />

dead will be a state of the soul's<br />

finally gaining the independence from the body and the purity<br />

cording<br />

to Socrates'<br />

for which, ac<br />

report, some human beings long, requires that we consider<br />

how much or how little an individual's life on earth, as consisting of these two<br />

arcs of sleeping and waking, is like another cycle, whose existence we are<br />

inquiring into.<br />

This other cycle would consist of the two arcs (a) life on earth, from being<br />

born, through acme (the stretch around the meridian), to death; (b) life under<br />

the earth, in Hades, the invisible realm.<br />

Now in addition to the difficulty that I have in fitting the two circles together<br />

(the waking-sleeping circle ought to be part of the being alive-being dead cir<br />

cle, but can it?), I find it hard to know who or what is the thing (pragma) that<br />

traverses now the life-on-earth arc, now the life-under-the-earth arc.<br />

If this thing is, for example, Socrates, who is a composite of soul and body,<br />

what reason is there to hope that in Hades the soul will be released from the<br />

task of ruling over and caring for its body, free at last to devote itself entirely to<br />

wisdom?<br />

Both the astral paradigm which, I am confident, inspired much of the argu<br />

ment now under examination, and the sleeping-waking paradigm seem to re-


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 183<br />

quire that the thing over and under the earth be Socrates as ensouled body or<br />

embodied soul: Sleeping and waking as well as being now above,<br />

now below<br />

the horizon are attributes of animated bodies. Bear in mind that the stars are<br />

living beings for Plato, and Aristotle; for Ptolemy as well.<br />

If, on the other hand, throwing away the just-mentioned analogies, we try<br />

the hypothesis that the thing which traverses the life-on-earth arc is the embod<br />

ied soul of Socrates, whereas the thing<br />

sively Socrates'<br />

that traverses the Hades arc is exclu<br />

soul, his body having been left in the visible world as a corpse,<br />

then aren't we talking about two different things rather than about one thing<br />

with contrary attributes?<br />

Of course, the opening definition of death, according to which the process<br />

of dying is the process of loosening soul from body and the state of being dead<br />

is the state of each, soul and body, existing "itself by itself"<br />

(auto kath hauto),<br />

could be taken to amount to a denial of what was perhaps too confidently<br />

asserted in the last sentence: Mightn't being Socrates consist in being Socrates'<br />

soul, so that his present incarnated existence would be one among many adven<br />

tures of this same thing, the soul of Socrates?<br />

Many passages in the Phaedo (1 15d, 1 1 lc, 107c), and in other dialogues as<br />

well (Republic x. 608 ff. , Phaedrus 245, Meno 86, Symposium 212, Timaeus<br />

41, Laws x, xii), play<br />

migration to point a moral, the moral being<br />

with Pythagorean-Empedoclean-Indian ideas of trans<br />

our present life matters as though for all eternity.<br />

that how we conduct ourselves in<br />

According to these passages, the soul of Socrates continues as a soul with its<br />

individual past life at least in the sense that this soul's next life episode,<br />

whether incarnate or sans body, is chosen or bestowed because of the choices<br />

that were made in the course of the immediately preceding life.<br />

ing<br />

One is tempted to demythologize such talk about transmigration by combin<br />

it with the folk belief that our ancestors do not die but are reincarnated in<br />

ourselves, as we shall be in future generations. That would amount to urging<br />

something like what is said in the Old Testament, that the evil which we do<br />

lives beyond us till the third or fourth generation, in grandchildren and great<br />

grandchildren.<br />

Whether one ought to take Socrates'<br />

words in this rationalizing way is the<br />

thing I find hard to determine. On a rationalized reading, the story of the man<br />

in the myth of Er, who chooses a next life of evil because his previous life of<br />

virtue was based solely on habit unenlightened by reflection, would be taken to<br />

apply, say, to Polemarchus/Cephalus and their descendants.<br />

The reader may lack sympathy for my laboring over and belaboring<br />

of the<br />

question of what exactly Plato's Socrates and Plato intended. Why be so literal<br />

minded and humorless, precisely on this question of what Plato meant to be<br />

taken literally and what metaphorically, what was said seriously and what was<br />

said jokingly?<br />

So I had better confess that, whether reading or listening, I feel guilty when


184 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

I am caught, or catch myself, plugging in a sense that suits me, instead of<br />

straining for, guessing at, the other fellow's sense. It seems to me that, both in<br />

conversation and when we read, we are often much too quick to rule out mean<br />

ings which we believe to be obviously wrong or trivial. Sometimes we even<br />

puff ourselves up in pride that we sophisticates know how to read between the<br />

lines, know that this or that is said solely to pacify the vulgar, or again, that it<br />

is not to be taken straight but obliquely (ironically). We conceive of ourselves<br />

as humbly embracing<br />

the sane exegetic principle that wise men cannot err in<br />

obvious ways. But don't we sometimes make this exegetic principle axiomatic<br />

because our vanity is gratified that the wise author picked us to be his elect<br />

readers, we being<br />

the ones who have what it takes to determine in what tone of<br />

voice a wise author's falsehoods or fallacies were pronounced?<br />

It seems to me that the delicate business of hearing<br />

another person out is<br />

made impossible if we disallow that what he or she means is something we<br />

would not want to mean. To put it paradoxically, I believe it is a mark of<br />

disrespect to eliminate the possibility that an author's argument or imagery or<br />

theory may be wanting, in clarity or cogency or both. What I am attending to is<br />

the difference between "reverend interpretation"<br />

(as the scholastics called it) of<br />

a canonical legal or other community-building and community-sustaining text,<br />

such as the Bible or the myths used by the Greek tragedians,<br />

interpretation of the text left us by an individual designing author.<br />

and reverend<br />

As already said, I do find the argument from opposites wanting, yet wanting<br />

in an interesting way, since what the argument clearly leaves unclear is the<br />

identity<br />

of the "thing,"<br />

Socrates.<br />

The two "middle"<br />

arguments .<br />

1 . The<br />

argument according to which the learning soul has a richer store of<br />

mental possessions to draw on than it could have accumulated over any one<br />

span of life from birth to death (73a-77c) and must, therefore, have pre<br />

existed;<br />

2. The argument according to which the mind has the attributes of its objects<br />

so that, if they are simple and thereby indissoluble, it must be (78b-84b)<br />

even though, as I believe, they too fail, do nevertheless address the question<br />

with which the first argument left us, namely, who or what Socrates is. They<br />

will be taken up in the context of Part 4 of this essay, where I try to examine<br />

what the Phaedo tells us about Platonic Forms.<br />

I repeat, it looks to me as though the dialogue sets its readers the task of<br />

judging whether Socrates has acquitted himself of the charge of acting contrary<br />

to his own good in leaving life, thus, by his own standards, irrationally.<br />

Whether this fact sits easily with us or not, the arguments for the soul's immor<br />

"defense,"<br />

tality purport to be his<br />

so we are obliged to take them seriously. If<br />

nevertheless I turn for the present to another topic, in Part 3 of this essay, it is<br />

in order to prepare for taking the arguments seriously.


3. RECOLLECTION, CLOAKS, AND LYRES<br />

Some Observations About Plato'<br />

s Phaedo 185<br />

Toga and lyre, characteristic belongings of an Athenian youth, turn up early<br />

and late in our dialogue and in speeches by Socrates as well as in speeches by<br />

the two Theban friends Simmias and Cebes. To the two "models"<br />

for soul<br />

which we have so far encountered<br />

1 . That<br />

the soul is a sort of ether which is expelled from the body<br />

at death<br />

(77e) and which then either rises separately to a place above the atmosphere or<br />

immediately after leaving the body gets dispersed in the surrounding air<br />

(Cebes);<br />

2. That the soul is something like a star (rising above the horizon when the<br />

man or hero is born, culminating when he is fully mature and active, slipping<br />

below the horizon when he dies) (Socrates). (Cf. Ptolemy, Almagest 1.3, p. 7,<br />

Great Books of the Western World edition.)<br />

Simmias and Cebes add two other models that the soul is something like the<br />

harmony<br />

of a lyre (Simmias'<br />

weaver of togas (Cebes'<br />

contribution), and that the soul'is something like a<br />

contribution).<br />

My self-assigned task in the present section of this essay<br />

is to comment on<br />

some of the surprising uses to which the last two images are put by Plato.<br />

Socrates says:<br />

"When someone, upon seeing or hearing or in some other way perceiving<br />

something, not only recognizes/identifies/knows that thing, but becomes aware of<br />

(ennoesei) another, the knowledge of which is not the same (aute) but different<br />

(alle), do we not rightly say that he is being<br />

reminded of that of which he is made<br />

mindful (hou ten ennoian elahen)! For example, the knowledge of a man is<br />

different from the knowledge of a lyre. But you know very well that lovers,<br />

when they see a lyre or toga or something else that their darling uses habitually,<br />

tend to have the following experience (paschousi): They<br />

notice the lyre (egnosan te<br />

ten lyran) and also seize hold in their mind (en tei dianoiai) of the form (eidos) of<br />

the boy whose lyre it is which is a being<br />

Simmias is often reminded of Cebes. And there are lots of examples like these. .<br />

reminded. So too someone who sees<br />

Isn't this type of experience some variety of remembering, especially<br />

. .<br />

when it<br />

happens to someone in connection with things which were forgotten because for<br />

long he neither saw them nor meditated on them?<br />

Can a person who sees a drawn horse or a drawn lyre be reminded of a man, or<br />

when he sees a drawn Simmias, can he be reminded of Cebes?<br />

But it is also possible for someone to see a drawn Simmias and to be reminded<br />

of Simmias himself, isn't it? Now don't all these examples go to show that similars<br />

and dissimilars both can prompt remembrance?<br />

It became apparent that it is possible, when perceiving a thing visually or<br />

through hearing or apprehending it by<br />

of something else,<br />

some other sense, to become aware from it<br />

which had been forgotten but which consorted/was associated


186 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

with the other thing; and this may happen whether the two things are similar or<br />

dissimilar."<br />

(73c ff.)<br />

Allow me to present you with a slightly doctored extract from the notebook<br />

in which I recorded my first observations and reflections on the passage just<br />

translated:<br />

1. Socrates does not distinguish "being<br />

2. Only examples of the former, that is, "being<br />

3. The emphasis falls on pointing out that "unlikes"<br />

reminded"<br />

recall."2<br />

from "deliberate<br />

and<br />

"likes"<br />

are given.<br />

indifferently<br />

come in trains. But more, and more elaborate, examples of unlikes conjuring<br />

up an associated unlike are given, as though association by resemblance were<br />

held to be more plausible prima facie and the fact that unlikes too have this<br />

power of evoking each other needed special pleading.<br />

4. While it would be misleading to assimilate the pairing of Socrates'<br />

likes to mere Humean "association by<br />

are friends and the cloak and lyre belong to the beloved, so that a more intimate<br />

relation than "spatio-temporal<br />

contiguity"<br />

(since Simmias and Cebes<br />

propinquity"<br />

is supposed to tie the unlikes to<br />

each other), the contrast that would normally be made between "association by<br />

resemblance"<br />

and "association by<br />

nevertheless applies: Resem<br />

blance is an internal#contiguity an external relation. I call the relation between<br />

the toga and its owner "external"<br />

un<br />

contiguity"<br />

in that the beloved may give his toga to<br />

another without either the beloved dr the toga thereby undergoing alteration;<br />

hence their coupling for the mind may become undone. Contrarywise, the rela<br />

tion between a portrait of Socrates and Socrates, or a drawing<br />

horses, is "internal"<br />

of horses and<br />

in that, when one tries the thought experiment of removing<br />

the relation between the associated terms while keeping the terms the same, one<br />

fails: The look-alikes stay alikes for as long as each is itself.<br />

The example of the relation between Simmias and Cebes seems to me inter<br />

esting because it is not easy to decide whether it is strictly<br />

external: Is Simmias<br />

still himself, still the same, when (as seems conceivable) he is no longer Cebes'<br />

friend?<br />

To learn what to make of the features of Socrates'<br />

noted, we must place the passage in immediate and wider context.<br />

address to Simmias just<br />

We then notice that not Socrates but Cebes was the one who first brought up<br />

the theme of "recollection"<br />

(anamnesis, 126), in order to assist Socrates in his<br />

effort of proving the soul's immortality. Cebes, however, unlike Socrates,<br />

speaks of recollection pretty much as though he were quoting from the Meno:<br />

"Cebes, interrupting, said 'That also holds if it is true, as you, Socrates, are fond<br />

of saying, that our learning (mathesis) is nothing else than recollection (anamnesis).<br />

According to that argument we necessarily knew (perfect of manthanein) at some<br />

previous time the things that we now call to mind. But that would be impossible if<br />

our soul did not exist somewhere before it was born in this human form (eidos)."


When Cebes'<br />

learning is nothing<br />

Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 187<br />

friend Simmias begs for "proof"<br />

of the Socratic "thesis"<br />

that so it is), Cebes obliges. He says:<br />

that<br />

other than recollection (where Meno asked to be "taught"<br />

"Here is the best argument: When people are questioned, if someone puts the<br />

questions well, they say everything themselves (autoi), the way it is. And yet, if<br />

there weren't knowledge and right reason/correct speech (orthos logos) within them<br />

(autois), they would not be able to do<br />

this."<br />

Cebes seems to be talking about recollection as deliberate calling to mind,<br />

making an effort to answer a question, which in the circumstances supposed, of<br />

studying, e.g. mathematics, involves checking for truth and consistency and is<br />

not the sort of automatic triggering of the mind that Socrates seems to be talk<br />

ing<br />

about in the passage with which I began.<br />

Self-control (soophrosune) is one of Socrates's most striking characteristics<br />

(cf. 114e).<br />

Upon reading the Meno one is led to believe that this poise and sanity of<br />

Socrates is due to his unusually highly developed capacity to "recollect"<br />

"call to<br />

mind"<br />

(cf. Leibniz's New Essays bk ii, ch.21,<br />

or<br />

pp. 186ff.). But one is<br />

also led to believe that Socrates held that "natively"<br />

this ability belongs to all<br />

human beings; that making things, their antecedents and consequences and their<br />

mutual connections,<br />

clear and vivid to oneself is "natural"<br />

and that avoiding the strain, "not making the<br />

though strenuous,<br />

effort,"<br />

is some sort of distortion<br />

of our nature. Given these facts, it seemed odd to me that in the Phaedo So<br />

crates should talk about recollection as though it were mere free associating.<br />

Moreover, a later portion of the Phaedo (97ff.) confirms that to be Socrates<br />

is to prize deliberateness: Socrates there explains to his friends how thrilled he<br />

was when, as a young man (presumably going through the same stage of life at<br />

which Simmias and Cebes are now) he heard that a certain philosopher by the<br />

name of Anaxagoras had written a book propounding the thesis that Intelligence<br />

or Mind is what arranged and caused each and all things. Socrates couldn't wait<br />

to read the book but found himself sorely disappointed. Anaxagoras did not<br />

come through on his promise. Whatever Anaxagoras might have meant in say<br />

ing that Mind is the world's Ruler, the detailed working out of his cosmogony<br />

showed that he did not mean that the way each and all things in heaven and on<br />

earth are is due to their being deliberately so arranged. So Socrates gave up on<br />

Anaxagoras.<br />

Not only Anaxagoras, but also Simmias and Cebes are found fault with by<br />

I mean their "models"<br />

for the rela<br />

Socrates (93ff.)<br />

because their "theories,"<br />

tions of soul to body, being strictly biological, pay no attention to and perhaps<br />

don't even leave room for distinctively moral and intellectual agency (initiative,<br />

self-rule).<br />

So, I repeat, at second and third meditation on the piece of the dialogue with


188 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

which I began Part 3 of this essay, it struck me as curious that Plato should<br />

have given the "lines"<br />

about recollection as mere free association to Socrates<br />

and given Cebes the "lines"<br />

about recollection as deliberate calling to mind.<br />

Being mildly surprised by what looked to me like a sort of reversal of roles, I<br />

thought to myself that I should explain this<br />

anomaly.3<br />

Of course to experience<br />

the anomaly as an anomaly one would have to be pretty firmly settled in the<br />

conviction that the Platonic dialogues are artifacts made by the dramatist Plato,<br />

not stenographic records of overheard conversations. Well, then, this was the<br />

prior conviction in me. I was a "sophisticated"<br />

reader.<br />

Here are some of the questions I asked myself as I tried to account for what<br />

had struck me as a minor anomaly:<br />

1. Wasn't I going overboard with my fastidious sorting out of which speech<br />

or argument "befits"<br />

which dramatic personage? Aren't Platonic dialogues pri<br />

marily invitations to investigation, and doesn't that mean that the things that are<br />

being investigated and the arguments, analogies, and experiences brought in for<br />

life,"<br />

this purpose are more important than whom they "belong to"? In "real I<br />

mean, the real life of the mind of human beings, each of us is full of questions<br />

to"<br />

and proposals that "belong our opponents in argument. Why shouldn't the<br />

dialogues mime this fact?<br />

2. Had I, perhaps, been careless of differences between the things later (85e<br />

ff.and 87b ff.) said by the two Theban friends about body<br />

and soul and their<br />

relation? Though the two men's theories that the soul is the body's harmony<br />

(Simmias'<br />

(Cebes'<br />

offering), and that it is the weaver and reweaver of bodily tissue<br />

contribution) are alike in that both are offered to argue against the<br />

soul's immortality, Cebes'<br />

Simmias'<br />

image does give some sort of agency to the soul.<br />

image, on the other hand, though capable of the most fascinating<br />

elaboration, is offered as though, when the ratios happen to fall out right, a<br />

mess of gut and harder stuff becomes a living (empsuchon) being. It then oc<br />

curred to me that Cebes should probably be understood as assigning a sort of<br />

Aristotelian artisan-role to the soul. The soul, like any craftsman working<br />

within a set craft-tradition, executes a "weaving<br />

contrive but inherited. Conceivably<br />

plan"<br />

that it did not itself<br />

this is also the spirit in which his quoted<br />

remarks about the person who is doing the recollecting having "knowledge<br />

within"<br />

that becomes "uttered"<br />

preted.<br />

under favorable circumstances should be inter<br />

3. As the example of the association couple Simmias-Cebes itself had shown<br />

me when I took stock of the fact that the way in which friends are connected is<br />

more intimate then the way in which a cloak and its owner are connected (see<br />

above), I had been simpleminded in considering only the "extremes"<br />

involuntarily<br />

prompting<br />

prompted to find some "out of<br />

oneself to gain access to some "in<br />

mind"<br />

thing "in<br />

of being<br />

mind"<br />

and of<br />

mind"<br />

thing. The "anomaly"<br />

that<br />

got me going was a kind of artifact of the microscope of my too-willful fixing<br />

on "extremes"<br />

when I looked again at Cebes'<br />

without intermediate cases. This self-correction was confirmed<br />

speech the fact that another person's questions


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 189<br />

and diagrams figure in his explanation to Simmias of the notion that learning is<br />

recollection shows that there are gradations between automatic and deliberate<br />

recollection (Plato's thought, spelled out in Sophist 263d, that even solitary<br />

thinking is conversational has a bearing here).<br />

I exhibit this tiny slice of intellectual autobiography because it seems to me<br />

the quickest way of insinuating<br />

about recollection, taken together, might be "about"<br />

ing, i.e., the finding and making<br />

that what the speeches of Cebes and Socrates<br />

is thinking or investigat<br />

of connections and the subsequent critical<br />

examination of the strength and nature of these connections.<br />

There is simply no alternative to starting on any investigation one happens to<br />

undertake with the opinions one happens to have, for instance the opinion that<br />

Platonic dialogues are dramas, or the opinion that recollection means, in the<br />

Meno, deliberate calling to mind rather than free association, or the opinion<br />

that these two free association and self-critical recall of relevant instances<br />

are "opposites."<br />

When one brings these convictions, which are already "in"<br />

oneself, to bear on some present question, one tries to make them hang together<br />

with what is now being investigated and with each other. As one keeps going,<br />

one finds out that one must nuance, rearrange, or even drop<br />

convictions (cf. Phaedo 100).<br />

some of these<br />

So it doesn't matter if I was misguided when, initially, I felt that "free<br />

association"<br />

is not what we normally associate with Socrates (cf. the quotation<br />

from the Odyssey at 94d). What matters is that thinking can be self-corrective<br />

because there are constraints upon what conviction or observation or theory can<br />

be woven together or made to harmonize with what other conviction, observa<br />

tion, feeling, or theory. (Cf. 100 and 92c; cf. also how the weaving<br />

image is<br />

used in the Sophist and Statesman, the weaver's shuttle in the Cratylus.) The<br />

second thing that matters is that one can make a fresh start.<br />

Let's do that. Here is my new question about the same old thing, namely,<br />

the passage about recollection with which Part 3 of this essay began. Why<br />

important for the purposes that Plato had in writing the Phaedo that unlikes too<br />

may<br />

function as mutual reminders?<br />

I answer three ways<br />

1. In terms of writing's relation to speaking,<br />

2. In terms of body's relation to soul,<br />

3. In terms of speech's relation to Platonic forms.<br />

To state my hypothesis compactly, I believe that the Phaedo shows that<br />

Plato thinks (or wants us to think) (1) of writing as a sign of speaking, (2) of<br />

body as a sign of soul, and (3) of speaking as a sign of<br />

a. informed things,<br />

b. informed minds,<br />

c. forms themselves.<br />

I select for elaboration just the second of these suggestions, viz. that body is<br />

a sign of soul.4<br />

By examining in some detail how cloak and lyre illustrate the body-soul<br />

is it


190 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

relation we can, I think, explain why Socrates is made to dwell on the fact that<br />

things which are unlike each other nevertheless form "couples"<br />

and why he is<br />

portrayed as paying more attention than is usual with him to involuntary recol<br />

lection.<br />

Isn't it remarkable that Socrates illustrates recollection by the same things,<br />

toga and lyre (73), which the two young men from Thebes use as similes for<br />

the body (87b and 86a)?<br />

It looks to me as though Socrates was made to speak of how the mere toga<br />

has the power of reminding the lover of the absent beloved, the toga's user and<br />

owner (as does the mere lyre when the beloved has gone elsewhere) in order to<br />

both acknowledge and wean himself away from love of himself as an incarnate<br />

individual. Grieving is to be limited and desire reoriented.<br />

The most compendious description of the emotional effect intended by<br />

Plato's arranging for Socrates'<br />

examples of<br />

examples of the human body is, I think, this:<br />

Lovers'<br />

"reminders"<br />

to turn out to be also<br />

yearning to see the uncloaked form of their beloved is to be thought<br />

of as capable of becoming wholly transferred to the beloved's invisible self<br />

through the model of a "continued<br />

proportion"<br />

garment : bodily form (eidos)<br />

:: bodily eidos : self. And this "continued is conceived as continu<br />

ing until it reaches (haptetai, 65b) "beauty's self and beauty's<br />

Charmides 154c ff. , Symposium 211b).<br />

giver"<br />

(cf.<br />

When, on the other hand, Simmias is made to wonder whether the soul isn't<br />

as dependent on the body as is the harmonia of the lyre on the gut strung tautly<br />

on bent wood so as to make a musical instrument, this is, among other things,<br />

an insisting<br />

nent loss.<br />

In Socrates'<br />

on the right to grieve over the loss of Socrates as a real and perma<br />

speech to "convince"<br />

Simmias that "learning is nothing but<br />

recollection,"<br />

toga and lyre are only loosely connected with what they "belong<br />

to"; that is, in retrospect we realize that Socrates is made to speak of body and<br />

soul as separable, much as Aristotle, in the third book of the De Anima (see<br />

also 403a 10, 404a 26, 405a 14, 408b 19f., 410b 15), deems the mortal indi<br />

vidual human being to be separable from immortal Mind.<br />

In the two Thebans'<br />

speeches, body and soul fit each other much more<br />

tightly: The toga that covers the old weaver is a product of his craft,<br />

lyre-specific harmonia (the word also means dovetailing) is "in"<br />

though not only in its build, since it is also "in"<br />

and the<br />

its build,<br />

its sounds (86c). Thus, as<br />

Socrates'<br />

Simmias and Cebes come to employ images, soul is "of"<br />

its body<br />

pretty much as in the De Anima Book II definition of the soul, where soul is<br />

"from"<br />

or "first<br />

actuality" "organized."<br />

of a body that is<br />

So it looks to me as though the dialogue presents us with<br />

"contrary"<br />

counts of the soul's nature and its relation to the body: According to the first,<br />

the soul is something that has or wears a body as the beloved wears or owns a<br />

cloak or a lyre. According to the second, the body is something<br />

owns a soul as a lyre has "harmony"<br />

when its<br />

ac<br />

that has or<br />

strings'<br />

tensions are just right.


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 191<br />

The fact that Socrates and the two Thebans are portrayed as using "the same<br />

things"<br />

(toga and lyre) to speak so differently of the body-soul relation may be<br />

telling us about a perplexity<br />

solve. Needless to say,<br />

which Plato himself could articulate but not re<br />

neither can I.<br />

The fact that Plato makes the arguments "from<br />

forms"<br />

soul's kinship with the<br />

in the two different arguments "from<br />

look like "inner"<br />

recollec<br />

and "from the<br />

arguments by<br />

"wrapping"<br />

them<br />

opposites"<br />

confirms one's impression that<br />

toward"<br />

he "leans identifying self and soul with mind. (Cf. how, according to<br />

Hesiod, men deceived Zeus "wrapping"<br />

by<br />

their offerings of bare bones in<br />

luscious slices of fat!) Moreover, Plato arranges for all the interlocutors, even<br />

those who figure in the "frame"<br />

of Phaedo's report of what was said that last<br />

day in jail, e.g. Echecrates of Phlius, to band together in their adherence to the<br />

argument for the soul's pre-existing because of its capacity to recollect (87a,<br />

91ef.).<br />

4. EIDE<br />

Perhaps the quickest way of conveying where I want to go in the concluding<br />

section of this essay is to cite two poems, one by the German poet Hans Chris<br />

tian Morgenstern, the other, of which I select just a part, by the English poet<br />

Gerard Manley Hopkins.<br />

Once there was a picket fence<br />

with space between, to gaze from hence to thence<br />

An architect who saw this sight<br />

approached it suddenly one night<br />

removed the spaces from the fence<br />

and built of them a residence.<br />

The picket fence stood there dumbfounded<br />

with pickets wholly unsurrounded,<br />

a view so naked and obscene,<br />

the senate had to intervene.<br />

As for the architect, he flew<br />

to Afri- or Americoo.<br />

H. C. Morgenstern, Galgenlieder (bilingual edition by Max Knight. Berkeley:<br />

University of California Press, 1966). The translation has been slightly corrected.)<br />

How to keep is there any any, is there none such nowhere<br />

known some, bow or brooch or braid or brace, lace latch or<br />

catch or key to keep<br />

Back beauty, keep it, beauty, beauty, beauty, .<br />

away?<br />

from vanishing<br />

O is there no frowning of these wrinkles, ranked wrinkles deep,<br />

Down?


192 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

No there's none, there's none, O no there's none,<br />

Nor can you long be, what you now are, called fair,<br />

Do what you may do, what, do what you may,<br />

And wisdom is early to despair:<br />

Be beginning; since, no, nothing<br />

To keep at bay<br />

Age and age's evils.<br />

Be beginning to despair, to despair,<br />

Despair, despair, despair, despair<br />

Spare!<br />

can be done<br />

There is one, yes I have one (Hush there!)<br />

Only not within seeing of the sun,<br />

Not within the singeing of the strong sun. .<br />

Somewhere elsewhere there is ah well where! one,<br />

One. Yes, I can tell such a key, I do know such a place,<br />

Where<br />

. is<br />

whatever'<br />

s prized and passes of us<br />

kept<br />

Yonder What high as that! We follow, now we follow.<br />

Yonder.<br />

Yonder, yes yonder, yonder,<br />

From "The Leaden and the Golden Echo"<br />

To say it with absurd brevity: The Phaedo seems to me to be about how the<br />

world's beauty, in the form of "betweens"<br />

that are like the spaces between the<br />

pickets, abides "beyond the tall sun's tingeing, or treacherous the tainting of<br />

the earth's<br />

air"<br />

(Hopkins).<br />

Though the density of poetry<br />

gratifies the desire for compactness of state<br />

ment, I want to be intelligible as well as brief. So nothing but plodding exposi<br />

tory prose will come your way<br />

tell a story:<br />

for the rest of this essay. No. I do still have to<br />

A child asked why it must eat and was told "because there is a little stom<br />

ach-man inside you that gets hungry."<br />

So the child fell to,<br />

anxious to nurture<br />

the little person that lived in its stomach. But it did not take long before it<br />

occurred to the child to wonder why the little stomach man should get hungry.<br />

In preceding parts of this essay I wanted to minister to readers of the dia<br />

logue (including my former self) who feel as cheated by it as was the child by<br />

the grownup's answer.<br />

I tried to show, through a moderately detailed analysis of Socrates'<br />

argument for the soul's immortality and by sketching the counterarguments for<br />

the soul's mortality which his partners in conversation propose, that the reason<br />

ing which culminates in detaching or attaching<br />

first<br />

the predicate mortal from/to the<br />

subject soul (or self or he or Socrates) turns in every instance on claiming that<br />

the soul is like some other thing and that it must, therefore, like that other thing<br />

about which we suppose ourselves to know whether it is mortal or not, be


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 193<br />

mortal or not. This meant, for instance, that Socrates argued against likening<br />

soul to air (which gets dispersed when it leaves its container) and for its being<br />

like a star, which temporarily disappears from sight, but will reappear after a<br />

sufficient interval.<br />

I was at pains to hold on both to the fact that everything said in the dialogue<br />

is in fulfillment of the "assignment"<br />

that Socrates prove that it is better for him<br />

to die than to live (cf. 95c) and to the fact that Socrates is made to interpret this<br />

"better"<br />

as though it were connected with death's not really being what to<br />

bereaved survivors it appears to be, annihilation of the one they love. So the<br />

dialogue looks, to quote a friend, like a "passionate, frighteningly relentless<br />

effort to hammer into the reader's mind a conviction of the soul's immortality"<br />

(cf. 107c).<br />

Yet since the means of establishing this conviction are, with but one excep<br />

tion, the examining of already available images or models for the soul, it seems<br />

to me an allowable refocusing of attention to contend that what the dialogue<br />

much of the time does is look at answers to the question who or what the soul,<br />

or the soul of Socrates, or Socrates himself, is. In saying this I am not trying to<br />

be coquettish or cute: Socrates consistently maintains in other dialogues (cf.<br />

Meno 71, 100) that to establish what predicate belongs to a subject one must<br />

first know precisely what the subject is. In the case at hand, this means that to<br />

establish whether soul is mortal or immortal one must know what it is.<br />

I call the models for the soul, or for its relation to the body, which are<br />

proposed in the Phaedo "already<br />

available"<br />

because the notions that it is a<br />

fallen star, that it is a weaver, that it is a special sort of pneuma (cf. Aristotle's<br />

sumphuton pneuma = quintessence =<br />

ether) resembling but not identical with<br />

fire have come my way in other books, some of them predating Plato or be<br />

longing to traditions distinct from the Hellenic. Many of these images seem to<br />

be folk beliefs. Whether they came to the folk through the poets or whether the<br />

poets simply preserved and elaborated on them we do not (and perhaps cannot)<br />

know.<br />

However, the Phaedo's two middle arguments for the soul's immortality<br />

recollection"<br />

the argument "from<br />

and the argument "from the soul's<br />

kinship<br />

to Platonic forms"<br />

If they involve "models,"<br />

(73a-77c)<br />

(78b-84b) seem to be of a different sort.<br />

it is in some murkier way than so far encountered,<br />

others.5<br />

as is shown by the fact that one cannot draw them as one could draw the<br />

And if these middle arguments the argument from recollection and that<br />

from the simplicity and consequent indissolubility<br />

of the Forms owe a debt to<br />

poets, as seems to be suggested in the Meno (80b) through the reference to<br />

Pindar, the Platonic distance from that poetic source seems to be more impor<br />

tant than the possible fact that there is such a poetic fund from which Plato<br />

drew.<br />

Both of the middle arguments depend, for their meaning as well as their<br />

cogency,<br />

on the thesis that there is a "fine itself,"<br />

a "large itself,"<br />

a "healthy


194 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

itself,"<br />

an "equal itself"<br />

apart from such things as a fine-looking baby, a large<br />

house, a healthy Pausanias, etc. (76e). Therefore, after outlining the two argu<br />

ments according to which the soul must pre-exist the partnership with its pres<br />

ent body and postexist this partnership, I shall dwell at some, though not suffi<br />

cient, length on what Socrates-Plato could conceivably have meant by these<br />

"themselves,"<br />

the Platonic Forms.<br />

There will not, I fear, be a pleasing roundup of the dispersed pieces of the<br />

essay entire at the end. The best I can come up with is an appreciative critique<br />

of what I believe Plato sincerely meant. The heart of this critique is that, while<br />

there is every reason to be grateful to Plato for his discovering the realm of<br />

logic as the realm of rational necessity and for recognizing that it lies "beyond"<br />

sense and beyond passion, there is also reason to try the hypothesis that he may<br />

have misrepresented his own insight.6<br />

What I call the misrepresentation of his own insight is sometimes diagnosed<br />

as consisting in the mistaken notion that "pieces of language,"<br />

to do their job of<br />

pointing beyond themselves,<br />

must one and all be names. I do not think that this<br />

is the happiest description, because (for one thing) it slights Plato's hard-won<br />

discovery (see Sophist) that true and false talk comes in sentences, at least<br />

when you consider how what is said is heard by the listener: The listener<br />

"takes"<br />

what he is "given"<br />

by the speaker as having subject-predicate format,<br />

that is, as both referring and describing. A more nearly just description is, to<br />

my mind, that in spite of what we hear Socrates say in the Phaedo (99d, e ff.)<br />

about doing his own investigating by way of speeches/arguments rather than by<br />

way of direct inspection of things, Plato seems to be unwilling to let knowing<br />

be anything else, ultimately, than a knowing of, acquaintance with, contact (cf.<br />

Meno 71b, Cratylus, Phaedrus, Symposium, Seventh Letter).<br />

And I take the outrageously risky step of wondering whether it was passion<br />

(cf. Hopkins'<br />

"keep / Back beauty") that made him downgrade skill (savoir<br />

faire), and knowledge of matters of fact (savoir) and led him to suppose that<br />

the true goal of inquiry is direct contact with divine forms (connaitre as when<br />

we know a person or a landscape) because it seems to me that the textual<br />

evidence for the dialogue's asceticism being sincere is simply too strong. One<br />

has to do violence to the text to overlook or discount it.<br />

By its being sincere I mean that the Phaedo seems to me to ask of us, as of<br />

Socrates'<br />

companions in jail, that we become resigned to his detachment not<br />

because we accept that Socrates is attached to the Athenian community, for<br />

whom he deems it better if the execution is carried out, nor because he antici<br />

pates an old age that might be full of indignity and pain and expects death by<br />

hemlock to be an easy death, but because there is something finer than any<br />

human thing contact with which waits for Socrates on the nether side of the<br />

horizon.<br />

The moral message of the Phaedo is, I believe, that we ought to cultivate<br />

the superhuman temperance of willingly giving Socrates up to a beloved we


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 195<br />

deem worthier than ourselves, namely, the crystalline purities called Platonic<br />

Forms that supposedly draw him on. To them, not him, we ought ourselves to<br />

become attached (cf. 68a, b).<br />

It is probably fairly obvious that I believe this invitation to asceticism to be<br />

misguided. That is, insofar as the hypothesis that there are Forms "above"<br />

"apart from"<br />

longing for something<br />

and<br />

mortal things (including human speeches) is motivated by the<br />

to know and love that could substitute for mortal things<br />

and that an individual could become intimate with when he concentrates him<br />

self and is no longer bonded to his fellows, I believe it to be a mistake. Yet I<br />

have great sympathy for the feeling and thought that underlie it.<br />

Isn't Einstein speaking of such feelings and thoughts when he writes:<br />

one of the strongest motives that lead men to art and science is flight from<br />

everyday life with its painful harshness and wretched dreariness, and from the<br />

fetters of one's own shifting desires. A person with a finer sensibility is driven to<br />

escape from personal existence and to the world of objective observing (Schauen-<br />

theooreiri) and understanding. This motive can be compared with the longing that<br />

irresistably pulls the town-dweller away from his noisy, cramped quarters and<br />

toward the silent, high mountains, where the eye ranges freely through the still,<br />

pure air and traces the calm contours that seem made for eternity. With this<br />

negative motive there goes a positive one: Man seeks to form for himself ...<br />

a<br />

simplified and lucid image of the world (Bild der Welt), and so to overcome the<br />

world of experience by striving to replace it to some extent by<br />

this image."<br />

(Ideas<br />

and Opinions, [New York: Crown, 1954], pp. 224 f., my italics; cf. Phaedo 79d).<br />

Nor is it only giants of the intellect like Einstein or Plato who know such<br />

feelings. Picture the first-grade classroom where the teacher is checking the<br />

children's arithmetic exercises and she comes to Johnnie's desk and turns to<br />

him, ever so pleased, and says, "Very good, Johnnie."<br />

with great irritation and says, "What do you mean 'very<br />

And he looks at her<br />

good'perfect."<br />

? It's<br />

That child knows that some things are not matters of degree and not true or<br />

right because some human authority declares them to be so!<br />

So if Platonic asceticism is a "mistake,"<br />

it is one of immense importance.<br />

This, indeed, is the prime reason for the writing out of this essay on the<br />

Phaedo.<br />

Well, then, back to the arguments for immortality, in particular, for the pre-<br />

existence of the learning soul.<br />

I understand Cebes'<br />

quotation from the Meno to be to this effect:<br />

1. If studying or learning with the help of a teacher is something<br />

that the<br />

student or learner himself does, not something that is done to him by his<br />

teacher, then studying or learning<br />

is in an important respect no different from<br />

recollection. Recollection is an active seeking for something that one believes<br />

oneself,"<br />

the reason for one's self-confidence being,<br />

in the case of recollection taken literally, that one knows one previously knew<br />

one could lay hold of "by


196 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

the thing not now at hand and one has had experience of fishing for some<br />

submerged thing in the mind and actually catching one's fish. This first inter<br />

pretation of the famous metaphor of Socrates that learning is nothing but recol<br />

lection puts all the emphasis on the polarity active-passive.<br />

To appreciate that one ought to give a good deal of weight to this first<br />

interpretation of Socrates'<br />

to mind two things:<br />

metaphor for learning, it is probably helpful to call<br />

a.)that Platonic dialogues as well as Greek tragedy are continually ruminat<br />

ing about active-passive, doing and being done to.<br />

b.)that Platonic dialogues pay an inordinate amount of attention to matters of<br />

grammar, diction, and syntax,<br />

say "Ptolemy was teaching astronomy<br />

and that it so happens that in Greek you don't<br />

to Syrus,"<br />

with the thing taught the di<br />

rect object and the person taught the indirect object. Rather, both the thing<br />

taught and the person who gets taught are direct objects. This mere accident, if<br />

you like, of the Greek language makes it important for someone like Plato (who<br />

is always scrutinizing how what people think and do is affected by what people<br />

say and vice versa) to pull resolutely the other way, to make a great fuss over<br />

the fact that in a learning situation the recipient is active, is not a mere piece of<br />

wax that gets imprinted by the teacher.<br />

When you put what was just said together with other passages in the dia<br />

logue (98d) you get the result that the teacher is "condition"<br />

only a not a<br />

"cause"<br />

of the student's learning; the "cause"<br />

of the student's learning is his<br />

love of the activity of investigation and/or of the things investigated (cf. Au<br />

gustine's On the Teacher). This first interpretation of Socrates'<br />

metaphor seems<br />

to have no bearing on the question whether the learning soul is mortal or im<br />

"natural"<br />

mortal. Rather, it bears on learning's being a<br />

motion, to use Aristotelian language.<br />

2.)A second interpretation,<br />

rather than a "violent"<br />

which one anticipates might become connected<br />

with the result wanted, namely the pre-existence of the learner's soul, is this:<br />

Any learning is based on prior knowing or prior believing, because to learn<br />

means to seek. And you cannot seek unless your search is oriented to some<br />

thing which to some extent you trust yourself to know already, sufficiently, at<br />

least, to recognize it as "it,"<br />

the very thing you were and are looking for, when<br />

you come upon it.7<br />

Nor can you guess at a riddle unless you at least recognize<br />

it as a riddle. Moreover, there is no way of ruling against a step taken on the<br />

way<br />

to a wouldbe solution to a riddle or the wouldbe conclusion of a search<br />

unless, again, you trust that there are constraints whether "gentle forces that<br />

commonly<br />

prevail"<br />

prohibitions."<br />

or "imperative<br />

These too you must rely on as<br />

though you knew them.<br />

Now what shall we say about the very beginning of learning, guessing,<br />

investigating? And what shall we say about how we came to know these con<br />

straints upon interweavings of subjects and predicates,<br />

another?<br />

or of one sentence with


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 197<br />

It seems as though there are just two alternatives: Either we must deny that<br />

everything that we know we came to know by learning it, or we must deny that<br />

there is an absolute beginning of learning /guessing.<br />

These two hypotheses are not the same. The first will be recognized as<br />

Leibniz's (New Essays bk i ch. 2, pp 52, 78f., 87). It amounts to the claim that<br />

even if it is nearly true that nothing is in the intellect that was not previously in<br />

the senses, still, the intellect itself is "in<br />

there,"<br />

and its activity and structure<br />

are not the result of but the condition for sense experience's leading anywhere<br />

when we investigate.<br />

To someone who, like Socrates in the Phaedo, treats the pigeonholes "sen<br />

sory"- "nonsensory"<br />

as exclusive and exhaustive, and who, moreover, identifies<br />

these two with the pigeonholes "mortal"-"immortal,"<br />

the thesis that some<br />

knowledge is not learned but innate, being constitutive of the intellect, amounts<br />

to the claim that the soul is immortal if by soul we mean the intellect.<br />

Let's look at the second hypothesis. According to it, every<br />

premise is itself a<br />

conclusion, that is, the outcome of some sort of guessing, reasoning, seeking,<br />

and there is no reasoning that doesn't have premises. I am using the word<br />

"reasoning"<br />

in such a way that deductive reasoning is only one variety of rea<br />

soning, so that "reasoning from<br />

called "models,"<br />

rank as reasoning.<br />

Now most of us believe that Socrates'<br />

analogy,"<br />

seeking and finding and using what I<br />

and any man's or woman's life "be<br />

gan"<br />

and, pace right-to-lifers, the going opinion in Athens seems to have been<br />

that a human life begins when the child exits from the womb. But if, because<br />

every premise is itself conclusion, there is no first in the series of learnings or<br />

guessings though one believes that there is a first in the series of drawing life's<br />

breath in the body, and if, further, learning can only be done by souls, doesn't<br />

that prove that the learning that looks like the first learning which a child does<br />

is not really first but relies upon a prior believing or knowing deposited in the<br />

child's soul from a prior phase of that soul's life?<br />

As was said in a previous portion of this essay, Platonic arguments for the<br />

pre- and postexistence of the individual soul often lend themselves to social<br />

interpretations. In Part 1 I tried to sketch how such a social interpretation of the<br />

notion of the soul's postexistence might be understood. I illustrated it by ap<br />

plying what is said in the Republic's myth of Er about the man whose decency<br />

is solely a matter of habit, unenlightened by reflection, to the grandchildren of<br />

Cephalus. At present I am talking about the portion of the Phaedo that goes<br />

into the soul's pre-existence. A social interpretation of this notion would, for<br />

instance, go like this: Any<br />

human being's investigating, studying, guessing<br />

relies on pre-existent knowledge and opinion in the community within which<br />

the person who is doing the investigating<br />

was raised and of which he is a<br />

member. But I hope you agree with me that it is really extremely puzzling how<br />

an individual, in particular a child, gains access to this communal fund. It<br />

seems to be in some ways quite strictly true that the child must itself actively


198 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

guess at the contents of the communal fund of knowledge (human beings learn<br />

to speak, but not by being taught); and it also seems likely<br />

that the child's<br />

guessing is genuine guessing, has intelligence in it, is not purely chance, there<br />

fore has something like premises and/or knows constraints. So although what I<br />

called the "social"<br />

interpretation of the argument from recollection is tempting,<br />

I do not believe it to be strictly true, either to the facts of human learning or to<br />

the dialogue. It is not faithful to the dialogue because, for one thing, it fails to<br />

pay attention to the prominence given to mathematical inquiry in the passages<br />

explaining Socrates'<br />

metaphor that learning is nothing but recollection.<br />

Way back I proposed that perhaps recollection is thinking and vice versa.<br />

This suggestion was based on analysis of the two rather different speeches<br />

about recollection given by Cebes and by Socrates and on the observation that<br />

what Socrates says about recollection brings to the foreground how very diverse<br />

the linkages between what is "present to the<br />

vicariously "made<br />

present"<br />

or "recalled"<br />

mind"<br />

and what is "absent"<br />

but<br />

are. And I remarked on how curious<br />

the mix of voluntary and involuntary, active and passive is if you take Socrates'<br />

and Cebes's two speeches together.<br />

Yet in urging this very broad interpretation of Socrates'<br />

metaphor that learn<br />

ing, studying, investigating is recollection, I slighted the fact that the favored<br />

examples of recollection given in the Phaedo and Meno are examples of mathe<br />

matical thinking.<br />

Any<br />

adequate account of the import of this fact would have to go into both<br />

the finding of demonstrations for mathematical truths and the demonstrating of<br />

mathematical truths. Nor would this be sufficient; one would also have to go<br />

into the finding of mathematical truths that might be understood to be explana<br />

tory of phenomena. I reserve an exploration of this topic for another occasion.<br />

In the context of the present essay I merely note that one effect of selecting<br />

mathematical thinking from the whole of thought is that the kind of thinking<br />

which characteristically encounters logical musts and cannots is, so to say,<br />

identified as nonmortal be<br />

shoved to the foreground. Thereby what is already<br />

cause it is nonsensory (viz. thinking) is moved still closer to the Divine by<br />

giving us experience of "<br />

inexorability (cf. Iliad and the will of Zeus was<br />

accomplished," Parmenides'<br />

poem On Truth, Fr. 8, 1. 32, Republic passages<br />

on noncontradiction at iv 436b-40 and x 602d ff., Sophist 230b).<br />

Just one more step is needed, which is taken in the argument for the soul's<br />

immortality that I dubbed "the argument from the soul's kinship<br />

with the<br />

Forms"<br />

(78d ff. [p. 273 Loeb]). This last step is that knowing is a becoming<br />

assimilated to becoming like that which is known.<br />

Were this assumption true, and were it shown that all scientific investiga<br />

tion, perhaps all investigation scientific or not, depends on the soul's knowing<br />

because foreknowing and recollecting Forms, and were it established that these<br />

Forms are immortal (because "simple"<br />

tality<br />

and thus indissoluble), then the immor<br />

of the soul insofar as this soul was, is, comes to be "in touch<br />

with"<br />

Forms


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 199<br />

might be said to have been demonstrated. To the Forms we must, therefore,<br />

turn, or rather, to passages in the Phaedo, and a few other places, about Forms.<br />

These are: 65, 74-77, 78b-84, 92a-bff., 100 a f., 103e.<br />

The questions I shall pay a little attention to are: (a)Of what are there<br />

Forms? (b)What are Forms?(c)Why suppose that there are Forms?<br />

My answers, to state them baldly in a preliminary way,<br />

are these: (a)There<br />

are Forms (in the sense of eide chooristaf of qualities that are inherently rela<br />

tional. (b)The Forms are the relationships, I mean the somethings to which we<br />

in English tend to refer by what are called abstract nouns equality, justice,<br />

beauty, magnitude, health. (c)It is irresistibly plausible to suppose that there are<br />

Forms if one takes words to be names for their senses (logical depths) and<br />

up"<br />

"refer"<br />

holds that names, to do their job of "calling the named, must and<br />

indeed must refer to some one thing if the name is not to be ambiguous. And<br />

even if one has a more complicated theory of discourse than this, something<br />

like a theory of Forms would still be plausible. What is not plausible, to me at<br />

least, is the rank that is given to the Forms, by Plato, but not only by Plato.<br />

Let me now try<br />

What is it about<br />

to explain and furnish textual evidence for these answers.<br />

"just," "fine," "good," "large," "healthy," "strong"<br />

Socrates should single them out from among other qualities and claim that they<br />

must be "in and of themselves,"<br />

beyond just men or cities,<br />

that<br />

apart from fine<br />

horses or young women, healthy men and children, strong carts and boxers?<br />

Since roughly the same set of examples occurs repeatedly, in the Phaedo<br />

(65d, e), in the Republic (479), in the Meno (72d), in the Parmenides (131a),<br />

we must ask why Socrates seems to believe that something is left out, over<br />

looked, were it said that the enumerated words or names (onomata) are mean<br />

ingful in that they name such beings (onto) as healthy Pausanias, strong Cal<br />

lias, and so on, or, if you like, the particular health, strength, beauty etc. that<br />

are in these men.<br />

In calling attention to the fact that certain adjectives (in neuter singular)<br />

recur whenever Socrates touches on the theme of eide choorista (Platonic, that<br />

is, independent, Forms), I am quarreling with one fairly standard answer to the<br />

question what such Forms are: If they were "universals,"<br />

any and all<br />

as Aristo<br />

tle sometimes leads us to believe (see e.g. Metaphysics xiii 1078b33), nouns as<br />

well as adjectives should figure in the list.<br />

Aren't "man"<br />

and<br />

"animal"<br />

and "fire"<br />

and "snow"<br />

just as "predicable of<br />

many"<br />

as are "just"<br />

and "beautiful"? Why, then, are they not parade instances<br />

of independent Forms?<br />

The Parmenides puts the question whether for kind-words like<br />

"horse"<br />

and mass-words such as "gold"<br />

or "fire"<br />

or<br />

"wood"<br />

"man"<br />

or<br />

to be meaningful<br />

one must suppose that there is a prototypical "man himself,"<br />

"fire itself,"<br />

ter itself"<br />

"wa<br />

(Cf. Philebus 15b and Timaeus 49, 51b, 30). Most readers of the<br />

dialogue believe that the answer is in the affirmative. They base this conclusion<br />

largely on the fact that Socrates is in this dialogue portrayed ( 1 30c) as rejecting


200 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

such an expansion of the domain of Forms only because he is embarrassed at<br />

the thought that the same reasoning that generates a "water itself"<br />

generate a<br />

"hair," "mud," "dirt"<br />

per se. Parmenides diagnoses Socrates'<br />

would also<br />

intel<br />

lectual condition as one of youthful excessive respect for high-low distinctions.<br />

This seems to imply that the young Socrates'<br />

they<br />

are spoken of "mean and worthless things"<br />

that are, so to say, too base to be "called<br />

them,"<br />

is mere prejudice.<br />

I am, however, struck by<br />

the fact that Socrates'<br />

exclamation As we see them, so<br />

like hair and mud, things<br />

after"<br />

any totemic ancestor "beyond<br />

exclamation is virtually a<br />

quotation of the famous passage about fingers in the Republic (523). According<br />

to these texts, men and fingers and sticks and stones directly "deserve"<br />

names. (See also Alcibiades I, st. 111c.) Their to ti en einai is "in"<br />

them.<br />

their<br />

The conclusion I draw from the facts just enumerated is that according to the<br />

words"<br />

do not call for Forms which exist apart<br />

majority of the dialogues, "thing<br />

from the things that illustrate them. (I leave unsettled whether they ought to be<br />

called "early"<br />

and "middle"<br />

aeus as "late.")<br />

If, however,<br />

over against the Parmenides and Philebus and Tim<br />

adjectival character alone sufficed for Socrates to believe that<br />

there must be a Form as a sort of "patron"<br />

after whom all the things bearing the<br />

adjective as a patronymic are called, there ought to be a Form "the hot itself"<br />

ancestral to all hot things. But "the hot itself"<br />

tions as an "eponym"<br />

employed) "shared<br />

out"<br />

(see Parmenides 131a,<br />

among participating hot things.<br />

nowhere to my knowledge func<br />

where that word and notion are<br />

Is it, then, because the enumerated adjectives name good things,<br />

objects of<br />

desire, that they are treated as somehow special? Perhaps, but whatever one<br />

makes of the telic or luring<br />

character of the qualities for which Socrates claims<br />

that there are separate Forms, one must tell a story that takes into account that<br />

equal is the Platonic Form most elaborately dealt with in the Phaedo9<br />

and that<br />

the idea of equality (and inequality) is at least as much "foundational"<br />

supposedly "value-neutral", desire-muting<br />

for the<br />

mathematical sciences as for poli<br />

tics: Euclid's Common Notions have just one theme equality<br />

traries, greater than, less than.<br />

and its con<br />

I could imagine that Gestalt psychologists and phenomenologists would pro<br />

pose that we think of Platonic Forms as the "limits"<br />

to some process of "ideal<br />

ization"<br />

(whether postulated or acknowledged) which realizes, recognizes, that<br />

the cognitive and moral and aesthetic demand (need, or even lust, that is, eros)<br />

is for perfection perfect justice, perfect health, perfect equality, perfect any<br />

of the things about which Socrates asks "What is it?"<br />

although, or rather,<br />

because what the world supplies never quite comes through by fully meeting<br />

the standards of the given desire (cf. Phaedo 74d, e).<br />

I would accept their proposal, though I would add the rider that the aspira<br />

tion toward perfection might be a demand for incomplexity that deserves tam<br />

ing: I've always liked Whitehead's reminder, "seek simplicity, and distrust it."


I would further add that the Gestalt<br />

circle itself"<br />

Some Observations About Plato'<br />

s Phaedo 201<br />

theorists'<br />

perfect geometric shapes ("the<br />

or "the square itself") do not figure in any of the Socratic lists of<br />

independent Forms that I have cited.<br />

So far my claim is that being a normative adjective/attribute (I mean, being<br />

an adjective the sense of which involves the thought that there are standards to<br />

live up to, as in the case of<br />

"healthy," "beautiful," "good."<br />

Cf. Euthyphro 5e,<br />

7; Phaedrus 263; Laches 192) may, on Platonic principles, be a necessary<br />

condition for implicit reference to a Platonic Form. It is not a sufficient condi<br />

tion.<br />

Just one way of making sense of the examples that Socrates gives and does<br />

not give occurs to me: There are Platonic Forms for those qualities that belong<br />

to things only insofar as they are ranged under a condition or in so far as they<br />

are vis-a-vis some correlative and/or in some context. What Plato discovered is,<br />

I believe, the reality of relations and their primacy in mathematics and politics.<br />

By "reality"<br />

I mean, not figments that depend on some individual's having<br />

originated them, as one might say Hamlet was originated by Shakespeare or a<br />

dream by its dreamer. By their primacy I mean that right reasoning and percep<br />

tion is due to recognizing this relational character and wrong reasoning and<br />

perception is chiefly due to failing to recognize it.<br />

But I mean more than this. Plato recognized something about relativity that<br />

bears on our entire emotional and intellectual nature. I call it our "gappiness"<br />

(Ungesdttigtkeit). Plato is ever talking about this: for instance, in Republic ii<br />

(369b), Socrates identifies the origin of cities as individual neediness and lack<br />

of self-sufficiency. In the Symposium (202b), the nondivinity of love is said to<br />

be entailed by the very meaning<br />

of the words to be divine is to be self-<br />

sufficient. But love's greed proves that it is not and has not what it longs for.<br />

This dependency of love on what it is of marks its nature through and through.<br />

Not only is love relative rather than absolute, it is multiply relative according to<br />

Diotima ou tou kalou ho eroos alia tes genneseoos kai tou tokou en tool<br />

kalooi (206e). Knowledge too is inherently relative, and in several respects,<br />

being of the known, of the one who knows, and of or among other knowledges.<br />

The Theaetetus makes quite a point of this relativity.<br />

Once the notion that Plato is interested in studying relativity and its kinds<br />

has entered on the scene, one no longer stumbles over previously weird pas<br />

sages, like the long stretch in Republic i where Socrates seems to be pestering<br />

Polemarchus with the question how to fill in the gaps in the formulas "justice is<br />

the craft of giving to<br />

"<br />

It would not be difficult to show how each and every Platonic dialogue is<br />

"of"<br />

about one or another kind of being relative: Speech is or "about"<br />

as well<br />

as "to"<br />

and<br />

"from."<br />

(cf. Sophist 244, 263c). So are knowledge, rule, part,<br />

whole, always of something else that is in the possessive or some other oblique<br />

case.<br />

The men who do the speaking, teaching, loving, ruling may think that they,


202 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

who are in the naming case, active rather than passive, giving<br />

ceiving, rather commanding than obeying, are<br />

rather than re<br />

"substantial"<br />

and "independent,"<br />

whereas the crowd which they address, the pupils whom they teach, the slaves<br />

whom command are they insubstantial and dependent. Yet for the performance<br />

of any of these imposing roles they depend on what they deem beneath them.<br />

I believe that one of the reasons for Plato's never quite losing his charm is<br />

the depth he gave to this insight.<br />

Is there then no one and nothing absolute, self-determined, self-sufficient?<br />

Platonic Forms, like the divine Nous of Aristotle's Metaphysics book<br />

Lambda, are, I think, meant to be the absolutes to which mortal things are<br />

relative but which are not in turn relative to these mortal things. They are, to<br />

use T.S. Eliot's word, the "objective<br />

correlatives"<br />

for the human longing to<br />

stoop before what by its very indifference to adoration shows itself worthy of<br />

worship.<br />

To savor the strangeness of this thought that the longing for absolutes is, if I<br />

understand the project, to be satisfied by<br />

relationships themselves, not things<br />

that are related, I turn now to the topic of equality and try to show how "just,"<br />

"healthy,"<br />

"strong," "excellent."<br />

(I mean the qualities on what I called the<br />

recurrent list of Form-demanding names) might, from a certain point of view,<br />

be deemed to have a logical structure analogous to that of the seemingly un<br />

problematic because value-free qualities<br />

"large," "equal."<br />

Clearly, the quality of being equal belongs to a thing only<br />

insofar as it is<br />

relative to another, of which it is an equal. Observe, though this is not pointed<br />

out by the dialogue, that the other thing<br />

whose equal this stone is need not be a<br />

stone but may be a stick. Notice, too, that although Socrates here, and in many<br />

another dialogue, remarks on our getting into intellectual muddles because we<br />

speak (and perhaps even think and feel) inarticulately, fail to notice or to say<br />

that "this stone is both equal and<br />

unequal"<br />

relative to that stick on the one<br />

hand, this other stone on the other, we are, even after becoming explicit to this<br />

degree, still speaking elliptically. This stone can obviously be one and the same<br />

stick's equal and unequal its equal in length but its unequal in weight.<br />

The (in Greek) inherently oblique-case-needing<br />

stick-or-stone,<br />

character of being-an-equal-<br />

and the multiply-relative character of being-an-equal-stick-or-<br />

stone may not seem worth belaboring. But you will, I imagine, agree with me<br />

that these logical truths become more than a little interesting in moral or politi<br />

cal context. (Cf. Aristotle's treatment of claims to equality and inequality in the<br />

Politics, also 97c on "best for each and best for all").<br />

But how do these observations concerning relativity bear on such qualities as<br />

health or strength (or justice, excellence,<br />

and beauty)?<br />

The Meno gives, or at least suggests, an answer. But, since it is an answer<br />

supplied by Meno, who has a bad reputation, many<br />

what he says.<br />

readers do not appreciate<br />

Wouldn't it, from a Greek physician's point of view, be true that the health


Some Observations About Plato'<br />

s Phaedo 203<br />

of an old man is different from that of a man at mid-career in that, say, the<br />

androgen level of the one is healthy for him but, should the other have the<br />

numerically<br />

same androgen level, some sort of imbalance or unhealthiness<br />

would exist in him? And do we really want to say that the same degree of<br />

muscular strength in a man and a woman is required for us to call either of<br />

them strong? Or that we expect a boy of six who is spoken of as tall to be the<br />

same height as a tall teenager? And are we entirely confident that Socrates<br />

would and should reject Meno's notion that a woman's way of being excellent<br />

is different from a man's?<br />

Meno is not simply wrong in speaking of excellence as relative to station in<br />

life, and the same holds, according to my argument, for the other qualities<br />

mentioned. Throughout, inexplicitness about the condition under which the<br />

quality that is spoken of belongs to what it qualifies tends to generate misap<br />

prehension and misreasoning. In this respect equal, healthy, tall, strong, splen<br />

did, just, and good are alike. For example, it seems abhorrent that for vultures<br />

to feed on the corpses of heroes is both right and wrong,<br />

until one makes<br />

explicit whether the corpses are Persian or Hellenic. Well and good. But So<br />

crates finds fault with Meno's answer. So far I have said nothing about why.<br />

Compare with Meno's litany about virtue (71e f.) this statement of my own<br />

invention about what being equal is:<br />

"There are many kinds of equality, as of weight, or of length, or of speed,<br />

or of volume. A balance will prove things equal weight. A stopwatch will help<br />

show their equal speed. Perfect coverage by each of each will show their equal<br />

length. Pouring the liquid that fills one container into another and finding that<br />

there is no overflow will establish that the two containers are of equal<br />

Would we not side with Socrates in feeling that although everything that was<br />

said is true and relevant and perhaps even indispensable, (cf. the indispensable<br />

and nevertheless "rejected"<br />

examples of knowhow and science at the opening<br />

of the Theaetetus), the tenor of our question is not being appreciated. We<br />

wanted to reach greater clarity about how all these different ways of being<br />

equal are ways of being equal.<br />

When Aristotle, in the Physics, defines motion as "the actuality of the po<br />

tential qua<br />

potential" whole,"<br />

he is defining "motion as a because he is saying<br />

something about how the different species of motion (viz. in respect of place,<br />

in respect of size, in respect of quality) are akin. Thus he is giving the type of<br />

answer Socrates is ever seeking. He is defining the genus.<br />

In the Meno, Socrates himself illustrates in what spirit he would like Meno<br />

to consider excellence by answering<br />

the "what-is-it?"<br />

question about shape.<br />

Being a rectilinear and being a curvilinear figure are, for Socrates, in some<br />

manner<br />

"opposite."<br />

Nevertheless he comes up with an answer to the question<br />

how being circular and being triangular both are ways of being<br />

volum<br />

figures (cf.<br />

Aristotle, De Anima ii 414b-415a end; see also Charmides and Theaetetus).<br />

What motivates this Socratic hunt for the generic? How is it connected with


204 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

the postulating of Forms apart from the above the things "called<br />

after"<br />

the<br />

Forms? And what became of my claim that Forms are, or are primarily, patrons<br />

of relativity?<br />

The example from the Meno just given,<br />

which shows how the genus figure<br />

manages to hold the round's and the straight's conflicting ways of being figures<br />

together,<br />

gives us a clue:<br />

Intellectual ascent to the genus is frequently a way of rising above mutually<br />

antagonistic ways of being and seeing their togetherness, their forming a<br />

"community"<br />

a (koinonia)<br />

A homely way of illustrating<br />

whole,<br />

many of us about Nixon's "enemy list."<br />

under the generic totem.<br />

what I mean is to meditate on what troubled<br />

When we heard that this was the label<br />

used by the Committee for the Re-Election of the President, many of us felt<br />

that Nixon and his camp had thereby become scoundrels (panourgoi), because<br />

they were denying that American political parties, even if they contend against<br />

each other, are parties of the American people, that there is a genus that holds<br />

together the different ways of being American citizens. As this example shows,<br />

reminding conflicting social or political parties that and how they<br />

"akin"<br />

are also<br />

or of one genus (sungenos) can be of great practical importance, that is,<br />

make a difference in deliberations steering toward action.<br />

For me the most vivid instance of what I am talking about is the speech<br />

whereby the brothers of Joseph, in the concluding chapter of the book of Gene<br />

sis (50:16-21), seek to move Joseph to mildness towards them. They say:<br />

"Your father said before his death, forgive the servants of the God of your<br />

father."<br />

It is the indirectness of that speech's rationale for reconciliation to<br />

which I am calling your attention. The indirectness betokens that only insofar<br />

as there is something that is regarded as to theion, divine, inasmuch as it is of a<br />

kind to rule and hold sway whereas the rival mortals all are to be ruled and to<br />

serve, can mortal rivalry<br />

be stilled (Phaedo 80a).<br />

But not every ascent to (recollecting of?) the genus that contains diverse and<br />

even rival species has such practical effects for the community. Sometimes all<br />

that is gained is peace of mind for an individual. Thus it appears to me that<br />

people who skip the earlier sections of the Phaedo because they don't like to be<br />

counted among the "vulgar"<br />

overlook the fact that the Phaedo acknowledges<br />

"animated"<br />

the different and apparently competing ways of being<br />

(empsuchon)<br />

by desire for goods that are of diverse species (cf. Aristotle, Nichomachaean<br />

Ethics i.6), yet of one genus in being good.<br />

To recognize that, as Pythagoras put it, life or at least human life is like a<br />

festival, where some go to sell, some to win honor by proving<br />

through their<br />

victory that they outrank their rivals, and some just to watch the game, the<br />

sellers, and the watchers, is to be on the way to becoming reconciled to the fact<br />

that each way of life claims that it is the true way, and in trying to win adher<br />

ents to itself will come into conflict with the others. My brief and perhaps<br />

slightly unusual way of expressing this recognition is to say<br />

cies of human life as species of one genus.<br />

one sees the spe


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 205<br />

Sometimes, however, and here the so-to-say privileged status of the Form<br />

equality comes to the fore, ascent to the genus gives immense theoretical satis<br />

faction.<br />

Euclid's Elements postdate the Platonic dialogues, but 1 imagine that the<br />

idea of recognizing truths about equality-inequality as "common<br />

to"<br />

the sci<br />

ences arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, music, and whatever predecessor of<br />

Archimedes'<br />

science of weight probably existed was already on the scene<br />

when Plato wrote his dialogues.<br />

truth?<br />

To what are the Common Notions true? How do we come to know their<br />

The Socrates of the Phaedo answers: We learned them via mortal and per<br />

ceptible things that happened to be equal to one another in this or that respect.<br />

But the sign of our only being reminded of "the equal itself"<br />

instead of being<br />

things from which we learned<br />

directly informed by these things is that the very<br />

about being equal are (a)only approximately equal and (b)only<br />

equals as re<br />

garded in terms of one rather than another of their attributes, and (c)deserve the<br />

name only vis-a-vis a correlative.<br />

The truths that Euclid collects under the heading Common Notions outrank<br />

other truths in that they are Common to all the sciences, rendering arithmetic,<br />

plane and solid geometry, astronomy, the science of weights, music theory, as<br />

well as the subject matters of these several sciences, akin (sungenos). More<br />

over, the demonstrative power of these diverse species of science seems in<br />

large measure to hinge on the Common Notions.<br />

Now whereas when I tried to illustrate the idea of genus earlier through<br />

political and social examples, the diverse species that belonged to the genus<br />

were "contained in"<br />

their genus, it is my best guess that according to the Pha<br />

edo the genus of equal things to which Euclid's Common Notions are strictly<br />

applicable are not equal sticks or stones or equal heard musical intervals or<br />

equal observed angles made by heavenly bodies. Rather, these common notions<br />

hold strictly true of equals that are purely and perfectly and without qualifica<br />

tion what their name proclaims them as.<br />

And beyond them, higher yet than "the there is the source<br />

above"<br />

the<br />

of mutual equals mutuality. having This One is the Form "apart and<br />

things called after it, whence mutual equals have their mutuality, their broth-<br />

erliness. It outranks the terms related even when these terms are "perfect"<br />

the way that "mathematicals"<br />

To "the equal<br />

ultimately "look"<br />

itself"<br />

are. It is the relationship equality.<br />

in this sense of the word Socrates would say that we<br />

when we pronounce such truths as that equality is transitive<br />

and symmetrical. To this same Form the things here on earth (and even those<br />

over the earth that can be seen with the body's eyes) that are yoked together as<br />

each other's equals<br />

"look"<br />

when they<br />

"inferior"<br />

short"<br />

and remain (Phaedo 74d).<br />

aspire to be true to their name but "fall<br />

Let what's been said be my tentative answer to the three questions I prom<br />

ised to take up:<br />

in


206 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

1 . Of<br />

what are there forms? Of relational qualities such as figure in the<br />

mathematical sciences but also in politics and morals.<br />

2. What are the forms? They<br />

"fathers"<br />

are the or "patrons"<br />

of the innumer<br />

able couples, triples, quadruples, bonded to each other by the relation they bear<br />

toward each other.<br />

3. Why suppose that there are forms? Because the relation-words,<br />

which are<br />

the very words on which much of our reasoning turns, are meaningful, and<br />

their meaningfulness cannot be explained by treating them as the names of the<br />

things that are "towards"<br />

each other by virtue of their relation, not even if one<br />

takes these things in groups, small or large. The word, if name it is, is primar<br />

ily name of what it signifies, secondarily<br />

of what it denotes.<br />

Now this entire excursion into the region of the Platonic Forms was for the<br />

sake of meeting our obligation to appraise Socrates'<br />

self-defense before his<br />

friends. And that self-defense was given the form of attempts to demonstrate<br />

the soul's immortality.<br />

We must, therefore, return to the question whether, when toward the end of<br />

the dialogue his friends see Socrates'<br />

corpse stretched out and Crito has closed<br />

its mouth and eyes, these friends would rightly hope that Socrates now associ<br />

ates with beings better than themselves, namely, the Platonic Forms.<br />

My<br />

own belief is that the answer is "no."<br />

somewhat succeeded in conveying that if one says<br />

I hope, however, that I have<br />

"no,"<br />

if one contends that<br />

Socrates has not established that it is better for him to die because at death his<br />

true self will become disencumbered of "accretions"<br />

and will gain full intimacy<br />

with associates long divined, one has to think rather carefully about everything<br />

over and under the sun.<br />

One of the things one learns from Platonic dialogues is that one should try to<br />

find out what follows from denying an assumption.<br />

arguments"<br />

If the "middle<br />

have not succeeded,10<br />

then I can see only three<br />

ways in which Socrates's drinking of the hemlock is "doing<br />

good for him. Two of these you will probably not like.<br />

1 .<br />

Socrates<br />

what he a<br />

is using the verdict of the Athenians as a permissible mode of<br />

suicide, anticipating a troubled old age (cf. Memorabilia IV. viii, Loeb ed.<br />

p.352).<br />

2. Socrates is "making a name for himself,"<br />

shaping how future generations<br />

will remember him, by dying for Athens and philosophy. Despite the fact that<br />

Socrates is made to speak of other heroes in some such way as this in the<br />

Symposium, and in spite of the fact that the passion for fame plays so immense<br />

a role in human life, I have some difficulty ascribing this motive to Socrates<br />

because he is so profoundly aware of how the passion for fame makes one<br />

dependent on those who bestow fame. And I was under the impression that the<br />

Einstein passage, which towards the end speaks of substituting the intellectual<br />

for the lived world, shows that becoming independent of one's fellow human<br />

beings is one of the prime motives of the man whom Plato portrays in the guise


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 207<br />

of Socrates (cf. Epistle ii 314c, legomena sookratous .<br />

gegotos).<br />

. kalou<br />

kai neou<br />

3. Socrates judges that the good of Athens is his good and regards the exe<br />

cution of a procedurally correct judicial verdict as a public good.<br />

If you opt for this last way, that seems to show that what a thing, or at least<br />

a human being, or at least certain human beings are is a matter of relations. It<br />

may, were there but argument enough and time,<br />

from facts of being related.<br />

NOTES<br />

show that relationships derive<br />

1. Apologeomai is the correlative of kateegoroo (Liddell and Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon<br />

[Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968], p. 207). At Phaedo 63e the latter is the expression Socrates uses<br />

when, with a ("him,''<br />

reminding contrast between the city's representative viz. the jailer) and his<br />

own little band of friends, he says, "Never mind about him. To you, who are now my judges, I<br />

want to explain (logon apodounai) why a man is of good courage when he is to die if he has<br />

spent his life genuinely in<br />

philosophy."<br />

The Meno's logon didonai is likewise a political expres<br />

sion logon didonai is what a magistrate does at the conclusion of his term of office.<br />

2. Aristotle, On Memory and Recollection, ch. 2, especially 453a7, where these are expressly<br />

distinguished, recollection being a kind of searching; cf. also Nichomachean Ethics 1 1 12b20.<br />

3. A reader to whom I showed a draft of this essay considered my use of the word "deliberate-<br />

ness"<br />

in connection with nous grossly misleading. The issue is too important for this essay (which<br />

is, after all, primarily intent on gaining some clarity about relations between thought and desire, not<br />

to repond to his query. But it is too large really to tackle. So I compromise with a note.<br />

Disregard for the moment passages in the Republic which contrast dianoia with noesis. Disre<br />

gard also what Aristotle says in Metaphysics Lambda. Nous is, after all, not an invention of<br />

philosophers.<br />

To judge by the entries from Herodotus, Homer, Xenophon, Platonic dialogues and Aristotelian<br />

writings more broadly that are recorded by Liddell-Scott, the range of meaning stretches over<br />

houtos ho noos tou rematos ("this is the sense of the word"), pros ton auton noun ("to the same<br />

effect"), en noun echein plus future infinitive ("to intend"), poiein ti epi noon tini ("to put into<br />

someone's mind to do"), agathooi nooi ("kindly"), ek pantos noou ("with all his soul/heart/mind").<br />

A survey of these entries leads me to believe that neither the contrast between heart and head<br />

nor that between will and understanding is in or associated with the word nous. As far as I can see,<br />

the overall sense of the root is something like "paying<br />

yourself is attentive? Eye of the soul or of the body, head,<br />

attention,''<br />

with the question "What part of<br />

or heart?"<br />

left unasked. The questions<br />

"Why are you paying attention? Do you mean to do something as a result of what you've noticed?<br />

Or do you mean to demonstrate something? Or are you just absorbed in what you are attending<br />

have not come on the scene.<br />

Consider now the passage in the Phaedo on which I drew when I characterized Socrates (97c<br />

ff. ), Socrates says that when he heard that it is nous which diakosmoon te kai pantoon aitios ("nous<br />

is what arranges and is responsible for all things"), this seemed somehow right to him. He imme<br />

diately adds: "If this is so, the mind in arranging things arranges everything (panta) and each thing<br />

In a sentence a little later, this emphasis on "best for each and<br />

(hekaston) in such a way as is best."<br />

best for<br />

Purely<br />

all"<br />

is reiterated. That is, Socrates never talks about a nonarranging nous!<br />

contemplative nous, as in Metaphysics Lambda, is never given entry. Rather, it looks as<br />

though the later passage, where Socrates speaks of what seemed best to the Athenians and what<br />

seemed best to him, is already being prepared for. Thus I take Socrates to be talking about reasons<br />

for action rather than causes of events and as maintaining that when someone does something, or<br />

does everything<br />

to?"<br />

nooi he does what he does out of/from a/because of a regard for what is the best of


208 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

each (including himself) and for all (including his family, and the city, and the little band repre<br />

sented by those with him in prison on his last day).<br />

I have a very hard time distinguishing "doing something deliberately"<br />

from doing it after and as<br />

a result of attending to the good of each and all. Doesn't deliberation (even about how the various<br />

pieces of a lock fit together) consist in trying to figure out what, under the given circumstances, is<br />

fit for each and for all?<br />

I certainly agree that people other than Socrates get distracted from the outcome of their deliber<br />

ations (what they "saw<br />

clearly"<br />

when they were so lucky as to reach clarity), don't keep their eye<br />

on the ball (viz. the good of each and all). So if I am to make sense of the fact that Socrates is not<br />

like other people, I shall have to listen to those who say, "Ah, but there is many a slip between the<br />

cup of seeing clearly and the lip of saw."<br />

doing in accord with what you I therefore appreciate what<br />

as mediating between "insight"<br />

and<br />

tempts people to postulate "will"<br />

my own tendency<br />

"action.'<br />

But I confess that<br />

is to work rather with the idea of concentration (see 83a and 80e-end on ath-<br />

roizesthai), substituting it for will, or identifying the two. Consequently<br />

I often wonder in the most<br />

literal-minded way about Meno's opening question, because it seems as though human excellence<br />

consists so largely in this ability to concentrate, which seems to be helped along by<br />

regimen and<br />

education, but nevertheless seems very much to be a matter of talent or grace. Examining Aristo<br />

tle's Nicomachean Ethics vii would greatly help to clarify the issue.<br />

4. Allow me to outline what I would want to say under headings (1) and (3). Audible speech<br />

reminds. How does it manage to do so? Many readers of Plato answer, by prompting the hearer to<br />

turn his or her mind to the eide "referred<br />

to"<br />

or "partaken<br />

of"<br />

by the individual words he hears<br />

spoken. On this interpretation of what speaking is and of what Plato's Socrates means by eide,<br />

"significance."<br />

there ought to be an eidos for every significant word, the eidos being this I hold that<br />

such a theory of language, one which refuses to make do with an account of words as substitutes<br />

for things and insists, instead, that words have logical depth as well as breadth, Sinn as well as<br />

Bedeutung, intension as well as extension, is more nearly like the truth than most of its rivals. I<br />

even believe that it was Plato to whom we, in some complicated way, owe it. But, as will be<br />

argued below, the evidence of the dialogues is against this general identification of eide with<br />

logical depths. For the expression "logical depth,"<br />

see C.S. Peirce, Collected Papers, Vol.2, ch. 5.<br />

To fasten on writing and urge that reflection on its astounding powers is among the Phaedo's<br />

themes might seem merely modish. Yet consider, the Phaedo, more even than the rest of the<br />

dialogues, is a memorial to Socrates. Obviously the marks on wax or papyrus bear no resemblance<br />

to Socrates. They are letters not drawings. The only respects in which they seem to be like Socrates<br />

is that they are visible (have shape and perhaps color) and mean something (albeit only to those<br />

who have learned to read). So, except for being corporeal snub-<br />

they utterly fail to resemble the<br />

nosed man whom Phaedo and his companions deemed wisest, most just, and altogether best of the<br />

men in their acquaintance. Nevertheless, uncannily, they call Socrates to mind, who would other<br />

on."<br />

wise be forgotten, since "for long he has not been seen nor been meditated<br />

Now the entire corpus of Platonic dialogue is overrun with remarks about or references to<br />

written marks, grammata Hippias Major 285, Republic 11.368, Phaedrus 244, 274, Statesman<br />

277e, Theaetetus 202, Protagoras 312, 326, Cratylus 423-34, Philebus 17 ff. Sophist 253. True,<br />

letters and the learning or using of letters are frequently used as examples of something else, looked<br />

through rather than at. But it is hard to deny that Plato has mind."<br />

writing "on his<br />

Grammata are not mentioned or spoken of in the Phaedo. Diagrams, however, are. And in<br />

Socrates'<br />

speech to Simmias at 73c, the sentence about a drawn horse or lyre, in Greek gegram-<br />

menon, is bound to remind of a written horse or man.<br />

The word "diagram'<br />

is in the dialogue's text<br />

"When you lead people to diagrams or something of that sort it becomes particularly<br />

says Cebes in the speech to Simmias which intends to explain in what way learning or studying is<br />

recollection.<br />

The thing is not. There are no pictures or diagrams in the divided-line section of the Republic or the<br />

double-square section of the Meno either. Moreover, to judge by Sophist 240a, professors of math<br />

ematics like Apollonius may have left the supplying of illustrative diagrams to the reader himself.


Some Observations About Plato's Phaedo 209<br />

Now one way of vividly experiencing the potency of writing is to stop and think about the fact<br />

that letters, merely conventional and otherwise arbitrary scratches, though they are not diagrams,<br />

yield diagrams, if the reader cooperates with the text by executing the required "setting<br />

dean ekthesis) of the author's enunciation.<br />

The Euclidean pattern of a reader's coming to assent to an author's "I<br />

drawing<br />

"cases"<br />

out"<br />

(Eucli<br />

say"<br />

declarations by<br />

which meet the author's general specifications, inspecting and experimenting on<br />

them, and finding that the particular cases which the reader was at liberty to conjure up bear out the<br />

author's claim is particularly clear and vivid.<br />

But mustn't we always do something like this when we read? Don't we otherwise merely mouth<br />

the words like an actor reading a script? (Cf. Aristotle Metaphvsics xiii 1087al7 and Nicomachean<br />

Ethics vii 1047a20 f.)<br />

You may well agree, yet wonder why I should do my ruminating about how one goes about<br />

realizing what is claimed by<br />

a sentence through meditation on written sentences. Isn't it just as true<br />

that to grasp the sense and test the truth of what someone says in a spoken sentence the person who<br />

listens must conjure up something to which to apply what is heard said, something which is not<br />

supplied in full by the speaker? I believe the answer is<br />

"yes."<br />

Remember, however, that what<br />

prompted me to think about the thinking that is stirred up when one is on the receiving end,<br />

interpreting someone else's words, was that I was trying to interpret what the Phaedo says about<br />

recollection, cloaks, and lyres.<br />

The scholarly justification for the hypothesis that one of the things that these passages in the<br />

dialogue are about is writing is the resemblance between Aristotle's On <strong>Interpretation</strong> 16a and<br />

Phaedo 73. But what is important about this hypothesis is the following: The passages in the<br />

Phaedo about recollection, cloaks, and lyres and the dialogue entire, are about thinking and for<br />

thinking, not only Socrates', Simmias', and Cebes', and ours, but also Plato's, the author's. What I<br />

mean in saying this is that we ought to try the notion that what the Sophist tells us about thought,<br />

viz., that it is the dialogue of the soul with itself, so that in thinking the one who does it is both<br />

speaker and hearer, I and You, applies to writing too: The author is both writer and reader.<br />

Clearly<br />

this is the experience which the likes of ourselves have when we compose a written<br />

piece. Why opt for radical discontinuity<br />

between Plato and us?<br />

If the supposition of continuity between what motivates major authors to write and what<br />

prompts ourselves to write sounds like hubris, think again about the slave in the Meno. Yes, it is in<br />

some measure more plausible to see continuity between Meno, the Thessalian nobleman, and his<br />

slave than between Plato and ourselves. Yet reconsider Isn't the long-run question of the dialogue<br />

about the excellence that consists in being oneself both Socrates and slave, teacher and learner, that<br />

is, self-ruled investigator? And in respect to certain kinds of investigation, in particular, the finding<br />

of the geometry that transforms Hesiodic stellar lore into mathematical astronomy, isn't there, on<br />

Plato's part, as much need for someone who played the role of teacher vis-a-vis him as there was a<br />

need for Socrates in the slave's case (cf. Epinomis 989e)'.'<br />

Now once one allows oneself the thought that Plato resorts to writing not only to teach but also<br />

to learn, the riddling character of the dialogues acquires a different ethos. They are no longer Zen<br />

master's koans.<br />

The things I said in connection with<br />

Cebes'<br />

and<br />

Socrates'<br />

rather different ways of speaking<br />

about recollection will now apply to the process of writing the dialogues as well as to the outcomes<br />

of that process. The author himself, looking back on what he has written, will have to study the<br />

questions which connections that were written down are strong and which are weak and why. And<br />

if he is anything like the Socrates whom he depicts, the author will trust that even erroneous<br />

answers to his questions have a rationale (as is certainly the case when the slave thinks that doub<br />

ling an area calls for doubling the sides which contain it).<br />

Therefore he will not throw mistakes away even when he has convinced himself that they are<br />

mistakes. He will, having had previous experiences of finding the true in the interstices of moti<br />

vated falsehood,<br />

look promising.<br />

Socrates'<br />

which was the slave's experience under tutelage, "save"<br />

mistakes that<br />

But as for which mistakes are promising, he will have to guess at that. Being a reader as well as


210 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

a writer of his own text, he too will in some measure have to guess at "what is<br />

which is, of<br />

course, the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but the truth about the subject at hand. (Is it at<br />

hand? )<br />

5. Try picturing the weaver sitting at his loom and fabricating the life-cloth by passing horizon<br />

tal weft threads through the vertical warp threads, over and under, over and under, thus making a<br />

surface<br />

"emerge"<br />

just right so that the<br />

try picturing<br />

a man<br />

from<br />

"lines."<br />

Or again, picture the musician who gets the lyre<br />

strings'<br />

tension<br />

"potential"<br />

for noise becomes the "potential'<br />

for music. But isn't it hopeless to<br />

"reaching"<br />

within his mind or memory for an "absent"<br />

item? And, if anything,<br />

still more hopeless to try picturing anything which is utterly mono-eides, one-aspected, simple, and<br />

indissoluble? Say you mean to picture the color yellow, just yellow by itself. You will have to do it<br />

without also picturing surface and shape, but can you?<br />

6. I am claiming that in discovering the "noetic and distinguishing it from the visible<br />

cosmos, he discovered precisely that the "space of is different from that of<br />

that the semiotic is other than the causal "order."<br />

7. Cf. Felix Cohen, "What is a Question?"<br />

Cf. the writings of Wilfrid Sellars.<br />

"causes,"<br />

in The Legal Conscience (Archon Books, 1970).<br />

Also notice how Euclidean proofs circle back on their opening enunciations at the end, in the q.e.d.<br />

or q.e.f. statement.<br />

8. The word eidos, as has frequently been pointed out, is not a Platonic coinage. It seems to be<br />

used, by authors other than Plato, roughly as in German the words Wesen and Gestalt are, e.g. in<br />

the sentences "Sie hat ein angenehmes Wesen."<br />

"Welch eine entzuckende Gestalt."<br />

What gets<br />

emphasized by these German words in the given sentences is the global, overall impression left by<br />

someone or something. Sometimes, indeed, Plato himself so uses the Greek word eidos, for in<br />

stance, at 79a f. , when he speaks of "duo eidee toon ontoon, to men horaton. to de aeides. "To<br />

this use eidos in the Timaeus roughly corresponds. As I understand the passage in the Meno (72)<br />

about "bee"<br />

in the Cratylus (389) about "shuttle,"<br />

in the Republic (596) about "bed,"<br />

or<br />

eide in these<br />

passages are not "separate"<br />

except for the contriving mind. The same holds for the eidos or Gestalt<br />

of the beloved whose toga or lyre reminds of the absent one whose property these are: these are<br />

eide, but not eide choorista, para tauta panta heteron ti.<br />

9. Cf.<br />

"similar," "multitude," "rest"<br />

"big," "heavy"<br />

and their "contraries"<br />

being<br />

fundamental to what will become our physics.<br />

and their opposites in the Parmenides, and "double,"<br />

in the list at Republic v, 479, all the words in quotation marks<br />

10. I take for granted that the reader will agree that the final argument (102e ff.) leaves unde<br />

cided whether, when death comes, the soul<br />

"withdraws"<br />

exist."<br />

or has already "ceased to


The Serious Play<br />

David Roochnik<br />

Iowa State University<br />

of Plato's Euthydemus<br />

Plato's Euthydemus is a strange dialogue.'<br />

In it two old, but not very experi<br />

enced, sophists, the brothers Euthydemus and Dionysodorus,<br />

"eristic"<br />

show off their<br />

abilities. They bombard their audience with fallacy after fallacy, many<br />

of them quite absurd. (Example: that dog is a father; that dog is yours; there<br />

fore, that dog is your father (see 298e].) The dialogue is loaded with word<br />

play, and throughout Socrates is transparently ironic in his praise of his sophis<br />

tic competitors. When they finish their show, he says, "no one of those present<br />

could praise highly enough the argument and the two men, and they nearly died<br />

laughing and joy"<br />

clapping with (303b).<br />

As a result of its almost farcical quality,<br />

strained to begin their work on the Euthydemus by asking<br />

serious enough to merit analysis.2<br />

commentators often feel con<br />

whether it is even<br />

The task of the commentator is then to show<br />

that enough serious material can be extracted to justify the commentary. Typ<br />

ically the sophistical fallacies, which represent about half of the work, have<br />

been taken as the most significant portion of the dialogue. (Including the intro<br />

duction and conclusion the dialogue has seven parts, three of which are filled<br />

with the<br />

sophists'<br />

eristic). Even if they are occasionally absurd, it is obvious<br />

that arguments concerning the nature of learning (275d-77d) or the ambiguity<br />

of the verb "to be"<br />

(283b-e) or the issue of self-predication (300e-301c)<br />

should be seriously analyzed. Kuelen, for example, claims that there is an<br />

important relationship between the learning<br />

Meno; Peck argues similarly about the "to be"<br />

fallacies and the doctrines of the<br />

arguments and the Sophist;<br />

Sprague interprets a passage from the Euthydemus as an objection to the theory<br />

of Forms similar to one articulated in the Parmenides (see Keulen, Peck,<br />

Sprague [1967],<br />

and also Mohr).<br />

The fallacies have also been examined from a historical perspective. Since<br />

they are closely related to many<br />

phistical Refutation (SE) the following sorts of questions have been asked:<br />

of the examples Aristotle uses in his On So<br />

What is the relationship between Aristotle's treatment of the fallacies and<br />

Plato's? (Keulen asks this question, as does Praechter.) Was there an original<br />

source that supplied both the Euthydemus and the SE with its eristic arguments?<br />

Was there, for example, a historical figure named Euthydemus who actually<br />

compiled a handbook of fallacies (as is perhaps suggested at SE 177M2 and<br />

Rhetoric 1401a26)? (This is the main question in Praechter'<br />

s essay.)<br />

A similar historical question is this: What is the relationship between Plato's<br />

interpretation, Winter 1990-1991, Vol. 18, No. 2


212 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

dialogue and the "Dissoi Logoi"<br />

manual, possibly written at the end of the<br />

fifth century (see Sprague [1968], pp. 160-61)? Whatever the answer, it is<br />

clear that the Euthydemus provides valuable information about the state of<br />

Greek logic during this period, and it is likely that a great deal of serious work<br />

the sophistical arguments of the dia<br />

is both reflected in and was inspired by<br />

logue. The Kneales suggest an example: "It is probable then that the early<br />

Megarians took part in, and were stimulated to logical discovery by, such dis<br />

putes as we find satirized in Plato's Euthydemus"<br />

(p. 15).<br />

There is thus no doubt that the fallacies deserve attention from both histo<br />

rians of logic and philosophers concerned with Plato's development. In this<br />

essay, however, I propose a different approach to the serious side of the Euthy<br />

demus. Instead of focusing on its three eristic sections (275d-77d, 283b-88b,<br />

Socrates' "protreptic"<br />

293b-303b), I shall concentrate largely on speeches<br />

and Praech<br />

(278e-83a, 288d-93a). Commentators (e.g., Stewart, Friedlander,<br />

ter) frequently dismiss, simply paraphrase,<br />

or ignore these arguments. M. A.<br />

Stewart describes the argument as "an extravagant induction"<br />

and "equivocal."<br />

P. Friedlander says almost nothing about these arguments. Praechter describes<br />

the philosophical side of the dialogue as essentially negative and Socrates'<br />

guments as "unmittelbar ohne frucht"<br />

(p. 9). By contrast, I hope to show that if<br />

analyzed carefully, these speeches employ some of Plato's most crucial<br />

terms techne and arete are the prime examples and they raise philosophical<br />

questions of the highest order.<br />

The two protreptic speeches together form a continuous argument which is<br />

indeed quite serious. However, precisely because it is protreptic, the argument<br />

is also intrinsically problematic. Protreptic, as explained by Socrates, is a form<br />

of argument designed to persuade its audience that "one ought to philosophize<br />

and care about<br />

arete"<br />

(275a6. For a comparison see Isocrates To Nicocles 57. 1,<br />

Evagoras 11. 1 , Antitdosis 60.4, 84.2, and 86.2,<br />

ar<br />

and Aristotle's Rhetoric 1358b<br />

ff.) It invites its audience into the project of philosophy and promises, either<br />

implicitly or explicitly, that such a quest will be rewarding. But protreptic is<br />

next."<br />

incomplete: it only promises and does not itself deliver "what comes<br />

This phrase, "what comes<br />

next"<br />

(to meta touto) comes from Cleitophon 408d7,<br />

a dialogue devoted to the question of protreptic. I have commented on this<br />

work at length in "The Riddle of Plato's Cleitophon."<br />

It urges its audience to<br />

love wisdom but does not itself provide, or clearly articulate the nature of, that<br />

wisdom. As a result, protreptic forces the reader to consider some of the most<br />

pressing questions raised by the dialogues: Do "positive"<br />

they contain a teach<br />

ing? Can Socrates'<br />

promise of wisdom be fulfilled? Is there a theoretical doc<br />

trine, an episteme or techne, that actually does "come or is Socratic<br />

protreptic merely promissory? Does Socrates only refute and exhort his inter<br />

locutors, or does he actually teach them?<br />

Answering such questions would ultimately require a comprehensive inter<br />

pretation of the dialogues. This the essay to follow will hardly supply. Instead,


The Serious Play of Plato's Euthydemus -213<br />

I shall argue only for the following thesis: The protreptic arguments offered by<br />

Socrates fail to demonstrate conclusively that one ought to philosophize. If this<br />

is correct, does it follow that Socratic protreptic undermines itself? After all, if<br />

arguments purporting to show that one ought to philosophize are themselves<br />

riddled with problems, then why ought one to philosophize?<br />

While its conclusion is not universally or necessarily true, I shall argue that<br />

the protreptic does not undermine itself. As we shall see, Socrates'<br />

arguments<br />

are compelling only to those who are predisposed to agree with their conclu<br />

sion. Such a diagnosis sounds entirely damning; it is not, however. A thorough<br />

examination of the protreptic will disclose that these peculiar arguments are<br />

uniquely instructive. While they are not powerful enough to persuade every<br />

body to philosophize (i.e., to demonstrate that philosophy is an unconditional<br />

good), they can yet be effective in urging someone like Kleinias, the young<br />

man who (along with the reader) is the real target of Socrates'<br />

pursue philosophy. Furthermore, they<br />

can teach him how to do so.<br />

speeches, to<br />

In sum, then, the protreptic, like the Euthydemus itself, is a strange blend of<br />

seriousness and play. On the one hand, the protreptic arguments for the pursuit<br />

of philosophy fail to attain their stated purpose; "we were entirely<br />

says Socrates as he nears their conclusion (291b). Nevertheless, the protreptic<br />

succeeds in performing a most serious task: outlining the questions that must be<br />

pursued if Socrates'<br />

exhortation to philosophize is to be heeded.<br />

In the prologue the two sophists make a mighty boast for themselves:<br />

"Arete, Socrates, is what we think we can transmit more finely and quickly<br />

than anybody<br />

sponse is this:<br />

else"<br />

(273d8-9). The first question that Socrates poses in re<br />

Are you only able to make a man good who is already convinced that he should<br />

learn from you,<br />

or can you also teach that man who is not yet convinced either<br />

because he does not believe that in general arete is teachable or that you two are<br />

teachers of it? Come on, is it the work of the same techne to persuade such a man<br />

that arete is teachable and that you are the ones from whom someone could best<br />

leam, or is that the work of some other techne? (274d7-e5)<br />

Dionysodorus answers that it is the same techne that does these two jobs.<br />

Socrates then reformulates: "Therefore, Dionysodorus, of all men you most<br />

finely<br />

losophy<br />

'protrepticize,'<br />

encourage (or protrepsaite , 275al) others to pursue phi<br />

and to be concerned about<br />

arete?"<br />

(274a8-75a2). The sophist agrees.<br />

ridicu<br />

Examination of this passage raises general questions about the possibility of<br />

teaching arete which, I suggest, can best be illuminated by comparing the<br />

teaching of arete with other, more typical, subjects (or technai). The passage


214 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

implies that instruction in the latter requires at least four separate phases. (1)<br />

Before beginning a specific study<br />

a student must first be persuaded that the<br />

subject can be taught. In a typical subject like geometry this is easily done. A<br />

prospective student can simply observe that those who took Geometry<br />

101 in<br />

the fall, and knew nothing of the subject, can prove a host of theorems by the<br />

spring. (2) The student must be persuaded that the prospective teacher can<br />

to obtain. It can be<br />

actually teach the subject. Evidence of this is also easy<br />

determined that Dr. Jones received a degree in mathematics and taught the<br />

students who took Geometry 101 last year. (3) A third preparatory phase (one<br />

only suggested by the passage) is also required: The student must be persuaded<br />

that putting in the hours of study geometry demands is "worth it."<br />

As a result,<br />

the teacher must persuade the student that geometry is valuable. A good teacher<br />

of a typical subject thus requires two separate capacities: fluency in the actual<br />

material to be taught, and the ability<br />

to arouse the<br />

students'<br />

interest and<br />

commitment to the subject. It is obvious that the former need not imply the<br />

latter. (4) The final stage of instruction is communication of the actual course<br />

material.<br />

This schema seems applicable to any ordinary techne. Arete, however, is an<br />

extraordinary subject whose teaching will disrupt the schema for the following<br />

reasons. First, it can be quite difficult to persuade a student that arete is an<br />

actual subject. As Socrates often points out, there is no obvious version of<br />

Arete 101 and its teachers are not easily identified (see, e.g., Meno 89e ff. and<br />

Protogoras 319e ff.). How, then, does one persuade a student that arete can be<br />

taught? The student must be "protrepticized,"<br />

exhorted to attempt an extraordi<br />

nary subject. For most people, instruction in arete is left to the basic customs or<br />

institutions of the community: imitation of the elders, obedience to civil law,<br />

and religious traditions are examples. To persuade someone to study arete as a<br />

distinct subject therefore requires calling into question the authority of such<br />

familiar activities and opinions. To be a candidate for such instruction, the<br />

student thus has to be willing, at the outset, to question the nature of arete. But<br />

this is equivalent to commencing the study of arete itself. In other words, the<br />

initial protreptic phase, (1) and (2) from above, collapses into phase (4), the<br />

actual study of the subject.<br />

A similar collapse occurs with phase (3). How does a teacher persuade a<br />

student that arete, assuming it can be taught, is worth studying? Only by argu<br />

ing that knowledge of arete is valuable. This would require employing and then<br />

explaining some standard by which to measure the value of this knowledge.<br />

But arete itself is precisely the standard that measures the value of activities.<br />

Therefore, it itself would need to be invoked to prove the value of knowledge<br />

of itself. In other words, should a teacher try to persuade a student that arete is<br />

worth studying, she would have to explain the value of the subject. But this<br />

explanation would be an actual lesson in arete. Again, there is no division<br />

between the protreptic preliminaries and the actual study itself.


The Serious Play of Plato's Euthydemus -215<br />

The dilemma of commencing the study of arete thus echoes Meno's famous<br />

paradox. A student cannot learn arete unless he can be convinced that it is both<br />

teachable and worth studying. But only the student already convinced of both is<br />

open to the possibility of being<br />

so persuaded. Put into somewhat exaggerated<br />

terms, since being convinced that arete is teachable and worth studying<br />

a component of being good, only somebody already<br />

This issue, which admittedly is only suggested by the passage,<br />

is itself<br />

good can be made good.<br />

will become<br />

more explicit as the dialogue progresses. As we shall see in Sections III and V,<br />

it will prove to be critical for understanding the intrinsic limitations of Socratic<br />

protreptic.<br />

Dionysodorus states that it is one and the same techne that persuades a<br />

student that arete is teachable and that he and his brother can teach it (274e6).<br />

In a sense, this is the right answer: Because of the collapse of the various<br />

instructional phases just discussed, it has to be one and the same activity that<br />

both persuades the student to study and engages in the actual instruction. In<br />

another sense, however, it is clear that the sophist is unaware of a lurking<br />

problem. This concerns the very notion of a "techne,"<br />

the word commonly used<br />

by Socrates to label ordinary forms of knowledge such as medicine, carpentry,<br />

geometry, etc. As has just been argued, the study of arete is extraordinary. The<br />

question should therefore be raised, Can there be a techne of arete? If so, who<br />

If not, does this imply there<br />

sophists.3<br />

possesses it? Certainly not the two old<br />

is no knowledge of arete at all, or can arete be comprehended by some form of<br />

"nontechnical"<br />

knowledge (see Woodruff)? As we shall see in Section IV be<br />

low, these are precisely the issues taken up in Socrates'<br />

speech.<br />

II<br />

second protreptic<br />

The fallacies of the first eristical scene commence when Euthydemus asks<br />

Kleinias, the highly promising youth who is the occasion for the entire dialogue<br />

(273a-c and 275a), "of the following two groups, who are the ones who learn,<br />

those who are wise (sophoi)<br />

When Kleinias answers "the<br />

swering<br />

"the ignorant,"<br />

or those who are ignorant (amatheis)T (275d).<br />

wise"<br />

he is refuted. quickly He responds by an<br />

and is refuted once again. As Socrates later explains<br />

(277e-78a), the sophist here plays on the ambiguity of manthanein, which can<br />

mean either "to<br />

understand"<br />

(sunienai: 278a4) or "to learn new."<br />

something<br />

Manthanein can refer to expanding upon knowledge presently possessed (a stu<br />

dent who already knows his letters will understand a grammar lesson)<br />

acquiring<br />

or to<br />

new knowledge (a student who does not know his letters can learn<br />

them). As such, the question can receive two different, and seemingly exclu<br />

sive, answers. Given the first meaning of the verb, the answer is "the wise";<br />

given the second, it is "the ignorant."<br />

Kleinias is befuddled.


216 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

This argument has occasioned much debate. It is not clear, for example,<br />

exactly where the force of the ambiguity falls. "Does the sophism depend upon<br />

an equivocation on manthanein .<br />

theis ('knowledgeable/ignorant'<br />

or on an equivocation on sophoi and ama-<br />

and 'clever/stupid')?"<br />

(Hawtrey,<br />

pp. 58 ff.). It<br />

is also possible that rather than equivocation the fallacy is better described as,<br />

"the one known traditionally as a dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter.<br />

. . . This<br />

fallacy consists in taking absolutely what should be taken only acci<br />

dentally, e.g., to go from 'knowing<br />

(Sprague [1962], p. 6).<br />

one's letters'<br />

to simply 'knowing'"<br />

Since the focus of this essay is on Socrates', and not the sophists', argu<br />

ments, I shall simply assert that some form of equivocation is going on. What<br />

is clear is that, whatever the exact status of the argument, its consequences, if<br />

taken seriously, would call into question the very possibility of learning. If "the<br />

one who learns"<br />

cannot be identified, then the process of learning itself cannot<br />

be rationally explained, and it becomes legitimate to ask whether it is even<br />

possible. Clearly the sophistic arguments echo Meno's famous learning para<br />

dox. (Again, Keulen makes this a major issue.)<br />

After explaining that the fallacy rests on an equivocation, Socrates seems to<br />

dismiss the<br />

sophists'<br />

arguments as follows:<br />

These are student games (paidia) and thus I tell you that these fellows are playing<br />

(prospaizein) with you and I call this play (paidian) because even if someone<br />

should leam either many or all of such things as they teach, he would have no<br />

more knowledge of how things really are, but he would only be able to play with<br />

other men, tripping up and overturning them, by his use of the difference of<br />

names. They are like boys who take pleasure in pulling a chair away from people<br />

who are about to sit down and laugh when they see them sprawled upside down.<br />

You should think of what these fellows do as play (278bl-c2).<br />

Socrates proposes that instead of such play, the sophists should fulfil their<br />

promise to engage in the serious work (ta spoudaia: 278c3)<br />

of protreptic. A<br />

series of dichotomies thus suggests itself: Sophistry is the mere playing with<br />

words; it is concerned only with appearances and refutation,<br />

and not with in<br />

struction in how things really are; it is superficial, manipulative, and bad. By<br />

contrast, philosophy uses words to understand things; it is serious, protreptic<br />

(or "dialectical")<br />

("Dialectical"<br />

and good. is Sprague's word in Plato's Use of<br />

Fallacy, p. 3, and her interpretation is a good example of what I'm talking<br />

about. The relationship between dialectic and protreptic would constitute an<br />

issue in itself, and I shall not broach it here. See also Szlezak, p. 81.)<br />

While such comfortable dichotomies are attractive, I suggest that they are<br />

not as easily sustained as commentators wish to think. Despite their lack of<br />

perspicacity, the sophists have a position which is potentially quite serious.<br />

Whatever the exact status of the argument concerning learning, there is no<br />

doubt that overcoming Meno's paradox is not easy. Let us assume for a mo-


The Serious Play of Plato's Euthydemus -217<br />

ment that the process of learning cannot in fact be rationally articulated and that<br />

its possibility should therefore be called into question. If that were the case,<br />

then the verbal combat of sophistry, the manipulation of words whose goal is<br />

only to achieve victory in any given contest of speeches, should be taken very<br />

seriously. Since the use of language could promise no higher goal, i.e., knowl<br />

edge, there would be no reason not to become a sophist.<br />

This position that I here propose attributing to the sophists is roughly equiv<br />

alent to that often ascribed to Gorgias. In his "On Nature"<br />

"Praise of Helen"<br />

and Section 1 1 of the<br />

he presents a form of scepticism. This in turn provides him<br />

with a warrant for his commitment to rhetoric, wherein truth is only an "adorn<br />

ment"<br />

(kosmos) of "logos."<br />

first word of the "Praise of Helen."<br />

The key<br />

It is extremely difficult to translate "kosmos,"<br />

the<br />

See Diels, pp. 288 ff. , for the Greek text.<br />

point is this: The sophists who oppose Socrates are no doubt comic<br />

figures. This does not imply, however, that their position should be dismissed<br />

as a farcical "Gegenbild"<br />

(Szlezak's word, p. 81) to the serious work of Socra<br />

tic philosophy. It is possible to abstract the sophistic view from its playful<br />

context and the result is troubling, and perhaps formidable.<br />

The sense in which the sophistic view can seriously oppose Socrates'<br />

will be<br />

made clear as we examine the first protreptic argument. As we shall see, the<br />

conclusion Socrates purports to establish is, at the least, precarious. In other<br />

words, it will not be clear that good reasons are provided as to why Kleinias,<br />

the target of the protreptic, should accept the invitation to philosophize rather<br />

than join the sophistic camp. Indeed, we shall see in the following section that<br />

Socrates'<br />

argument requires prior agreement with, and does not itself certify, at<br />

least one of its premises; and it is precisely this premise that the sophistic<br />

scepticism concerning learning would call into question.<br />

Ill<br />

The following<br />

tions and Kleinias'<br />

tic:<br />

is an outline of the argument 1 extract from Socrates'<br />

ques<br />

answers, and which Socrates describes as genuine protrep<br />

1. All human beings wish to do well (eu prattein: 278e6), i.e., wish to be<br />

happy<br />

(eudaimonein: 280b6).<br />

2. In order to do well, the possession of good things is required (279a3 ff.).<br />

2A. A sample list of good things: wealth, health, physical beauty, good<br />

family,<br />

power and honor in one's community, temperance, justice, courage,<br />

wisdom (279a7-c3).<br />

2B. Good fortune (eutuchia: 279c7) is a subsequent addition to the list.<br />

However, because "wisdom is good<br />

fortune"<br />

(279d6) the same item is actu<br />

ally listed twice.<br />

3. To bring happiness, good things must benefit their possessor (280b7-8).


218- <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

4. To benefit,<br />

good things must be used (280c l-d7).<br />

5. To benefit, good things must be used correctly (280e3-4).<br />

6. Knowledge (episteme: 281b2) leads to correct use.<br />

7. All items on the sample list (2A) are actually neutral (281e3-4). Knowledge<br />

(or "good sense: [phronesis: 281b6[<br />

or "wisdom"<br />

\sophia: 281b6]<br />

or "intel<br />

ligence"<br />

[nous: 281b7|) is the only intrinsic good and should be sought at any<br />

cost. (I omit that portion which argues that those with little sense should do less<br />

in order to err less [281b ff. ).)<br />

This is a classical protreptic argument, traces of which probably appear in<br />

Aristotle's Protrepticus (see During, p. 19). Its conclusion, "that it is necessary<br />

to love (philosophein: 282dl), if seriously accepted, would demand a<br />

total commitment on the part of anyone who agrees. Indeed, the conclusion is<br />

so serious and, with its use of the word "necessary"<br />

(anagkaion), so apparently<br />

unconditional in its admonition, that the premises deserve the closest scrutiny.<br />

Unfortunately, they are, as we shall see, quite vague. (This has led Stewart to<br />

describe this argument as an example of "Plato's sophistry.") A similar vague<br />

ness is found in the conclusion itself: Even if Kleinias were to agree that he<br />

ought to love wisdom, Socrates uses several words to describe the knowledge<br />

towards which the argument directs him. Two related questions, What exactly<br />

is this knowledge and How might Kleinias attain it? are thus left distressingly<br />

open. Finally, the principal examples used to illustrate knowledge or wisdom<br />

come from "the typical<br />

actually<br />

technai."<br />

It is not clear, however,<br />

whether these can<br />

provide an adequate theoretical model for the type of knowledge the<br />

argument encourages Kleinias to seek.<br />

The first premise contains a famous ambiguity in the phrase "eu<br />

Does it mean "to do<br />

well,"<br />

in the sense of being virtuous,<br />

or "to in<br />

the sense of achieving one's goal, whatever that may be? Both Hawtrey and<br />

Gifford comment on the pointed ambiguity of "eu<br />

its usual acceptation it would rather mean "faring<br />

pratte<br />

prattein."<br />

The latter says, "In<br />

well"<br />

than "acting<br />

(p. 20). The reformulation the phrase receives, "eudaimonein,"<br />

never quite adequately translated as "to be happy,"<br />

only<br />

typically but<br />

recapitulates the prob<br />

lem. It does not seem to be the case that all people wish to be virtuous. We<br />

may all wish to succeed, that is, attain what we deem to be worth attaining. Eu<br />

prattein covers both situations. Its ambiguity, however, may not be entirely<br />

vicious; the first (as well as the second) premise expresses a basic, and typ<br />

ically Socratic, opinion about human behavior: All human beings desire what<br />

seems to them to be good. We make value judgments, pursue goals,<br />

well'"<br />

attempt to<br />

move from here to there with an eye towards attaining what we want and deem,<br />

even if inarticulately, to be good (see, e.g., Symposium 206a). The argument<br />

assumes, and does not prove, that human beings are free agents whose rational<br />

choice of what is good determines their action. It is vague and undefended, but<br />

not without some basis in ordinary observation.<br />

Premise (2) implies that human action is inspired by epithumia, the desire


for and consequent pursuit of objects. Again,<br />

The Serious Play of Plato's Euthydemus -219<br />

although the premise is vague it<br />

reflects a broad and (to some) compelling perception of human behavior: Peo<br />

ple go after what they want, and what they want is what they think is good.<br />

I describe the list of good things Socrates proposes as "sample"<br />

because the<br />

specific items on it are not in themselves that important. The point is only that<br />

such a list can in principle be drawn. The items on this list (which have been<br />

accused of fluctuating<br />

"between the causes and the constituents of<br />

[Stewart, p. 23]) cover a very broad spectrum, ranging from bodily beauty to<br />

justice. Nevertheless, in keeping with the kind of analysis made so far, the list<br />

is plausible: it signifies again something basic about ordinary behavior. Each of<br />

us has a set of goals that energize our desires, a sample list of good things we<br />

think are worth pursuing.<br />

To summarize: The assumptions initiating Socrates'<br />

argument are vague and<br />

questionable. Nevertheless, they express a plausible conviction about human<br />

action, namely that it is caused by free and rational choices. More serious<br />

problems with the argument are yet to come.<br />

After placing wisdom on the list of sample goods, Socrates digresses. He<br />

states that he and Kleinias have left out "the greatest of the good things .<br />

good fortune (eutuchia: 279c7)."<br />

succe<br />

. .<br />

He cannot, however, add eutuchia to the list<br />

for it would repeat an item already there, namely sophia. By means of a series<br />

of examples, Socrates argues that good fortune and wisdom are really the same.<br />

In the matter of flute playing skilled flautists have the best fortune; in reading<br />

and writing letters, it is the writing masters; in warfare it is the wise generals;<br />

in times of sickness one would always prefer to try one's luck with the wise<br />

doctor. (About eutuchia Gifford says it means both "an accidental concurrence<br />

of favourable circumstances, and success resulting<br />

choice of<br />

from the agent's judicious<br />

means"<br />

[p. 22]. Note that at 279el the word used is eupragia. So<br />

crates generalizes: "Wisdom everywhere makes human beings have good for<br />

tune"<br />

[280a6]. This same point is made about eutuchia and techne in the Hip-<br />

pocratic writing, "Peri Technes,"<br />

section IV.)<br />

Why does Socrates go off on this tangent,<br />

hia and sophia really as "disastrous"<br />

and is this identification of eutuc<br />

as Stewart thinks (p. 23)? The purpose of<br />

this digression, I suggest, is to focus attention on the character of techne. As<br />

has often been stated, techne is the mode of knowledge that best overcomes,<br />

and enables its possessor to control, tuche, luck (see, e.g., Nussbaum, 95-<br />

100). The pilot, for example, fares well when facing the contingencies of the<br />

sea. In this passage Socrates relies exclusively on techne for his model of wis<br />

dom,<br />

soon to be defined as that knowledge of the correct use of neutral items<br />

which brings its possessor happiness. But is wisdom best modeled by techne?<br />

In Section I we noted the features of arete that would distinguish its being<br />

taught from instruction in the ordinary technai. For Socrates arete is equivalent<br />

to sophia; therefore,<br />

this digression should be read with an eye towards the<br />

possibility of irony. In other words, despite its superficial identification of


220 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

sophia with techne, the real purpose of this passage may<br />

well be to call that<br />

identification into question. Is techne in fact the best model for sophia? If not,<br />

what is the nature of that sophia which knows how to use correctly the neutral<br />

items on the sample list and thus bring happiness to its possessor? These ques<br />

tions will be returned to shortly.<br />

Premise (3) states that the good things on the sample list must bring benefit<br />

to their possessor. This is true by definition and so adds little to the argument.<br />

Premise (4) does add something new: It states that benefit requires that the<br />

good things be used. I may possess an apple, but it brings no nutritional benefit<br />

unless I eat it. A woman may, for example, have a great deal of money, but<br />

she would neither be benefited nor made happy by it unless she used (spent) it<br />

(280d). "Use"<br />

becomes the crucial term because it refers to the process of<br />

bringing possessions into the human sphere, i.e., of applying them.<br />

Premise (5) elaborates the concept of use. Benefit requires, not only that<br />

good things be used, but that they be used<br />

"bad"<br />

item is used incorrectly the result is<br />

"correctly"<br />

(orthos: 280e3). If the<br />

(kakon: 280e6). This, I propose, is<br />

the pivotal premise of the argument. It assumes that the items of the sample list<br />

are in fact not good at all; they<br />

are neutral and can be used for good or ill. Most<br />

important, it assumes that the use of an item can be understood as correct or<br />

incorrect, good or bad.<br />

This assumption, I suggest, is problematic in a way that is both similar to<br />

and different from the problems surrounding the first four. None of the prem<br />

ises is self-evidently true; they are neither defended nor is their meaning en<br />

tirely clear. In order for the conclusion to be compelling, therefore, the target<br />

audience of the protreptic must already be predisposed to agree with them.<br />

Premises (1) and (2), for example,<br />

assume that human beings are free agents<br />

whose selection of what is good can determine their actions. This may not be<br />

true. Its truth, however, is not here the issue; the point is that in order for the<br />

audience to be protrepticized they must believe it is true.<br />

Premise (5) poses a similar, but more serious and complicated, dilemma. Is<br />

it in fact the case that, (1) things like wealth and health are not good but<br />

neutral; (2) their use can be rationally evaluated as correct and for the good, or<br />

incorrect and for the bad; (3)<br />

what the correct/good use is can be learned? It is<br />

possible to accept the earlier premises but still deny Premise (5). Indeed, this is<br />

precisely what sophists such as Dionysodorus and Euthydemus would do. They<br />

surely<br />

would maintain that human beings are free agents whose actions are<br />

determined by some conception of what is good, e.g., attaining political power<br />

in the Assembly. Without this assumption, their sophistry would become mean<br />

ingless: they would have no reason to seduce an audience. They would not,<br />

however, agree with Premise (5). Their scepticism as disclosed in the first<br />

eristic scene (275d ff.) prohibits them from doing so. As suggested in Section<br />

II above, the entire case for sophistry rests on the denial that objective knowl<br />

edge is possible. Premise (5)<br />

of Socrates'<br />

first protreptic argument assumes the


The Serious Play of Plato's Euthydemus 221<br />

opposite, namely objective knowledge of the correct or good use of an object is<br />

attainable. In other words, Socrates assumes that the "practical"<br />

question, How<br />

should we live our lives and apply or use our possessions? can be answered.<br />

From this assumption he concludes that such answers should be sought.<br />

To reformulate: If Socrates'<br />

premises are granted, then it follows that<br />

knowledge of how to use one's possessions would be the most desirable posses<br />

sion which is needed in order to be happy (which everybody<br />

wishes to be).<br />

Everyone, therefore, ought to seek knowledge of the correct use of neutral<br />

items. It is, in other words, "necessary to<br />

propose, is question-begging.<br />

philosop<br />

But Premise (5), I<br />

According to Socrates, an item like health is neither good nor bad, for it can<br />

be used well or badly. A strong body can beat up innocent weak bodies or build<br />

hospitals. Socrates assumes that one of these applications of the body<br />

is and<br />

can be known as correct. This assumption begs the crucial question. If correct<br />

use is a property belonging to neutral items, and if neutral items span the broad<br />

range that the sample list indicates, then knowledge of correct use would be<br />

required for happiness. The conclusion is thus built into the premise: If there is<br />

such a thing as correct use, then knowledge of it should be<br />

sought.4<br />

But on the<br />

basis of what should this assumption be granted? It is not self-evident: What if<br />

there is no such thing as correct use, if use is simply in the eyes of the be<br />

holder? What force would the protreptic argument then have? Can the living of<br />

a good life be directed by knowledge? Perhaps so. This, however, is precisely<br />

what the argument should show,<br />

and not assume.<br />

As if to signal distress, the conclusion is stated with a flurry<br />

of different<br />

terms: "episteme"<br />

(281b2). "phronesis"<br />

(281b6), "sophia"<br />

(281d6), and "nous"<br />

(281b7) are all used to label that which should be sought. This terminological<br />

flux helps to raise a decisive problem with the conclusion of Socrates'<br />

argu<br />

ment: Just what is this knowledge, assuming it exists, that Kleinias is being<br />

exhorted to seek? Throughout the discussion, most clearly in the eutuchia/<br />

sophia digression (279c-80b), typical technai such as flute playing, reading<br />

and writing, piloting a ship, being a general, and medicine are cited as exam<br />

ples of knowledge. Furthermore, it is carpentry that provides the example of<br />

correct use in Premise (5) (281a). Is it a typical techne, then, one whose subject<br />

matter is the good use of neutral items, that Kleinias should seek? The mere<br />

"technical"<br />

presence of so examples would seem to suggest<br />

many<br />

that it is.<br />

Such a conclusion, however, is difficult to maintain. Exactly why can be made<br />

Socrates'<br />

clear by further examining use of the example of the carpenter.<br />

A typical techne has a determinate subject matter. The carpenter's subject is<br />

the production of furniture from wood (281a5). He knows, says Socrates, how<br />

to use tools and wood (280c8-9). Socrates makes an analogy between the car<br />

penter and his tools and a man with money. The carpenter uses his tools and<br />

wood knowledgeably (or "technically") and is therefore benefited by them.<br />

Correspondingly, the man with money should use his wealth knowledgeably in


222 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

order to be benefited and be made happy by it (280d). "In the working<br />

and use<br />

concerned with wood, is there anything other than the episteme of carpentry<br />

that effects the right<br />

use?"<br />

(281a2-4). The answer is no. Analogously, says<br />

Socrates, it is episteme that should direct the possessor of the items on the<br />

sample list, such as wealth, towards the correct and therefore beneficial use of<br />

his possessions; towards, in other words, happiness.<br />

There is a problem with this analogy which only becomes explicit in So<br />

crates'<br />

second protreptic speech. There are two senses of the word "use."<br />

First,<br />

the carpenter knows how to use his tools and wood. With them he knows how<br />

to build furniture. But he does not know how to use the furniture . The<br />

carpenter<br />

knows how to build a chair; but to what end will the chair be put? Will it be<br />

used to seat someone comfortably at a symposium,<br />

or will it be used as an<br />

instrument for torturing a political prisoner? It is this second sense of "use"<br />

would be required for "using"<br />

the neutral items on the sample list correctly and<br />

for the good. The first sense is technical and value neutral: the carpenter uses<br />

the tool correctly to produce the chair. The second sense is value laden: the<br />

chair is used correctly and for the good in order to achieve happiness. The<br />

carpenter, qua possessor of a techne, knows nothing of this.<br />

This problem discloses the difficulty of identifying what type of knowledge<br />

it is that the target audience of the protreptic is being urged to seek. It cannot<br />

be an ordinary techne. But technai have been the sole supplier of examples of<br />

knowledge. Then what is it? The second part of the protreptic explicitly takes<br />

up this issue.<br />

IV<br />

Socrates begins this section be restating the conclusion of the first part of the<br />

protreptic: Human beings should seek wisdom, i.e., philosophize (288d6-7).<br />

But what knowledge should we seek (see 289d9-10)? To elicit an answer, he<br />

suggests as possibilities the ability to discover gold (or alchemy), in other<br />

words the ability to produce wealth (288e6-89a5); medicine; the ability to pro<br />

duce immortality (289b 1). None of these epistemai, however, can really bring<br />

happiness, for they do not understand how to use their results.<br />

Plato's word at 288d8, d9, 289al, a4, bl and b4. "Techne"<br />

As is often the case, the two are synonymous.) An immortal life,<br />

("Episteme"<br />

that<br />

is<br />

returns at 289c4.<br />

even one<br />

supplied with indefinite wealth, can still be wretched. The type of knowledge<br />

that is needed is one in which the knowledge of how to produce is combined<br />

with knowledge of how to use what is produced (289b4-7), in which the mak<br />

ing is united with the using techne (289c2. See Republic 601c for more on the<br />

using techne.). Clearly, the sense of "use"<br />

here is not technical and value neu<br />

tral, but value laden.<br />

Ordinary technai, exemplified next by instrument making, fail this test. So-


The Serious Play of Plato'<br />

s Euthydemus 223<br />

crates then rather enthusiastically asks, "By the gods,<br />

what if we should learn<br />

the techne of making speeches (logopoiikeri)! Is this what is required to make<br />

us happy"<br />

(289c6-9)? Kleinias answers no,<br />

and he offers as evidence the fact<br />

that this techne can easily suffer the same split as any other: It is possible for<br />

speechmakers not to know how to use the speeches they make (289d).<br />

Socrates indicates some disappointment at the failure of the speechmaking<br />

techne. On the one hand, he is surely being ironic, for "speech<br />

making<br />

imme<br />

diately connotes the work of men like the very sophists with whom he is argu<br />

ing (see 304-6. I think, for example, of Lysias. See Phaedrus 257c. Also, the<br />

close of the Euthydemus , 304d-306b, returns to this issue.) On the other hand,<br />

his disappointment hints at something more positive: "Logos"<br />

is surely part of<br />

the right answer to the question, What knowledge should be sought? for what is<br />

required is a logos of how to use all objects of desire. What is required is<br />

sophia, understood not as an ordinary techne, but as a comprehensive account<br />

of what is good in the human sphere. (Szlezak believes that what is being<br />

referred to here is the scientific rhetoric of the Phaedrus [p. 86].) However, as<br />

we shall now see, identifying<br />

account is intrinsically problematic.<br />

Socrates offers the "general's<br />

the sort of knowledge that can provide such an<br />

techne"<br />

(290bl; mentioned earlier at 279e) as<br />

his next proposal. He does so apparently because the general,<br />

to command other human beings, knows how to organize,<br />

who knows how<br />

and in this sense<br />

use, the various technicians under his sway. Kleinias, however, immediately<br />

counters with an objection: The general's techne, he says, is a kind of hunting<br />

(290b5). Therefore, just as the hunter of game hands over his catch to a cook,<br />

so the general hunts and acquires cities and "then hands them over to the politi<br />

cal men, for [the generals] themselves do not know how to use that which they<br />

hunt"<br />

(290d2-3). In fact, Kleinias gives a quite detailed description of this type<br />

of knowledge:<br />

No part of hunting itself covers more than chasing and overcoming. And when the<br />

hunter overcomes what he is chasing he is not able to use it. Instead, hunters and<br />

fishermen hand over their catch to cooks. Analogously, geometers and astronomers<br />

and mathematicians for these also are hunters since none of them make their<br />

diagrams, they discover what is since they themselves do not know how to use<br />

these things, but only how to catch them, they hand them over to those men<br />

accomplished in dialectic so that they can use what these hunters have discov<br />

ered at least they can use however many of their discoveries that are not entirely<br />

senseless (290b7-c6).<br />

This is an impressive little speech, for it succinctly presents an entire con<br />

ception of techne. As if to signal its remarkable character, Plato places this<br />

speech in an extraordinary<br />

dramatic context: He has Krito interrupt the narra<br />

tion and ask whether young Kleinias was actually its author (290el). This is a<br />

good question: How did a mere boy learn about dialectic? Socrates responds by


224 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Productive"<br />

Animals<br />

t<br />

Cooks<br />

TECHNE<br />

Living<br />

(Hunting)<br />

^Acquisitive^<br />

Nonliving<br />

(Mathematics)<br />

Human Dia! ectic<br />

Political Men<br />

saying that he does not remember who the author was; perhaps it was the older<br />

Ktessipus. The situation is then made even more mysterious when he adds,<br />

"Good Krito,<br />

things"<br />

perhaps one of the higher beings was present and uttered these<br />

(291a3-4). Such mystery is, I believe,<br />

unparalled in the dialogues.<br />

What is the point of such dramatic tension? I suggest it is to highlight the<br />

fecundity of this succinct epistemological proposal, which the accompanying<br />

diagram schematizes.<br />

Although somewhat awkward, this diagram schematizes an important epis<br />

temological conception which finds parallels in several other dialogues. (For<br />

parallels, see Charmides 165c-166b, Gorgias 450b-d, Philebus 55d-58a,<br />

Sophist 281e-219d, Statesman 258b-260b. The diagram is awkward because<br />

some branches give genus and species and others do not.) First, it represents<br />

the fact that there are two basic forms of techne, the productive and the acquisi<br />

tive. The former are the most ordinary of all forms of knowledge, e.g., carpen<br />

try, pottery, medicine, etc.; the latter is itself divided into two parts, the second<br />

of which, I propose, is metaphorical; the acquisition of nonliving beings repre<br />

sents what Aristotle calls "theoretical knowledge."<br />

(That this is so is made clear<br />

in the Sophist, 291cl-7. See Rosen, pp. 91-92.) This type of knowledge does<br />

not produce its object, which it only studies and does not alter or bring into<br />

being. Aristotle's examples are mathematics, physics, and first philosophy; for<br />

Plato the single best example is mathematics (see Aristotle's Metaphysics<br />

1026a8-22).<br />

A mathematical techne, such as geometry, "hands<br />

over" "catch"<br />

its<br />

to the<br />

dialectician. Dialectic in this passage refers to some form of meta-mathematical


eflection, e.g., the study of "number itself."<br />

Plato'<br />

The Serious Play of s Euthydemus 225<br />

It is not possible, given the single<br />

mention of dialectic, to determine what Plato here had in mind. It can only be<br />

stated that the passage posits the existence of some theoretical discipline that is<br />

higher than ordinary mathematics. (Of course. Republic VII discusses dialectic<br />

in these terms and at length. For an interesting discussion of this issue see<br />

Klein, pp. 21-49.)<br />

Analogous to the handing over of theoretical entities to the dialectician is the<br />

hunter of men, i.e., the general, who hands over his acquisitions to the pos<br />

sessor of the political techne, who presumably knows how to use them. As<br />

such, the political techne seems to be "the one we were seeking and the cause<br />

of correct acting in the city. And just (atechnos) as Aeschylus says, it alone<br />

would sit at the helm of the city, steering everything and commanding every<br />

useful"<br />

(291cl0-d3). Atechnos again appears at<br />

thing and making everything<br />

n. 3. This knowledge, the putative goal towards which the pro<br />

29 1 d 1 . See<br />

treptic urges, is then named "the kingly (basilike)<br />

"kingly<br />

techne"<br />

(291d7). On the<br />

art"<br />

see Statesman 305c ff. and Xenophon's Memorabilia IV. 2. 2 ff.).<br />

The serious work of protreptic now seems over, for the knowledge that<br />

Socrates has been exhorting Kleinias to seek appears to have been identified.<br />

Unfortunately, this hopeful appearance is soon shattered. When he and his<br />

mysterious interlocutor reconsidered the basilike techne, Socrates tells Krito,<br />

"we were totally ridiculous, just like children running after birds"<br />

(29 1 b I 2).<br />

Why? Because the attempt to identify the structure and specific object of this<br />

type of knowledge leads to an aporia.<br />

First it is agreed that the basilike and the politike techne are the same and<br />

that to it "the general's techne and all the rest hand over their results of which<br />

they<br />

use them"<br />

are the producers for it to rule on the grounds that it alone knows how to<br />

(291c7-9). But a question then arises: What result (ergon) does the<br />

basilike techne itself produce (29 1 e I ) ? The assumption here is that it has a<br />

determinate and therefore identifiable result, i.e., that it is analogous to an<br />

ordinary<br />

techne. But the assumption is faulty. A spokesman for medicine<br />

(291e5) or farming (291e8), for example, can identify<br />

that which results from<br />

his knowledge (health or food from the earth). If the basilike techne is truly<br />

analogous, then its spokesman should be able to do the same. But this Krito at<br />

least cannot do (292a6).<br />

Because they agreed that the basilike techne is beneficial, Socrates next<br />

asks, "Isn't it necessary that it supply us with some<br />

first protreptic argument established that "nothing<br />

good?"<br />

(292al 1). Since the<br />

else is good except knowl<br />

edge"<br />

(292b 1-2), all the results that one would typically point to when consid<br />

ering the politike techne, such as wealth for the citizens, freedom, and the<br />

absence of factionalism, are "neither good nor<br />

bad."<br />

Only<br />

if it can make the<br />

citizens wise (or good or happy) can this techne be considered truly beneficial<br />

(292b4-cl). Once again, however, this description of the basilike techne fails<br />

to satisfy, for as Socrates next asks. In what specific sense will it make men


226 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

good? Will it make all men good in all things? Since knowledge is the sole<br />

good,<br />

will it provide all forms of knowledge, including shoemaking, carpentry,<br />

and the rest (292c6-9)?<br />

The basic point is this: No determinate and identifiable ergon can be spe<br />

cified for the basilike techne. (Orwin discusses this issue in the context of the<br />

Cleitophon in quite helpful terms, and Blits has an interesting treatment of<br />

similar questions.) As shown by the first protreptic argument, it cannot issue in<br />

an ordinary result; if it did, it would end up being classified as a neutral item.<br />

The only knowledge, therefore, that it can provide is "of itself (292d3-4).<br />

This obscure formulation is not explained further. I shall return to it shortly.<br />

A final effort at describing the basilike techne is made: It makes other men<br />

good (292d5-6). But, asks Socrates, those men who are made good will be<br />

good with respect to what? The answer: they will be good only in making other<br />

men good. Of course, this just postpones the answer, for the question Good<br />

with respect to what? would surface again. The basic problem here is the same<br />

as that described above, namely that of determining the object of this techne.<br />

time Socrates<br />

The search for such an object is "labyrinthine"<br />

(291b7); every<br />

thinks he has found a way out (it makes the citizens wise, it makes them good)<br />

he discovers that the demand for specification (wise in what?, good at what?)<br />

amazes him again.<br />

This extraordinary section closes with Socrates saying, "Corinthus, Son of<br />

Zeus, the situation is exactly (atechnos) as I was describing it: we were still as<br />

far, if not further, from knowing what that knowledge is which would make us<br />

happy"<br />

(292e3-5).<br />

This confession of a serious theoretical aporia (292e6) is couched in playful<br />

terms. "The Scholiast on the passage relates that when Corinth had sent ambas<br />

sadors to Megara to complain of their revolt,<br />

the mythical founder 'Corinthus son of Zeus'<br />

one argument advanced was that<br />

would be aggrieved if they failed<br />

to exact condign punishment. The proverb came to be used of boastful repeti<br />

tions of the same<br />

story."<br />

So says Gifford. Unfortunately,<br />

neither he nor Haw-<br />

trey takes notice of the use of atechnos at 292e3. The issue of techne is the key<br />

here; therefore, the pun seems unavoidable. Socrates professes to be drowning<br />

in the third wave of the argument (293a3) and he calls upon the two old so<br />

phists to save him. This is ludicrous, for of all men they surely can provide no<br />

relief.<br />

V<br />

Serious problems plague Socrates'<br />

protreptic. In his first argument, the<br />

premises are questionable. Even if they are granted, his conclusion, that it is<br />

necessary to philosophize in order to be happy, is jeopardized by its obscurity.<br />

Just what is the wisdom we are told to love? This obscurity is amplified by


Socrates'<br />

Plato'<br />

The Serious Play of s Euthydemus 227<br />

second speech: there are intrinsic difficulties in the very notion of a<br />

basilike techne. How, then, can a target audience which is being<br />

exhorted to<br />

pursue wisdom even begin its quest? Are we forced to conclude that the pro<br />

treptic undermines itself? If so. then the Euthydemus would have to be counted<br />

as truly bizarre: The Socratic protreptic would really be "apotreptic"; it would<br />

turn people away from the pursuit of wisdom. (I coin "apotreptic."<br />

See Aristo<br />

tle's Rhetoric 1358b for his use of apotrope.) On this reading, Socrates the<br />

serious protrepticizer who accuses the sophists of only playing with words, fails<br />

to give good reasons why we should pursue philosophy rather than sophistry.<br />

I shall conclude this paper by showing why<br />

mine itself. It is true that Socrates'<br />

the protreptic does not under<br />

arguments end in an aporia from which he<br />

needs rescue. This is not, however, equivalent to failure because the arguments<br />

provide direction in how to perform the rescue operation. Kleinias,<br />

importantly we readers, are being<br />

and more<br />

called upon to respond to the aporia that<br />

Socrates has created for us. We are being called upon to philosophize.<br />

The most serious question raised by Socrates in the Euthydemus is, Is there a<br />

techne of arete? This can be twice reformulated: First, can there be a "using<br />

techne,"<br />

o.ie whose subject matter is the correct and beneficial application of<br />

neutral items in the human domain? The second refers back to the diagram in<br />

Section IV There the technai were divided into two kinds: the theoretical (ac<br />

quisitive) and the productive. The diagram, I propose, invites the question, Is<br />

there a third kind, namely<br />

the "practical,"<br />

which is possessed by the "political<br />

men"<br />

to whom the hunters of human animals hand over their catch ?s<br />

Given the<br />

basic assumption operative throughout the dialogue, namely<br />

that techne is the<br />

model for knowledge, and the problems sketched in the previous section, the<br />

answer would seem to be no.<br />

The epistemological lesson that the Euthydemus teaches is this: Knowledge<br />

of arete cannot be completely analogous to an ordinary techne. This is because<br />

the latter has a determinate object or result (ergon). Medicine studies health,<br />

farming<br />

studies the production of crops. There is no analogous object of the<br />

putative basilike techne. Apparently this is because its subject matter, arete or<br />

the good use of neutral items, is indeterminate. Socrates presents no explicit<br />

argument here (292c-e) as to why this is the case. It can be inferred, however,<br />

that it is because the items on the sample list, namely the objects typically<br />

deemed good by human beings, are themselves indeterminate. It would follow,<br />

then, that the question of their correct use would not allow for a determinate<br />

answer and so would not constitute a stable epistemological entity. This is why<br />

Socrates and his mysterious interlocutor repeatedly fail to identify a specific<br />

object for the basilike techne.6<br />

If techne is the only form of knowledge, then<br />

there can be no knowledge of arete and Socratic protreptic cannot be distin<br />

guished from sophistry.<br />

There is, however,<br />

nontechnical mode of knowledge.7<br />

a thread to lead us out of this maze: a conception of a<br />

I suggest two approaches to articulating


228 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

what it is. First, let us return to the obscure formulation that describes the<br />

basilike techne. It has, says Socrates, itself as an object. Second, let us con<br />

sider somewhat further the very nature of protreptic.<br />

The salient feature of Socrates'<br />

its circularity:<br />

search for the object of the basilike techne is<br />

When we reached the basilike techne and were examining it, to see if this techne<br />

was the one that supplied and produced eudaimonia, it was just as if we had fallen<br />

into a labyrinth: when we thought we had reached the end, we twisted around again<br />

and appeared to be again at the very beginning of our search and just as much in<br />

need as we were when we began searching (291b4-c2).<br />

Why is this search circular? Given the premises of the argument, the basilike<br />

techne must supply something good. But what good is this? Given the results of<br />

the first protreptic argument, the answer must be knowledge. But knowledge of<br />

what? Of that which is good. But the good is knowledge: hence, the circularity.<br />

The basilike techne, which we now know is no ordinary techne at all, is then<br />

described as follows:<br />

It is necessary that it be a producer of no result, either good or bad; instead, it<br />

must transmit no knowledge other than that of itself (292dl-4).<br />

Possessors of typical technai study and then teach about (or produce) an<br />

object that is distinct from the technai themselves: The doctor teaches about the<br />

workings of the human body, the carpenter about the production of furniture<br />

from wood (see Charmides 165c: episteme [or technelis episteme tinos). Is<br />

there an analogous object of the basilike techne? One is tempted to answer,<br />

Yes, it is arete. But this is not quite right, for at least insofar as we pertain to<br />

the conclusion of Socrates'<br />

first protreptic, what this knowledge knows is only<br />

that knowledge of arete ought to be sought. When this knowledge that knowl<br />

edge of arete ought to be sought is transmitted to students, they are equipped<br />

only to exhort others to seek it.<br />

This is quite peculiar: Those who learn their Socratic lessons know nothing<br />

other than how to exhort others to love "wisdom."<br />

only<br />

Their wisdom is manifested<br />

in their knowledge that wisdom is lovable. Protreptic teaches the student<br />

only how to protrepticize; like the labryinthine aporia, it is circular. Or, in<br />

other words, it has no object distinct from itself.<br />

Socrates exhorts his listeners to pursue arete, that is, to philosophize. As<br />

suggested in Section I, however, such an exhortation appeals only to those<br />

already persuaded that the traditional purveyors of arete are insufficient and that<br />

knowledge is therefore worth seeking. In this sense, Socrates does not teach his<br />

audience anything new; his protreptic "goes<br />

only to those already "protrepticized."<br />

nowhere"<br />

for it is able to speak<br />

As explicated in Section III, the prem<br />

ises of his argument that human beings are free and rational agents and that


The Serious Play of Plato's Euthydemus 229<br />

the use of neutral items can be known as correct/good are undefended. Ac<br />

ceptance of the conclusion, that it is necessary to philosophize, therefore re<br />

quires that the audience be predisposed to accept the premises. In other words,<br />

the audience must already be predisposed to commence the search for objective<br />

knowledge, i.e., to philosophize. I propose that this is why the search for the<br />

determinate object of the basilike techne falters and why it is said to teach only<br />

itself.<br />

To reiterate the basic question, Does the circularity of the protreptic render it<br />

vacuous? No. Socrates does accomplish something significant: He reinforces<br />

and explicates a desire that is present in his audience. To clarify, imagine<br />

presenting<br />

Socrates'<br />

first protreptic argument. Its conclusion takes the form of<br />

an imperative (which I paraphrase): Turn away from your typical concerns,<br />

care about arete and love wisdom. The audience can respond in at least three<br />

ways. (1) They can reject such exhortation by dogmatically asserting that they<br />

are, for example, Christians and don't need help. (2) They can object to it and<br />

demand reasons why they should follow such advice. (3) They can heed the<br />

argument's imperative.<br />

Options (2) and (3)<br />

are similar: Those who ask for reasons are philosophiz<br />

ing. (This is reminiscent of the protreptical argument attributed to Aristotle:<br />

those who argue against philosophy are philosophizing. See the 'Testimonia"<br />

collected by During, p. 44.) Furthermore, both groups, those represented by (2)<br />

and (3), are similarly predisposed to philosophize. As discussed in Section III,<br />

the argument itself fails to provide satisfying reasons to philosophize. In other<br />

words, it cannot be said to produce (rationally)<br />

a new disposition to philoso<br />

phize in the target audience. In this sense protreptic is only effective with those<br />

who are already "protrepticized."<br />

What then does protreptic accomplish? It provides an occasion, as well as<br />

guidance in how, to philosophize. It addresses someone, like young Kleinias,<br />

who already is impelled to discover knowledge and encourages him to consum<br />

mate that desire. Furthermore, the argument teaches him how to do so. In<br />

particular, it points him in the direction of nontechnical knowledge. Techne is<br />

the pivot around which the protreptic revolves. Understood in a comprehensive<br />

sense, it provides a conceptual framework, such as that diagrammed in Section<br />

IV, within which ordinary knowledge can be classified. This framework allows<br />

someone like Kleinias to understand what is required to consummate his desire<br />

for knowledge of how to use neutral items correctly, i.e., for knowledge of<br />

arete. It shows him that the ordinary<br />

goal. What he really wants is a "higher"<br />

technai are insufficient to accomplish his<br />

form of knowledge, one that is non<br />

technical and somehow able to understand how to use the items on the sample<br />

list. Socrates does not identify this knowledge; as a result, and as Socrates<br />

himself admits, the Euthydemus is aporetic even maddening.<br />

The Socratic protreptic is not vacuous because in and of itself it represents a<br />

nontrivial form of knowledge. If its premises are granted, then it follows that


230 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

the typical things we normally desire (those on the sample list)<br />

are neutral and<br />

not good. It shows that if knowledge of the correct use of these neutral items is<br />

possible which it may not be then it is also desirable as the condition for<br />

happiness. It should be remembered, however, that the target audience of the<br />

protreptic already desires such knowledge. Therefore, at least implicitly, they<br />

assume it is possible. As a result, the protreptic directs the desires latent in the<br />

target audience; it urges them to turn away from more typical desires and pur<br />

sue wisdom. It shows how a most untraditional and therefore potentially alien<br />

ating desire, for wisdom, can be transformed into a coherent activity that can<br />

produce a happier life.<br />

To reformulate: Socrates fails to prove that philosophy is an unconditional<br />

good. The necessity found in the conclusion of the protreptic It is necessary<br />

to philosophize does not bind everybody. In particular, the injunction is not<br />

binding for those who would join Euthydemus and Dionysodorus in rejecting<br />

Premises (5) and (6) (that correct use is an objective property of neutral things<br />

and can be learned). <strong>Philosophy</strong>, then, is only conditionally good, and the<br />

necessity<br />

expressed in the protreptic conclusion is hypothetical, //one is predis<br />

posed to philosophize and to question the traditional purveyors of arete, then<br />

one must philosophize in order to be happy. This is a crucial lesson for some<br />

one like Kleinias. Unlike other associates of Socrates such as Charmides,<br />

Critias, and Alcibiades, whose criminal behavior discloses their willingness to<br />

call into question the traditional sense of arete, Kleinias should pursue philoso<br />

phy. He should seek the higher, the nontechnical form of knowledge, and he<br />

has been provided with a framework to begin doing so.<br />

In sum, the Socratic protreptic teaches a kind of self-knowledge, knowledge<br />

of the nature and consequences of those desires that belong to the student open<br />

to the protreptic. It invites the student into the project of philosophy, an activity<br />

to which he is already predisposed, and thereby teaches him how to attain<br />

eudaimonia. Protreptic itself thus manifests a kind of nontechnical knowledge:<br />

It does not have a determinate object other than itself. Its object is itself; that is,<br />

it is the study of the desire that wishes to know about arete. Other technai make<br />

discernible progress: one can move from ignorance of carpentry to skill by<br />

studying with a master. This is why the ordinary technai are easily recognized<br />

and usually admired. There is no analogous progress in the study of arete. Only<br />

one who already knows can be taught. But knows what? That knowledge of<br />

arete is desirable.<br />

NOTES<br />

1. My text is Burnet's Oxford edition. Translations are my own. Support from the State of<br />

Iowa, the Joyce Foundation, and the Northwest Area Foundation allowed me the time to work on<br />

this project. Professor David Sedley and an anonymous reader made many valuable comments on<br />

an earlier draft of this paper for which I am grateful.


The Serious Play of Plato'<br />

s Euthydemus 231<br />

2. An example comes from H. Keulen, who contrasts himself with Meridier,<br />

"L'Euthydeme est une comedie. avec son decor et ses<br />

who wrote:<br />

aceurs,'<br />

lautet einers der vielen Urteile, die<br />

den platonischen Euthydem als ein Ergenis spielerischer Laune Platons betrachtet sehen wollen.<br />

Dass der dialog jedoch sehr ernest zu nehmen ist, weiss man allerdings ebenso lange"<br />

(pp. 4-5).<br />

Or consider Leo Strauss, who describes the Euthydemus as "bantering, not to say frivolous and<br />

farcical"<br />

(p. 1) but then goes on to explain why he thinks the dialogue is extremely serious. In fact,<br />

because of the mention of Socrates'<br />

daimonion at 272e, Strauss says of the dialogue: "No other<br />

conversation presented by Plato has so high an<br />

origin"<br />

(p. 3).<br />

3. That the sophists do not possess such a techne is playfully indicated with the phrase Socrates<br />

uses to describe them: they are, he says, "passophoi<br />

where (1987, pp. 255-63), Plato consistently<br />

"without<br />

atechnos"<br />

(271c6). As I have argued else<br />

puns with atechnos; that is, he uses it to mean<br />

techne."<br />

R.S.W. Hawtrey comments extensively on passophoi in this passage but neglects<br />

to mention the pun with atechnos. The same is true in E.H. Gifford's edition.<br />

4. This statement does not mention any of the problems normally associated with the naturalis<br />

tic fallacy.<br />

5. This discussion is informed by<br />

physics 1026a8-22.<br />

Aristotle's tripartite division of the epistemai. See Meta<br />

6. The key question this paper raises is, Is arete, is the human good, determinate? There is a<br />

little joke at Statesman 266b which indicates my own position: the nature of the human race is like<br />

the diagonal of the unit square, i.e., indeterminate. I would argue that this holds for arete but I<br />

understand that a lengthy discussion is required.<br />

7. There are at least two other threads to lead us out of the labyrinth. As numerous commenta<br />

tors have proposed, there might be a techne of arete, if this can be understood in a "second-order"<br />

sense. R. Sprague (1976) most clearly expresses this position. She argues that the basilike techne<br />

art"<br />

represents a "second-order which "directs"<br />

made"<br />

or "knows how to use the things by other<br />

"arts"<br />

(p. 55). On her reading, even though the Euthydemus ends in an aporia, later dialogues<br />

actually express this higher or second-order knowledge.<br />

I think Sprague's position is seriously flawed. Her solution sounds plausible, but it ignores what<br />

I suggest is the critical problem: In what sense can the "first-order"<br />

an object of a "second-order"<br />

(or ordinary) technai function as<br />

techne? What exact kind of object would it be and why wouldn't it<br />

simply recapitulate the same problems discussed here? Furthermore, if this is really the type of<br />

knowledge that Plato has in mind, then why did he only describe or allude to it in the early<br />

dialogues and never clearly explain or illustrate il in the later ones? Sprague is extremely vague<br />

about such questions. This is damaging for her argument because techne is precisely that mode of<br />

knowledge whose object is clear and determinate and should therefore be readily explained. As a<br />

result, her solution, while inviting, simply postulates a hope that the aporia can be resolved.<br />

I mention Sprague in particular here because of all the many commentators who hold a similar<br />

thesis, she is the most systematic and clear. There is a mountain of literature on this subject. For<br />

representative views, all of which are similar to Sprague's, see Kato (1988), Kube (1967), and<br />

Irwin (1977).<br />

Another thread leading out of the labyrinth here is that of K. Gaiser (1959). Simply put, his<br />

thesis is that the dialogues are exoteric exhortations towards wisdom, while the positive teaching<br />

was esoteric.<br />

REFERENCES<br />

Blits, Jan. "Socratic Teaching<br />

321-34.<br />

and Justice: Plato's Cleitophon."<br />

<strong>Interpretation</strong> 13(1985):<br />

Diels, Hermann. Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Berlin: Weidmannsche, 1959.<br />

During, Ingemar. Aristotle's Protrepticus. Goteborg, 1961.<br />

Friedlander, P. Plato. 3 vols. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1958-69.


232 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Gaiser, K. Protreptik und Paranese bei Platon. Tubingen: Kohlhammer, 1959.<br />

Hawtrey, R.S.W. Commentary on Plato's Euthydemus. Philadelphia: American Philo<br />

sophical Society, 1981.<br />

Irwin, Terence. Plato'<br />

s Moral Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977.<br />

Kato, Morimichi. Techne und Philosophie bei Platon. Frankfurt: Lang, 1988.<br />

Keulen, H. Untersuchungen zu Platons Euthydem. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz, 1971.<br />

Klein, Jacob. Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra. Cambridge, MA:<br />

MIT Press, 1968.<br />

Kneale, W. and M. The Development of Logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984.<br />

Kube, Jorge. Techne und Arete. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1967.<br />

Mohr, R. "Forms in Plato's Euthydemus."<br />

Hermes 112(1984): 296-300.<br />

Nussbaum, Martha. The Fragility of Goodness. Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1986.<br />

Orwin, Clifford. "The Case Against Socrates: Plato's Cleitophon."<br />

Political Science 15(1982): 741-53.<br />

Peck, A. R. "Plato and the MEGISTA GENE of the Sophist."<br />

2(1952): 32-56.<br />

Canadian Journal of<br />

Classical Quarterly<br />

Plato, Euthydemus. In Platonis Opera, edited by<br />

University Press, 1900-1907.<br />

Works, edited by E.H. Gifford. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1905.<br />

Praechter, K. "Platon und Euthydemus."<br />

Roochnik, David. "Plato's Use of ATECHNOS."<br />

John Burnet. 5 vols. Oxford: Oxford<br />

Philologus 87(1932): 121-35.<br />

Phoenix 44(1987): 255-63.<br />

"The Riddle of Plato's Cleitophon."<br />

Ancient <strong>Philosophy</strong> 4(1984): 212-20.<br />

Rosen, Stanley. Plato's Sophist. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1983.<br />

Sprague, R.K. "Parmenides'<br />

Sail and<br />

Dionysodorus' Ox."<br />

"A Platonic Parallel in the Dissoi Logoi."<br />

6(1968): 160-61.<br />

1976.<br />

.. Plato's<br />

Phronesis 12(1967): 91-98.<br />

Journal of the History of <strong>Philosophy</strong><br />

Plato's Philosopher-King. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press,<br />

Use of Fallacy. New York: Barnes and Noble, 1962.<br />

Stewart, M. A. "Plato's Sophistry."<br />

Strauss, Leo. "On the Euthydemus."<br />

Szlezak, T.A. "Sokrates'<br />

Spott uber Geheimhaltung."<br />

The Aristotelian Society, S.V. LI (1977).<br />

<strong>Interpretation</strong> 1(1970): 1-20.<br />

Antike und Abendland 26(1980).<br />

Knowledge."<br />

Woodruff, Paul. "Plato's Early Theory of In Greek Epistemology, edited<br />

by S. Lrverson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.


The Wisdom of Plato's Aristophanes<br />

Charles Salman<br />

Trinity University<br />

Even if, like so much ancient biography, the story is not factually reliable,<br />

something truthful is nonetheless captured in the tale that Olympiodorus tells,<br />

that Aristophanes'<br />

comedies were found tucked away under the pillow of<br />

Plato's deathbed (2.66-72). To Nietzsche the ancients conveyed in this story<br />

something of Plato's secret nature (Beyond Good and Evil, sec. 28), although<br />

in the Symposium Plato's fondness for Aristophanes appears rather more<br />

openly, in the almost triumphant power that he grants to Aristophanes'<br />

speech.<br />

It is an age-old sentiment that "Aristophanes is second only to Socrates in<br />

his grasp of the mysteries of love"<br />

willingly saw his own erotic theory<br />

(Brentlinger, p. 12),<br />

prefigured in Aristophanes'<br />

and Freud himself<br />

mythical<br />

speech (esp. pp. 51-52; cf. below and Santas, pp. 155, 157, 160-62). Indeed<br />

one frequently<br />

finds Aristophanes'<br />

myth to be the best-remembered of all the<br />

speeches in the Symposium, and even those who see it transcended by<br />

tonic account often assign it a key<br />

propaedeutic place.1<br />

a Pla<br />

How are we to understand this Platonic admiration for Aristophanes? As a<br />

preparatory step<br />

we might point to the sense in which the poet and the philoso<br />

pher shared a picture of their world, a world evoked for us, at least in a synop<br />

tic way, as we recall the<br />

background of the Symposium.<br />

"political"<br />

concerns that Plato has written into the<br />

The significance for philosophy of the moment in time depicted by the dia<br />

two historical events. In<br />

logue could be said to be broadly circumscribed by<br />

deed in the dramatic imagery of the dialogue, the philosopher is surrounded by<br />

them: on the one side, the recent crowning of Agathon as poet laureate of the<br />

day and on the other, the imminent expedition to Sicily under Alcibiades, the<br />

turning<br />

point in Athens'<br />

precipitous fall in the Peloponnesian War. If the dia<br />

logue even intimates a kind of genetic connection between the two as if the<br />

advent of sophistry were the prelude to complete and utter ruin it would seem<br />

more systematically still to recreate the stages leading up to that final fall. As<br />

we move from the heroic life of the Phaedrean battlefield, to the more "com<br />

plex"<br />

(poikilos) legal codifications of Pausanias'<br />

cities, to Eryximachus'<br />

intro<br />

duction of all of the technai that proliferate within them and as we finally<br />

move on to the creative arts and the exquisite civilities of Agathonian poiesis<br />

we bear witness to a kind of symbolic structural analysis of the rise or<br />

"ascent"<br />

of Athenian culture. But Plato at the same time casts aspersions on the internal<br />

dynamic of this ascent: If only most explicitly by the character of this culture's<br />

interpretation, Winter 1990-1991, Vol. 18, No. 2


234 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

reigning "wise<br />

man"<br />

and by the portentous acclaim (213a) for the archon of its<br />

disastrous end (Alcibiades), Plato evokes our recognition that this ascent has<br />

been ambiguous at best, that this increasing<br />

"sophistication"<br />

culture is at the same time a kind of degenerate "softening"<br />

on the part of<br />

en route to com<br />

plete decline. It is thus no accident that apalos and its cognates cross Agathon s<br />

lips some fourteen times in his speech. The victory of Agathon stands at that<br />

imaginary moment when Athens finally identifies wisdom with the offspring of<br />

Gorgias, or (taking our cue from the meaning of Agathon's name) openly cele<br />

brates a sophistical "good."2<br />

At least in certain of its broadest features, the cultural assessment in the<br />

background of the Symposium was shared by<br />

focusing<br />

the historical Aristophanes. The<br />

of our attention on the dimsightedness of the war we find above all in<br />

the Lysistrata. The dubious character of the new learning (and in particular of<br />

the new scientific technai and the crowning product of their ethos, sophistry)<br />

are the central concerns of the paradoxically Platonic though anti-Socratic<br />

Clouds. Eryximachus, of course, is one locus of this shared reflection in the<br />

Symposium, and<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

facetious derision of his reductive physicalism<br />

(on behalf of the old "gods") has been frequently pointed out. If the attack in<br />

the Clouds on Athenian legalism is to be located in the Symposium, we must<br />

surely think first of all of the discourse of Pausanias, the other symposiast, in<br />

addition to Eryximachus, to whom Aristophanes specifically addresses himself<br />

(189c). Even the symbolic centrality of Agathon in the Symposium has its ana<br />

logue in Aristophanes, in the comic motif of the "softness"<br />

the young tragedian<br />

represents in the Thesmophoriazusae (cf. esp. 140ff., 191-92, 200, 206, and<br />

n. 4 below).<br />

The basic kinship between the comic and the philosopher that is grounded in<br />

these shared concerns seems reflected in the role Plato gives to Aristophanes in<br />

the workings of the Symposium. From the ambiguous unfolding of Athenian<br />

culture subtextually chronicled in the<br />

man striving, Aristophanes'<br />

symposiasts'<br />

collective logos about hu<br />

speech is thus made to stand apart. On the most<br />

concrete level he stands apart in the way that the comedian stands apart from or<br />

outside of his culture, as one who reflects back and ridicules, rather than un<br />

consciously adopts, the prevailing conventions of the times. So it is that right<br />

away we perceive in Aristophanes something<br />

of the "wisened<br />

cynic,"<br />

standing<br />

ironically aloof from the others while mocking, and in that sense critiquing<br />

them. As Aristophanes played the critic in historical Athens so Plato seems to<br />

grant him a similar honor here, allowing Aristophanes to claim for himself, in<br />

role.3<br />

the dialectic of the Symposium, something of a special<br />

But what more precisely is the nature of the special role to which Aris<br />

tophanes here lays claim? Curiously enough, we can bring it to light by attend<br />

ing to something he has in common with the other speakers, to the sense in<br />

which Aristophanes'<br />

encomium, like those of the others, is covertly a praise of<br />

the speaker himself. In a still intriguing paper on the Symposium, Helen Bacon<br />

identified this basic "principle"<br />

that governs the various speeches on eros:


The Wisdom of Plato'<br />

s Aristophanes 235<br />

There is, however, a kind of principle behind the manner of their praising, and that<br />

is that each man sees love in terms of his own profession. Phaedrus and Pausanias,<br />

the rhetorician and the sociologist, see Eros as a kind of supersophist, engaged in<br />

what the sophists considered one of their main occupations, the teaching of virtue.<br />

Characteristically, Phaedrus bases his speech on Homer and Hesiod and the tragic<br />

poets, Pausanias on the evidence of actual practice in religious cult and social<br />

institutions; to Eryximachus Eros is the universal doctor; to Aristophanes he pre<br />

sents himself as the explanation of man's comic predicament; to Agathon he is the<br />

greatest of poets. And all of them are happily unconscious of the fact that it is not<br />

love that they are praising but themselves (p. 429).<br />

From this point of view at least one major feature of the encomia is what we<br />

might call their self-referential and self-gratifying character, and one clue to<br />

their interpretation comes from attending to the lives of the individuals who are<br />

their veiled, though perhaps all the more immediate and determining, referents.<br />

To Professor Bacon's sketch we might thus briefly add the following particu<br />

lars: To young Phaedrus, the beloved of Eryximachus, Eros is a "great<br />

the source of virtue and "anything<br />

really<br />

great and<br />

god,"<br />

noble,"<br />

and its elevating power<br />

resides in the beloved youth or eromenos who inspires all manner of<br />

courageousness and valor in his lover. In battle even a "low<br />

moved by the power of love to be "like those who are best by<br />

great is the inspirational power of the beloved that lovers are "willing<br />

their<br />

beloveds." Phaedrus'<br />

man"<br />

can be<br />

nature,"<br />

and so<br />

to die for<br />

narcissistic phantasy about the power of the beloved<br />

reaches a kind of peroration in his celebration of Achilles (with whom we can<br />

by now imagine that Phaedrus identifies himself), who young and beardless<br />

(180a) was "more glorious . . than all the heroes put together."<br />

As an older erastes Pausanias takes exception to this simplistic (cf. 180c4:<br />

haplos)<br />

compelling<br />

view. Though Eros is indeed what "urges us toward noble<br />

us to "show great concern for our<br />

action,"<br />

virtue,"<br />

it shows itself properly<br />

not in the "pandemic"<br />

young boy but in the noble pedagogy of the more intel<br />

ligent older lover. Indeed, simply left to its natural devices eros is an ambig<br />

uous and potentially errant phenomenon, and it is only turned to the good by<br />

virtue of sophisticated institutions and the "complex"<br />

Athenian elders.<br />

While preserving Pausanias'<br />

machus, the doctor, ascends to a rather more<br />

approach. Beginning "from the medical point of<br />

principle operating in all of nature,<br />

(poikilos)<br />

nomoi of the<br />

sense of the duplicity of eros (186a), Eryxi<br />

"universal"<br />

and indeed scientific<br />

view"<br />

(186b) he sees eros as a<br />

and so at work in the spheres of all the<br />

various arts and sciences: medicine, gymnastic, agriculture, music, physics,<br />

astronomy, and divination. In all these domains accomplishing good is a matter<br />

of reconciling or balancing opposites, of making "the most antagonistic ele<br />

ments . friendly and<br />

loving"<br />

(186d). The one who has knowledge (episteme)<br />

of these love forces is able to impose "harmony and<br />

order"<br />

upon a poly-<br />

morphously baneful physis (cf. 188a6 ff.), so that through the contrivances of


236 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

mortal techne the man of science becomes likened to a veritable cosmic "demi<br />

urge"<br />

(cf. 186d4, 187d4).<br />

This metaphysical conceit and autoeroticism reaches finally a sort of cul<br />

thousand"<br />

mination in the speech of Agathon, the beloved of "thirty<br />

(175e) at<br />

the festival of Dionysus and poet laureate of Athens. Thus not only is Eros the<br />

most "gifted of<br />

things come into being<br />

poets"<br />

(196e) and so the creator by virtue of which "all living<br />

and develop"<br />

(197a2-3), but his various other attributes<br />

are all conspicuously recognizable as those of Agathon himself: He is the "most<br />

beautiful"<br />

(195a6), the "youngest"<br />

(195bl), "soft"<br />

ple"<br />

(196a2: hugros).4<br />

(195dl: hapalos), and "sup<br />

Indeed the beautiful poiesis that issues from Eros has<br />

"brought forth all good things that exist for gods and<br />

engendering<br />

a time of "affection and<br />

men"<br />

(197b8) and in<br />

peace"<br />

(195c5) has put an end to the harsh<br />

rule of Necessity (195c, 197b). The self-referential principle that has been at<br />

work throughout thus becomes virtually explicit in Agathon's speech, and Plato<br />

seems to underscore the importance of this feature of the encomium by having<br />

Apollodorus break into the narrative at its end: "When Agathon had finished,<br />

Aristodemus said, the people who were present applauded the speech which<br />

was so becoming to the young man who had given it, as well as the<br />

(198a).<br />

But what are we to say here about self-praise in Aristophanes'<br />

god"<br />

mythical<br />

speech? Is there likewise a principle of self-reference at work in the comedian's<br />

account of eros? Professor Bacon surely captures something promising here in<br />

saying that Aristophanic eros serves as "the explanation of man's comic predic<br />

ament,"<br />

since it explains why we are so hopelessly and obsessively preoccupied<br />

with joining<br />

and "melding"<br />

our bodies with that of another. So archaic and<br />

almighty is this erotic pathos (cf. 189d5) that all other aspects of life are finally<br />

subordinated to its end (191b), and indeed are possible only by virtue of its<br />

prior satisfaction, in periods of satiation and respite. As one only really appre<br />

ciates the "power"<br />

of eros when one sees this comical human situation,<br />

logos on eros makes a claim for the "power"<br />

the comical perspective.5<br />

In this sense Aristophanes'<br />

aim at a praise of "his own<br />

of the wisdom finally<br />

so this<br />

inherent in<br />

exposition doubtless does<br />

profession."<br />

But this is indeed only the surface of the speech's self-referential dimension.<br />

As we now reflect more closely on the particulars of Aristophanes'<br />

comical<br />

speech, we will begin to see just how much he would claim for himself in<br />

giving us this exposition and the internal specificity<br />

with which his praise of<br />

eros turns out to be implicitly self-referential. According to Aristophanes'<br />

ollective myth, the original circle-people mounted an assault against Olympus.<br />

In order to "stop their licentiousness"<br />

190c7: mekhanen) the plan of cutting them in two,<br />

rec-<br />

(190dl: akolasias). Zeus contrived (cf.<br />

sent in Apollo and "he told him to heal (190e4: iasthai) them<br />

sewed up their bodies, leaving<br />

smoothing out the wrinkles the way<br />

and after he split them he<br />

up."<br />

So Apollo<br />

the navel at the middle of the stomach and<br />

shoemakers do on lasts. The operation


would make them "more<br />

The Wisdom of Plato'<br />

s Aristophanes 237<br />

orderly"<br />

(190e4: kosmioteros). All the same, men<br />

began dying off in this condition (since each longed only to reunite with its<br />

other half), so Zeus himself performed a kind of second operation, "setting<br />

their genitals around in front of them"<br />

to prosthen) that they might propagate with one another.<br />

(191b5: metatithesin auton ta aidoia eis<br />

These events bear a striking similarity to the events of the Symposium itself.<br />

Like the very contrivance of Zeus himself, Aristophanes'<br />

progressing circle. This splitting, in effect,<br />

Eryximachus, technician and "demiurge"<br />

harmonization of physis indeed tries to "heal"<br />

intended to make men "more<br />

only<br />

hiccups halve the<br />

causes him to send in the doctor<br />

of the body, whose speech about the<br />

orderly"<br />

things up. That the surgery is<br />

underscores the reference to Eryx<br />

imachus whom Aristophanes has recently detected in his predilection for "the<br />

orderly"<br />

(cf. 189a: to kosmion) and the language of whose speech clearly<br />

makes him its particular partisan. Then comes the discourse of Aristophanes.<br />

On its deepest level it tries to recall the symposiasts to the "power"<br />

that is<br />

implicit in the yearning of their sexuality. Like Zeus in the myth Aristophanes<br />

himself now tries to "set their genitals around in front of<br />

discovery<br />

them."<br />

With the<br />

of this level of self-reference in his speech we begin to see the true<br />

grandeur of Aristophanes'<br />

praise of "his own<br />

self-image and indeed just how far-reaching<br />

is his<br />

profession"<br />

since with his comic exposition Aristophanes<br />

claims to be bringing to bear the Zeus.6<br />

very wisdom and justice of<br />

That Zeus should serve as symbol for the object of wisdom should greet us<br />

with no overwhelming surprise. At the beginning of his description of the ce<br />

lestial procession which leads to the "hyperouranian<br />

that "true being"<br />

region,"<br />

the place where<br />

dwells in terms of which the realm of genesis is to be under<br />

stood, Socrates announces: "And behold, there in the heaven Zeus, mighty<br />

leader, drives his winged team, first of the host to proceed, ordering all things<br />

and caring therefore<br />

"<br />

(Phaedrus 246e: ho men de megas hegemon en<br />

ouranoi Zeus, elaynon ptenon harma, protos poreuetai, diakosmon panta kai<br />

epimeloumenos .<br />

. .). To<br />

Hackforth this passage is "noteworthy as being the<br />

earliest intimation of the central doctrine of Plato's theology .<br />

.<br />

"<br />

(p. 71).<br />

Whether the presence of Zeus in the Symposium leads us to see this central<br />

doctrine intimated still earlier or whether we follow those who would argue that<br />

the Phaedrus is earlier than the Symposium need not concern us here (see<br />

Moore). What we need is to understand something of the substance of that<br />

"central doctrine."<br />

Hackforth is surely right in connecting the present passage to Socrates'<br />

in the Philebus about the nous that is basileus hemin ouranou te kai ges (28c).<br />

This "intelligence"<br />

. . (aitia) that<br />

that is "king<br />

of heaven and<br />

talk<br />

earth,"<br />

this "presiding cause<br />

orders and arranges (kosmousa te kai suntattousa) the years, the<br />

called sophia kai<br />

nous"<br />

(30c) Socrates<br />

seasons, and the months, and is justly<br />

clearly connects with the figure of Zeus at 30d. In making a fuller investigation<br />

of what<br />

"sort"<br />

this nous is, Socrates asks Protarchus:


238 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

"Are we to say, Protarchus, that the sum of things (sumpanta) or what we call the<br />

whole (holon) is governed by<br />

kai eikei dunamin), and so by mere chance (etukhen), or on the contrary to follow<br />

a power that is senseless and without purpose (alogou<br />

our predecessors in saying that it is steered through by intelligence and a wondrous<br />

wisdom (noun kai phronesin tina thaumasten suntattousan diakuber-<br />

governing<br />

nan)V (28d)<br />

As the "nous"<br />

which "orders all things and cares therefore"<br />

(diakosmon panta<br />

kai epimeloumenos) , Zeus is the personification of that law which governs over<br />

"heaven and the necessity which regulates the movements of "the<br />

years, the seasons and the<br />

months"<br />

or finally, the mindful "power"<br />

which<br />

arranges measures and order for life, growth, and healing (cf. Phil. 30a9-b8)<br />

in the cosmos. Zeus is thus the overseeing principle which animates the realm<br />

of genesis, or in language perhaps more appropriate to the mythical image, the<br />

Will behind all of physis. Aristophanes'<br />

claim to introducing<br />

the wisdom of<br />

Zeus is thus tantamount to the claim to seeing beyond opinion or the strictures<br />

of human nomos to the divine law or truth which resides in and animates nature<br />

itself.7<br />

How are we now to evaluate Aristophanes'<br />

implicit self-praise, his sublime<br />

claim, in the dramatic metaphor of the dialogue, to bringing to bear the wisdom<br />

of Zeus? The answer, I think, is not to be sought in a simple condemnation and<br />

dismissal. When we reflect on the critical role Plato has assigned Aristophanes<br />

in the context of the speeches of his fellow symposiasts, we are moved, rather,<br />

to adopt an attitude considerably more ambivalent, and to appreciate the sense<br />

in which Aristophanes'<br />

Olympian self-image does have a kind of legitimacy<br />

even if, in Plato's last analysis, Aristophanes fails to make good on his claim.<br />

What then is the substance of Aristophanes'<br />

comical critique? Aristophanes<br />

sees how Pausanias and Eryximachus, while appearing to praise Eros, really<br />

praise the controls that the human artifices of nomos and techne can have over<br />

it, and so honor not so much the divine power of Eros as the all-too-human<br />

powers of reason and logos. In this sense he recognizes precisely their claim to<br />

having<br />

transcended the power of physis: the self-praise of the symposiasts is<br />

thus mirrored in the self-praise of the culture of which they are the Platonic<br />

icons. Aristophanes "contrives,"<br />

as it were, to "stop their licentiousness."<br />

his recollective tale of the power by with which eros moves us to "joining"<br />

"melding"<br />

with one another, he decisively recalls us to the "power"<br />

With<br />

and<br />

of sexual<br />

desire, and in this sense compels our recognition of that erotic Necessity which<br />

transcends mortal dominion.<br />

Indeed Aristophanes'<br />

attack. The<br />

hiccups had already anticipated the substance of his<br />

symposiasts'<br />

project begins with a proposal by Eryximachus, that<br />

rather than drinking the party be devoted to the giving of speeches about eros.<br />

Moving next that they dismiss the flute girl (who might ordinarily have been<br />

pressed into sexual service at the drunken conclusion of the party), he suggests


Plato'<br />

The Wisdom of s Aristophanes - 239<br />

that on this occasion they "consort with one another through<br />

speeche<br />

instead<br />

(cf. 176e7: dia logon allelois suneinai). In view of the circumspect sexual<br />

sense of sunousia the meaning of the scene is clear : In the project thus being<br />

symbolically inaugurated by the symposiasts, the sobriety of logos is to take the<br />

place of or supersede the errancy of eros. Just as the orderly procession of logoi<br />

at the party caricature the claims of culture to have imposed order on unruly<br />

nature, so Aristophanes'<br />

disruptive hiccups anticipate what he will attempt to<br />

show by his critique : that for all its apparent establishment of dominion, hu<br />

man<br />

"order"<br />

is still subordinate to a yet stronger "power,"<br />

versive and intractable will of natural necessity.<br />

the potentially sub<br />

Both in ergoi and in logoi Aristophanes thus incarnates his satiric wisdom in<br />

the Symposium, opposing a kind of hybris on the part of culture with a recollec<br />

tion of the rule of Necessity. Recalling us to the "power"<br />

by<br />

which we are<br />

inextricably tethered to our mortal nature, he would reorient our thinking to<br />

ward a remembrance of "the<br />

gods"<br />

or the transcendence within physis. In thus<br />

recalling the rule of Necessity and undoing the injustice of the mortal rebellion<br />

against it, Aristophanes indeed acts to forestall an "assault against Olympus,"<br />

and his comedy becomes likened to a contrivance for the preservation of the<br />

rule of Zeus. In this sense Aristophanes'<br />

on its Olympian claim.<br />

comical wisdom seems to make good<br />

But the drama of the Symposium alone is enough to cast doubt on the ulti<br />

mate legitimacy<br />

of Aristophanes'<br />

claim : Despite the pronounced antisophistry<br />

of the comic Aristophanes, the reigning poet is the Gorgian Agathon. With the<br />

ascension of Agathon comes the final phase of the assault by mortal hybris, and<br />

the rebellion against Necessity here becomes most explicit and complete :<br />

declares that the ancient reign of Ananke is over if<br />

Agathon finally openly<br />

indeed those earlier writers who once told of its dominion were even telling the<br />

truth (cf. 195c, 197b). Justice is now to be located in agreement among men<br />

since "what one person willingly agrees on with another is just and the saying<br />

'the nomoi are king of the<br />

of Gorgias'<br />

city'right."<br />

is (Agathon quotes Alcidamas, a rhetor<br />

school. Cf. Aristotle, Rhet. 1406a 17-23.) As such "agreement"<br />

can seemingly be secured through the persuasive techniques of mortal speech,<br />

the students of Gorgias thus lay claim to having discovered the hegemony of<br />

mortal will and to having supplanted the archaic rule of physis by the kingship<br />

of conventional consensus. The nomoi of Pausanias and the technai of Eryx<br />

imachus are in this sense wedded and raised to their highest potential. At the<br />

culmination of the speech the powers of the gods are subordinated to the cre<br />

ative power of this "young"<br />

new Eros, including, at the last, even<br />

"Zeus'<br />

ernance of gods and (197b3). The victory of Agathon's sophistical poi-<br />

esis thus points back to something lacking in the Aristophanic contrivance, to<br />

his ultimate failure to bring to bear the "will of<br />

in physis.<br />

Zeus"<br />

or the "power"<br />

gov<br />

inherent<br />

Does Plato perhaps even intimate dramatically something of the ground of


240 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Aristophanes'<br />

failure ? Though Aristophanes contrives to gain a higher position<br />

in the order of speakers than Eryximachus (and in that sense appears at first to<br />

subordinate the technician), he is himself only able to speak by virtue of Eryx<br />

imachus'<br />

cure (cf. 185c, 189a). Does Plato here suggest that Aristophanes'<br />

logos is ultimately dependent on that of Eryximachus ? Does the wise Aris<br />

(18c2-3) logos on eros, perhaps<br />

"different"<br />

tophanes, in giving us his allegedly<br />

finally fail to transcend the sense of physis at work in the logos of Eryximachus<br />

(cf. Rosen, pp. 120, 133)?<br />

On Aristophanes'<br />

interpretation of eros,<br />

eros is our eternal search for our<br />

missing or "matching half (sumbolon), a search he thus characterizes as being<br />

whole"<br />

animated precisely by our "desire and pursuit of the (193al : tou holou<br />

oun tei epithumiai kai didxei). Since the reason (192e9 : aition) for this is that<br />

is was in our original nature to be whole, eros can finally<br />

another way,<br />

original<br />

be understood still<br />

as what would return us to or be "the restorer of our archaic or<br />

nature"<br />

(191dl : tes arkhaias phuseos sunago geus). As "everyone<br />

would openly acknowledge that this is the age old desire,"<br />

the "joining and<br />

melding"<br />

(192e7 : sunelthon kai suntakeis) into a whole with one they love, we<br />

must acknowledge that a logos on eros is first of all a logos about sexuality.<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

sexual frankness is thus present from the beginning of his speech :<br />

The archaic state to which eros would have us return is presented in the image<br />

of the rolling and tumbling circle-men,<br />

of whom Aristophanes names Ephialtes<br />

and Otus as if a representative couple (190b). The meanings of their names<br />

make for a wry Platonic touch : Since ephialtes was "popularly connected with<br />

"Otus"<br />

ephallomai (LSJ), and since seems to derive from the verb othed, they<br />

represent the coupling of none other than "he who leaps<br />

pushes<br />

back."<br />

But Aristophanes resists being characterized as a crudely<br />

upon"<br />

and "he who<br />

reductive erotic<br />

theorist. If a logos on eros must first of all be a logos of sexual desire, it must<br />

at the same time be an interpretation of desire as a whole, an interpretation in<br />

which sexuality has, so to speak, its psychical analogue. Of this Aristophanes<br />

himself would seem to be well aware, since he claims his account of<br />

archaic goal pertains to more than just the body's desire :<br />

But no one would believe that purely sexual union (aphrodision sunousia) is what<br />

is wanted, as if for the sake of this alone they enjoy coming together with such<br />

great zeal. But clearly there is something else that the psyche of each desires,<br />

which it is unable to articulate, but it does divine what it wants and hints in<br />

disguises (alia manteuetai ho bouletai kai ainittetai). (192d2)<br />

The soul too thus shares in the longing to return to our archaic state and partici<br />

pates in the body's perpetual "desire and pursuit of the<br />

eros'<br />

whole."<br />

Indeed the<br />

participation of the soul is such that it even seems to underlie the body's desire,<br />

so that sexual union simpliciter cannot be understood as the archaic "whole-


The Wisdom of Plato's Aristophanes 241<br />

that eros pursues. Beyond the aphrodision sunousia itself there is "some<br />

thing<br />

it were, only<br />

else"<br />

that eros is after, an archaic wholeness of which sexual union is, as<br />

a token."<br />

But sexuality is indeed a bona fide token of the type<br />

perhaps the most proximal of the phenomena in which desire as such appears<br />

and so provides us a "hint"<br />

as to the broader sense of the "archaic<br />

that eros as as a whole pursues. Thus there is a sense in which Aristophanes<br />

can be said to have given an account of what it is that the psyche, too, desires :<br />

The blissful "merging and<br />

melding"<br />

of erotic union acheives a temporary re<br />

lease from sorrows, a forgetfulness of the strivings of mortal existence, and a<br />

kind of dissipation of ordinary consciousness. As one "loses oneself in the<br />

enravishment of eros the world seems to disappear, and one escapes for a while<br />

in ecstatic freedom from the careworn labors of the creatures of genesis. In the<br />

blissfulness and eudaimonia of this moment mortal nature is given to feel ful<br />

filled, and the vicissitudes of life give way to stillness, ease, and peace; for a<br />

time, the wheel of Ixion stands still. In this time of world-forgetful ness and<br />

strifeless existence the psyche indeed pursues a kind of- return to its archaic<br />

situation, to the original nature it had "prior,"<br />

consciousness. The psyche too is thus marked by<br />

as it were, to the genesis of<br />

the "desire and<br />

wholeness, the blissful womb of unconsciousness, the "archaic<br />

which it came. That he so envisages<br />

fully reveals with his next words, where he finally<br />

wholeness that eros as such is after:<br />

pursuit<br />

of<br />

state"<br />

from<br />

eros'<br />

archaic goal Aristophanes now muse-<br />

does "divine"<br />

the nature of<br />

Now Suppose Hephaestus were to stand over them as they were lying together this<br />

way, having his tools ready, and he said : "What is it you want, you human<br />

beings, to get from one<br />

another?"<br />

And if in their perplexity he asked them again :<br />

"Is this what you desire, to come together as much as possible, and not have to<br />

leave one another, night and day? If this is what you desire, I am willing to melt<br />

you and weld you (suntexai kai sumphusesai) into one being. You would be as two<br />

become one, and you can live as one, with the two of you sharing a life in<br />

common. And when you die, there in Hades, too, instead of two there will be one,<br />

sharing death. But see if this is what you want and if you would be satisfied if this<br />

should happen."<br />

We know that not a single one of them, hearing this, would refuse<br />

such an offer. They would seem to desire nothing else. (192d2-e7)<br />

What does Hephaestus offer which would seem the very satisfaction of our<br />

longing<br />

and the attainment of<br />

eros'<br />

archaic goal? he proposes to make two into<br />

one, to create a state of wholeness or eternal union out of what had previously<br />

been held apart. Such wholeness or permanent union seems to be nothing less<br />

than a state of uninterupted fulfillment,<br />

a state where, as<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

image<br />

captures so unambiguously, there is no longer any separation between what<br />

desires and its object. Since it is just such a separation, as Socrates first of all<br />

shows (199c-201b), which is presupposed by the presence of eros, this state of<br />

erotic fulfillment would be a state characterized precisely by<br />

eros'<br />

absence.


242 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Plato deftly<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

captures this character of<br />

divination. The presence of<br />

suggestion that we be "welded<br />

tophanic "wholeness"<br />

:<br />

together"<br />

Hephaestus'<br />

eros'<br />

archaic goal in the particulars of<br />

Hephaestus'<br />

(sumphusesai)<br />

tools (organa) and his<br />

evoke a sense of Aris-<br />

work appropriately transfigures us into<br />

something inanimate, like metal or stone, since his offer of wholeness is pre<br />

cisely to put an end to the yearning of eros.<br />

desire "nothing<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

claim that we would<br />

else"<br />

amounts to the suggestion that what eros desires is its own<br />

termination, an end to the striving of consciousness. This logos on eros thus<br />

properly<br />

has its mythical telos in "Hades."<br />

Freud has therefore divined some<br />

thing of the truth in seeking his own erotic theory prefigured in Aristophanes,<br />

as he too conceives the "ancient<br />

goal" state,"<br />

to be "the inanimate and finally<br />

feels "compelled to say that 'the aim of all life is death'<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

comical logos on eros thus harbors a profoundly plaintive and<br />

somber pathos. At the bottom of the human situation lies a contradiction in<br />

heart of life itself. The creatures of physis are animated by an erotic Necessity<br />

which puts them fundamentally at odds with themselves, since they are com<br />

pelled to strive by what would find its fulfillment only in the release from<br />

striving. Since such release is only finally attainable by virtue of an end to<br />

erotic animation, there can be no genuine well-being or eudaimonia for animate<br />

creation. Life is animated by the ideal of death, the strivings of consciousness<br />

by the ideal of quiescence. Physis is fulfilled only by self-negation; in the<br />

meantime, the wheel of Ixion rolls on. The eros which moves mortal creation is<br />

the affect of a futile striving.<br />

The Aristophanic cosmos is in this sense fundamentally anous or "mind<br />

less", and the whole of nature governed by a "power senseless and without<br />

purpose"<br />

(alogou kai eikei dunamin) (cf. discussion on wisdom of Zeus above).<br />

The overseeing principle which animates genesis compels its creatures to strive<br />

"in<br />

vain"<br />

(eikei), thus condemning them to a life of perpetual frustration and<br />

suffering. In this way Aristophanes'<br />

hiccups themselves caricature his inter<br />

pretation of eros : a recurrent and intractable demand from which we could only<br />

wish respite and surcease. From this point of view one might represent the Will<br />

behind all of physis as uncaring for and even ill-disposed towards the aspira<br />

tions of its resident creatures aspirations which it itself nonetheless demands<br />

of and evokes in them. So Aristophanes pictures Zeus: Hostile to the strivings<br />

of the circle-men, Zeus refuses to wipe them out completely, being unwilling to<br />

lose their worship (190 cd); he decides instead to debilitate them. He thus<br />

creates a situation where men retain their "upward"<br />

of the means of fulfilling it.<br />

. .<br />

orientation but are deprived<br />

The pathos generated in the one who so perceives the "power"<br />

Necessity<br />

thus emerges in the "moral"<br />

behind erotic<br />

Aristophanes would have us draw from<br />

the wisdom of his exposition : This logos on eros shows that it behooves us to<br />

be obedient to the gods and "in the present<br />

circumstances"<br />

to do what "is best<br />

for now : that is to fall in with one of like mind to oneself (193c9 : touto


The Wisdom of Plato's Aristophanes 243<br />

d'esti paidikon tukhein kata noun autoi pephukoton). The cosmos that is anous<br />

and alogos is also by<br />

nature left for whatever good befalls to a fortuitous and<br />

promiscuous fate: tukhein (from tugkhano, "to fall in<br />

with"<br />

or "hit upon") thus<br />

pointedly carries the sense of "to meet chance."<br />

by Human existence is com<br />

pelled by an eros that allows it only surrogate and fugitive satisfaction and for<br />

this exiguous solace it is fundamentally abandoned to "chance"<br />

(cf. also 193b2,<br />

193cl, 193c4).<br />

ting<br />

"In the present<br />

circumstances,"<br />

then, the best we can have comes from get<br />

together with one of "like mind to oneself (kata noun autoi pephukoton).<br />

In the mythical ideal this beloved is less precisely a<br />

"complement"<br />

(cf. Dover<br />

[1980], p. 113) than a reaffirmation of the self-same: These lovers, as Aris<br />

tophanes would have it, have "two faces, exactly<br />

opa .<br />

alike"<br />

(189e7-al: kai pros-<br />

homoia pante). In his beloved the Aristophanic lover thus pursues not<br />

what takes a different form from the lover himself, but rather only, as it were, a<br />

kind of permanent reconciliation with what he already is like. What is "best"<br />

thus the absence of striving that comes from being<br />

is<br />

with one of "like mind to<br />

oneself,"<br />

who in reflecting the countenance of nothing beyond what one al<br />

ready is induces a kind of stillness and peace. In this sense in "sharing their<br />

lives in<br />

common"<br />

these two share a kind of mutual quiescence. Since the<br />

cosmos that is animated by eros is fundamentally alogos and contradictory,<br />

here again what is "best for is not to awaken or incite it, but rather to lull<br />

it into rest by<br />

whatever technique it can be quieted or "kept<br />

where Zeus warns : kai me thelosin hesukhian agein . . .).<br />

mous "conservatism"<br />

still."<br />

(cf. 190d5<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

is thus profound and pervasive : The wisdom at the telos<br />

of this logos on eros counsels a kind of retreat from the agitations and move<br />

ments of genesis. As the assuasive effects of the techne of comedy might now<br />

finally be held up to attest, the "best"<br />

we can have comes from the poiesis of<br />

what might allow us to release ourselves and take respite from life.<br />

Where are we here to locate Aristophanes'<br />

perspective is wanting in his perception of the "power"<br />

might root ourselves once again in the "principle"<br />

and bring to light one final self-referential feature of<br />

fa<br />

failure and see what from Plato's<br />

behind eros? Here we<br />

which guided us earlier on<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

speech. As<br />

Aristophanes tells the story, after their original nature had been severed men<br />

"yearned to be enmeshed<br />

together,"<br />

off from "hunger and general inactivity"<br />

their genitals around in front of them, "<br />

and caring only for this they began to die<br />

(191b). For this reason Zeus moved<br />

. . and through this got them to<br />

propagate with one another, the male inside the female. This way, if a man<br />

happened to meet (191c5 : entukhoi) a woman, while they were embracing they<br />

would generate and the race would<br />

In Aristophanes'<br />

continue"<br />

(191c).<br />

story, the procreation that results from erotic union is thus<br />

incidental to its true motive, namely, the desire to return to the archaic state of<br />

logos proves im<br />

"enmeshed."<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

"melding"<br />

and being<br />

Here again<br />

plicitly self-referential precisely insofar as the generation of someoffspring<br />

is


244 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

incidental in Aristophanes'<br />

interpretation of the "power"<br />

behind eros and<br />

thing<br />

inessential to understanding the archaic goal that eros ultimately pursues.<br />

But what does it mean for procreation to be incidental to an interpretation of<br />

eros, or conversely, to understand eros in terms of an essential orientation to<br />

offspring? Only in this latter way, one might say here, do we truly recover<br />

eros'<br />

archaic goal, and so begin to see the nature of the eros'<br />

Necessity behind<br />

intractable "power."<br />

So Diotima warns Socrates : He must understand that all<br />

humans are fundamentally pregnant (206c 1) and that eros is for "giving birth<br />

and procreation in the beautiful"<br />

(206e). For as what is to be born lives on,<br />

beyond the reaches of what brings it into being, so eros, viewed from this<br />

perspective, begins to appear this way : as a longing of what is subject to the<br />

vicissitudes of genesis for what endures beyond these vicissitudes standing<br />

more strongly and with greater vitality within the stream of becoming and in<br />

that way better constituted for what befalls mortal nature though the intractable<br />

will of genesis. It is this mortal's perception of something "immortal"<br />

behind the "power"<br />

which is<br />

of sexuality and what is implicit in the adamantine will of<br />

erotic Necessity. In this sense eros is the affective presence of something tran<br />

scendent in the mortal breast : In erotic longing the child who would be born is<br />

already daimonically<br />

present.10<br />

From this point of view what is wanting in Aristophanes'<br />

interpretation of<br />

eros is precisely recollection of the transcendence within physis, and as this is<br />

what is "behind"<br />

the power of eros, we might say that this is what he fails to<br />

see : That what is erotic is unconsciously animated by a vision of the "immor<br />

tal"<br />

of what is divined to be in some way delivered from the infirmities of the<br />

mortal and so of what in its transcendence is immanent as what orients the<br />

process. In this way we can understand the meaning of Diotima's oracular<br />

reference back to Aristophanes : "Whereas a person might tell a story that those<br />

who seek after the other half of themselves are lovers, my<br />

account describes<br />

love as being neither of the half nor of the whole, unless it should happen, my<br />

friend, to be something<br />

good"<br />

(205de). On this view eros is archaically ori<br />

ented less by the other ("half) or even the sunousia of the two (the "whole")<br />

"power"<br />

than by a prior perception of the of what might be created by virtue of<br />

their union, a hidden promise within physis of what they thus "instinctively"<br />

divine as making good on their mortal lacking.<br />

This understanding of the power of eros, has, so to speak, its psychical<br />

analogue or provides a "hint"<br />

through which one might likewise understand the<br />

"desires and<br />

pursuits"<br />

of eros as whole. Here too the longing of eros would<br />

have its arche in a perception of something "immortal,"<br />

and would be animated<br />

by a glimpse of the power of something it might produce, "something new, like<br />

itself (208b 12), but which it divines to be delivered from its own infirmities.<br />

The "mantic"<br />

character of the psyche is thus an elaboration of the general<br />

metaphor of mortal pregnancy : The longing of the soul is not the archaic affect<br />

of what would return to the stillness of the inanimate, but rather of what al-


Plato'<br />

The Wisdom of s Aristophanes 245<br />

ready nurtures within it a still greater vitality, speaking, like the prophetic<br />

"pregnancy"<br />

of the body, of a future animation. In the soul too eros would thus<br />

not find its fulfillment in release from mortal striving and the peaceful quies<br />

cence of "death,"<br />

but rather in bearing what is better constituted for this mortal<br />

existence and in bringing something new to life.<br />

In this way the soul would share in being animated by<br />

what stands beyond<br />

the vicissitudes of genesis, having always already divined, as it were, what is<br />

stronger, and makes good on its lacking. In its transcendence this would always<br />

be immanent as what orients the soul in its desire, the arche of the<br />

"power"<br />

compels it to longing, and the source of erotic Necessity. In being animated by<br />

this the soul is indeed subject to the demands of a higher Will, since this is<br />

what, of Necessity, compels the mortal soul to its pathos, to the inspired awak<br />

ening<br />

of a resolute pursuit or the hypnogogic inveiglement of a plaintive and<br />

forgetful flight."<br />

that<br />

As the affective presence of what transcends the mortal soul,<br />

eros divines precisely that with respect to which this mortal's life now appears<br />

as lacking, and so is the revelation of what points up<br />

its infirmities and failings.<br />

The affect of Necessity thus undoes and debilitates the completeness and integ<br />

rity of a way of life, or in the more imposing language of the mythic metaphor,<br />

sunders the hybristic whole. In this way erotic Necessity brings with it suffer<br />

ings and sorrows and is the archaic affect of a hard and demanding Will, since<br />

it shows what must first be overcome and undergo genesis in order that its<br />

promise be delivered and fulfilled. Here erotic Necessity<br />

might evoke the pa<br />

thos of mortal flight, and generating, as it were, in mortal forgetfulness, give<br />

way<br />

to a timorous delusion.<br />

But just insofar as erotic necessity points up our mortal debility by first<br />

divining that in view of which this way of life now appears as lacking, it is<br />

itself the revelation of how one could yet stand more strongly, and dwell, one<br />

might here say, in a cosmos that is "beyond"<br />

this one and which transcends it.<br />

In revealing what thus stands "beyond the horizon"<br />

eros is, in the language of the Phaedrus,<br />

of the present<br />

"cosmos,"<br />

an intimation of the "hyperouranian"<br />

place. Erotic necessity thus brings into view something captivating and beauti<br />

ful, since in pointing up our mortal lacking it divines the very way<br />

in which<br />

what is lacking could be made good. The hard Will of intractable necessity<br />

could here awaken<br />

mortals'<br />

resolute affection and be the inspiration of a cos-<br />

mogonic pursuit, the daimonic power by<br />

the way it could be "nourished and<br />

which an infirm mortal soul can see<br />

prosper"<br />

(cf. Phaedrus 247c ff. where by<br />

the vision of the hyperouranian place the soul is trephetai kai eupathei .<br />

The plaintive pathos of mortal flight is thus not itself demanded by this divine<br />

Will, since in the matter of the affect generated in the face of Necessity<br />

.).<br />

we are<br />

"chance."<br />

not fundamentally abandoned to In this way Plato's philosophical<br />

logos on eros harbors an encouraging and inspiring pathos, and an altogether<br />

more just and divine image of the nature of the will of Zeus,<br />

of all hidden within the "power"<br />

since it sees first<br />

of eros the promise of a better cosmos.


246 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

The cosmos in this way animated by<br />

and not governed over by a "power senseless and without<br />

tures of physis would not be compelled to strive "in<br />

eros would not be anous or "mindless,"<br />

purpose<br />

The crea<br />

vain,"<br />

since they are<br />

moved not by what finds its fulfillment only in the release of death, but by<br />

what would be fulfilled here, in the regeneration of life. In this sense the Will<br />

behind physis is not "ill-disposed"<br />

towards mortal nature, having animated it<br />

with an eros which at its arche holds the measures by which life is replenished<br />

and goes on. The "power"<br />

which animates genesis is thus not alogos, "sense<br />

less,"<br />

or even wholly<br />

"inarticulate,"<br />

but rather speaks daimonically of the very<br />

way in which a mortal's lacking could be nourished into strength, its affective<br />

presence harboring the hidden logos of a cosmos transfigured, its infirmities<br />

overcome. While mortal nature may thus be subject to genesis and being "sun<br />

dered"<br />

by what prevents it from remaining the same, it is animated by<br />

that can heal this by revealing how Necessity has arranged for a way<br />

change. In this sense the "power"<br />

an eros<br />

it can<br />

that rules over physis has filled its creatures<br />

with something divinely promising, and while its adamantine Necessity may be<br />

demanding and hard they are not deprived of the means of fulfilling<br />

it. The<br />

Will that governs the cosmos thus does not abandon mortal creation for its<br />

eudaimonia and whatever good befalls to the fortuitous workings of "chance,"<br />

but rather arrange measures and order for life, growth and healing<br />

cosmos,<br />

realm of genesis.<br />

and in that sense "cares for"<br />

From this point of view, our "archaic<br />

in the<br />

the mortal creatures which dwell in the<br />

nature"<br />

would never be though'<br />

in<br />

terms of the inanimate substance of physis, since it is what in its transcendence<br />

animates this that is at the arche of our erotic coming-to-life. Here one might<br />

speak of a cosmic nous that steers through all that is inanimate, like Zeus in the<br />

myth, the "first to proceed, ordering all things and caring therefore<br />

drus 246e: .<br />

"<br />

(Phae<br />

. . protos poreuetai, diakosmon panto kai epimeloumenos . . .).<br />

Thus Plato's logos would not move in the imaginal direction of the mythologiz-<br />

ing<br />

of Hades but rather towards a recollection of the psyche's divine or "hyper<br />

ouranian"<br />

origins. In this sense Plato brings to bear a sense of physis different<br />

from that which Aristophanes and Eryximachus both share, the "archaic<br />

of a fundamentally<br />

"mindless"<br />

and desacralized cosmos.<br />

Since the cosmos that is animated by eros is at its arche divinely promising,<br />

the "best for<br />

now"<br />

could not possibly be to lull it into quietness or "keeping<br />

still,"<br />

but rather to pursue the good that is promised mortal nature which honors<br />

the Will behind genesis. In this way the initiate Socrates proceeds in the coun<br />

sel of "Diotima."<br />

The wisdom at the telos of this logos on eros would thus not<br />

issue in the "conservative"<br />

and<br />

""soft"<br />

poeisis of what delivers us respite from<br />

life, but bids us suffer the sacred rites of genesis which promise its renewal<br />

and rejuvenation. Two lovers "sharing their lives"<br />

in this way would not share<br />

a mutual quiescence, since here again in their love what they share is some<br />

third thing, which makes good on and still transcends them (Phaedrus 250b,<br />

nature


The Wisdom of Plato'<br />

s Aristophanes 247<br />

252e). Thus in the end it would be better not to say that Aristophanes'<br />

consists in "making eros fundamentally<br />

tonic love it fundamentally is that. Aristophanes'<br />

failure<br />

sexual."<br />

Even for the initiate into Pla<br />

failure does not as much<br />

body"<br />

consist in his thinking that the "psyche is defined by and depends on the<br />

(Rosen, p. 140) as in his not seeing how both the body and the psyche are<br />

and depend<br />

"defined by<br />

on"<br />

their animation by something divine.<br />

Thus the wise Aristophanes could be said to have reminded us of the rule of<br />

a higher Necessity, recalling<br />

us to a "power"<br />

to which we are subject and<br />

which transcends mortal dominion. His comic recollection of intractable erotic<br />

compulsion in this way would mitigate mortal hybris,<br />

claim to being<br />

just as Aristophanes'<br />

and at first sight lays<br />

a poiesis that recalls us to wisdom about the power of Zeus. But<br />

hiccups are an anticipation in ergoi of the substance of his<br />

critique, so they are an ironic caricature of what is still wanting in his wisdom,<br />

of Aristophanes'<br />

failure to himself rightly perceive the "power"<br />

implicit in<br />

eros. Recalling erotic Necessity without the nous and cosmic divinity behind it,<br />

he might be likened to one who presents the will of Zeus as nothing more than<br />

a hiccup, making Aristophanes'<br />

of Aristophanes.<br />

NOTES<br />

1 . Thus in his inspiring<br />

object of erotic love is to oikeion kai<br />

paper "Platonic Love"<br />

hiccups themselves Plato's joke on the wisdom<br />

L.A. Kosman finds Plato's view that the "proper<br />

already<br />

"Central to Plato's vision as articulated comically in Aristophanes'<br />

endees" Aristophanes'<br />

present in<br />

speech :<br />

myth is that the self which I am<br />

about to become, my "ecstatic self, is ideally no mere projection of my fantasies or desires, but is<br />

my true nature from which I am only in some accidental sense, by a willful and jealous act of the<br />

gods,<br />

alienated"<br />

(pp. 60-61).<br />

2. Agathon's representative connection to sophistry is indicated by<br />

Socrates'<br />

opening words of<br />

response to his speech (198c : "The speech reminded me of Gorgias "). On the "abundant"<br />

presence of Gorgias'<br />

rhetorical "machinery"<br />

to 194e.<br />

in Agathon's speech cf. Bury, pp. xxxxv-vi and note<br />

That Phaedrus brings us back to the Homeric beginnings of this culture Plato indicates in a<br />

number of ways : not only is warfare the existential context for Phaedrus'<br />

conceptualization of<br />

virtue, and not only is Achilles finally named as the one who lives out his ethical ideal (179e ff.),<br />

but Phaedrus quite openly identifies virtue with the archaic Homeric menos (179b).<br />

For a somewhat fuller account of the subtextual<br />

"anthropogony"<br />

in the first five speeches of the<br />

Symposium, cf. the author's "Anthropogony and Theogony in Plato's Symposium''.<br />

The centrality of the Symposium of Plato's quarrel over the<br />

symbolically indicated already<br />

in the dialogues'<br />

"wisdom"<br />

of Agathon is of course<br />

prologue. Cf. esp. 174b-d and 175c-e.<br />

3. Thus Brentlinger aptly says of Aristophanes that "he dramatically fulfills a role in relation to<br />

the first three speeches which in other dialogues belongs peculiarly to the Socratic art of question<br />

and answer that of a wise critic. It is essential in understanding the Symposium to grasp this<br />

point, namely the similarity .<br />

between the comic poet and the dialectician.<br />

(p.<br />

12). Cf. also<br />

Friedlander: "It is apparent, to begin with the human or social content, that the four other speakers<br />

form two pairs of friends, Phaidros an Eryximachos, Pausanias and Agathon. Even as Aristophanes<br />

is alone among<br />

the guests in this human situation, so his speech is the furthest removed from the<br />

"<br />

speeches of the others. . Aristophanes is the sharpest critic . (p. 18).


248 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

In the Birth of Tragedy Nietzsche speaks of "the profound instinct of Aristophanes"<br />

ing "the signs of degenerate<br />

in recogniz<br />

culture"<br />

(cf. sections 13 and 17). To the extent that the drama of the<br />

Symposium lends a kind of approval to the Aristophanic "instinct,"<br />

we are led to wonder about a<br />

principal and complex issue-about the extent to which Nietzsche's critique of what he deems<br />

"Socratic"<br />

culture is really Platonic in origin.<br />

4. Along with Phaedrus the youngest at the party, Agathon was renowned for his physical<br />

beauty, and Alcibiades only gives voice to the general sentiment beautiful"<br />

calling him "the most<br />

Phaedrus'<br />

(213c: toi kallisto) man at the banquet. (Cf. also remark at 194d and Socrates'<br />

at Pro<br />

tagoras 315d.) According to Aristophanes (Thesmophoriazusae 191-92), he kept his beard close<br />

shaven, presumably to heighten the appearance of early<br />

unconnected. On the basis of Aristophanes'<br />

'"softness"<br />

youth. His predilection for<br />

is not<br />

portrait in the Thesmophoriazusae ,<br />

it appears that<br />

Agathon was widely known for his effeminacy and for his role as a passive homosexual (cf. 140<br />

ff., 191-92, 200, 206). If we are to believe in Aristophanes'<br />

can also understand the attribution of "suppleness"<br />

circumspect sexual sense, and the sexual accessibility<br />

: hugros<br />

merciless portrayal, at any rate, we<br />

("supple," "pliant,"<br />

"easy") has a<br />

Aristophanes attributes to Agathon makes it<br />

an apt characterization (cf. e.g. Th. 35, 56 ff., 200). But we need not turn to Aristophanes for a<br />

hint of Agathon's promiscuity. Of all the lovers in the Symposium, it is Agathon who displays a<br />

propensity<br />

for "looseness"<br />

by<br />

his open flirtation (175d) with Socrates (this in spite of the presence<br />

of his lover Pausanias). Cf. also 222c ff. On Agathon's effeminacy cf. Dover (1978), pp. 139-44.<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

5. Cf. Nussbaum, p. 172 : "As we hear<br />

distant myth of this passionate groping<br />

and grasping, we are invited to think how odd, after all, it is that bodies should have these holes<br />

and projections in them, odd that the insertion of a projection into an opening should be thought, by<br />

concern."<br />

ambitious and intelligent beings, a matter of the deepest<br />

It is of course precisely the<br />

"power"<br />

of eros which Aristophanes claims his predecessors have<br />

failed to see : "It seems to me that men do not perceive the power (dunamin) of eros at all. . I<br />

will try to show you its power, and you, in turn, will be the teachers of<br />

others"<br />

(189cd). For an<br />

extremely interesting discussion of the centrality of the theme of comic and tragic wisdom, see<br />

Clay.<br />

6. On the circular arrangement of the couches at Agathon's symposium, see Dover, p. 11.<br />

Dover takes epi dexia at 177d3 to indicate that the speakers are moving in an '"anti-clockwise<br />

sequence."<br />

Cf. also Friedlander, vol. 1, p. 161.<br />

For Eryximachus cf. 187d5, 187d6, 188a3, 188c3 and Bury's note to 189a. Consider here also<br />

the scene at 223b : When the revelers finally take over the party and "the slightest semblance of<br />

order (kosmoi)"<br />

disappears, Plato has Eryximachus make his exit.<br />

For the claims of Aristophanic comedy to critical sophia, cf. the parabasis of the Clouds esp.<br />

518-48. In making the claim to wisdom implicit in giving a logos of Zeus, Aristophanes here<br />

seems to take what he deems his rightful place in the "contest over<br />

initiated at the dialogues'<br />

wisdom"<br />

that Agathon had<br />

outset (175e). We should note too how he was implicitly solicited or<br />

perhaps better, provoked by Socrates who characterized him as "devoting himself entirely to<br />

Dionysus and Aphrodite"<br />

(177e).<br />

7. Thus Aristophanes begins : dei de proton humas mathein ter anthropinen phusin kai ta<br />

pathemata autes (189d4-6). (On Aristophanes'<br />

conflation of "human<br />

"nature" nature"<br />

and gener<br />

ally cf. 191a5.) The connection between wisdom and the figure of Zeus should of course also recall<br />

to us the passage at Phaedrus 250b where the philosophers are said to be the ones who have<br />

followed in the train of Zeus. (Cf. also 252e.) Perhaps even more important in the present context<br />

though is a passage in the Critias where "Zeus, the god of<br />

which such things as mortal decline are seen (121b).<br />

gods"<br />

is the one who has the power by<br />

8. Thus we can already see how it cannot be wholly right to say : "By making Eros fundamen<br />

tally sexual, Aristophanes illustrates two inseparable principles of his teaching. Human striving,<br />

whether for truth or fame, is essentially physical : the psyche is defined by and depends on the<br />

body"<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

(Rosen, p. 140). Cf. however Rosen's fascinating reading of entire speech<br />

(pp. 120-58) with which what follows might be compared.<br />

9. Beyond the Pleasure Principle, pp. 51, 32. On p. 51 Freud says: "Apart from this, science<br />

has so little to tell us about the origin of sexuality that we can liken the problem to a darkness into


Plato'<br />

The Wisdom of s Aristophanes<br />

which not so much as a ray of a hypothesis has penetrated. In quite a different region, it is true, we<br />

do meet with such a hypothesis; but it is of so fantastic a kind a myth rather than a scientific<br />

explanation that I would not venture to produce it here, were it not that it fulfills precisely the one<br />

condition whose fulfillment we desire. For it traces the origin of an instinct to a need to restore an<br />

earlier state of<br />

-<br />

249<br />

things'<br />

In the context of a discussion of whether Freud conflated Aristophanes'<br />

speech with Plato's erotic theory Santas says that a major "novel element in Beyond the Pleasure<br />

Principle was Freud's notion that the instincts are essentially 'conservative': they<br />

restoring<br />

aim at<br />

affairs."<br />

an earlier state of Freud "surveys the findings of biology for positive evidence of<br />

a death instinct or for the instincts being<br />

tophanes'<br />

conservative,"<br />

but finding none, he refers us to Aris<br />

myth which as Santas points out Freud had recited to his betrothed some forty years<br />

before (pp. 160-62). On p. 181 (n. II) Santas remarks that the "aims of Freud's Eros and Aris<br />

tophanes'<br />

eros would seem to coincide in general, in both aiming at an earlier state of but<br />

seems to wonder as to whether they would "coincide more<br />

of both Hephaestus'<br />

specifically."<br />

The symbolic significance<br />

smith art and his mention of Hades seem to make the coincidence deep-<br />

running indeed. Some version of the intuition that Aristophanic fulfillment culminates in death goes<br />

back at least as far as Aristotle (Politics II 4 1262b 9-17), as Friedlander (vol. 3, p. 20) points out.<br />

10. Here, strangely enough, we can seek help<br />

from the eccentric "Platonist"<br />

Schopenhauer.<br />

"immortal"<br />

who describes how only the presence of something can account for the overwhelming<br />

"power"<br />

of eros : "<br />

. this<br />

longing<br />

and this pain of love cannot draw their material from the needs<br />

of an ephemeral individual. On the contrary they are the sighs of the spirit of the species, which<br />

sees here, to be won or lost, an irreplaceable means to its ends, and therefore groans deeply. The<br />

species alone has infinite life, and is therefore capable of infinite desire, infinite satisfaction, and<br />

infinite sufferings. But these are here imprisoned in the narrow breast of a mortal; no wonder,<br />

therefore, when such a breast seems ready to burst<br />

"<br />

(vol. 2, p. 551). Behind sexual attraction<br />

Schopenhauer thus sees something like the unconscious "meditation of the genius of the species<br />

concerning<br />

the individual possible through these two<br />

already kindled in the meeting of their longing glances .<br />

affect in the breast of the mortal of what has a more "infinite life."<br />

"<br />

"<br />

(p. 549). "Its new life, indeed, is<br />

(p. 536)."<br />

Eros is thus the archaic<br />

But as we will suggest shortly<br />

below, what for Schopenhauer is the sexual substratum to which all love is to be privatively<br />

reduced, for Plato is the prototype of what holds analogically across the spectrum of erotic phenom<br />

ena.<br />

1 1 . On<br />

the centrality of the notions of affective presence and pathos to Plato's conception of<br />

the relation in which mortals stand to the "truth"<br />

REFERENCES<br />

Bacon, Helen. "Socrates Crowned."<br />

cf. the author's forthcoming<br />

"Platonic Rhetoric."<br />

The Virginia Quarterly Review 35( 1959):4 1530.<br />

Symposium."<br />

in the In The Symposium of Plato,<br />

Brentlinger, J. "The Cycle of Becoming<br />

translated by Suzy Q. Groden. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1970.<br />

Bury, R. G. The Symposium of Plato. 2d ed. Cambridge, Eng.: W. Heffer and Sons,<br />

1932.<br />

Clay, Diskin. "The Tragic and Comic Poet of the Symposium."<br />

In Essays in Ancient<br />

Greek <strong>Philosophy</strong>, edited by J. P Anton and A. Preus. Albany: State University of<br />

New York Press, 1983. Vol. 2. pp. 186-202.<br />

Dover, K. J. Greek Homosexuality. New York: Vintage Books, 1978.<br />

Plato: Symposium. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980.<br />

Edelstein, L. "The role of Eryximachus in Plato's Symposium."<br />

Association Transactions and Proceedings 76(1945): 85-103.<br />

Freud, Sigmund. Beyond the Pleasure Principle. Translated by<br />

York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1951.<br />

American Philological<br />

James Strachey. New


250 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Friedlander, Paul. Plato. Translated by<br />

Hans Meyerhoff. Princeton: Princeton Univer<br />

sity Press, 1958-1969.<br />

Hackforth, R. Plato's Phaedrus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1952.<br />

Kosman, L. A. "Platonic Love."<br />

Werkmeister. Assen: Van Gorcum, 1976.<br />

In Facets of Plato's <strong>Philosophy</strong>, edited by<br />

Moore, J. D. "The Relation Between Plato's Symposium and Phaedrus."<br />

W. H.<br />

In Patterns in<br />

Plato's Thought, edited by J. M. E. Moravcsik. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing<br />

Co., 1973. Pp. 52-71.<br />

Nussbaum, Martha. The Fragility of Goodness. Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1986.<br />

Olympiodorus. Commentary on the First Alcibiades of Plato. Edited and translated by<br />

L. G. Westerink. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Co., 1956.<br />

Rosen, Stanley. Plato's Symposium. 2d ed. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1987.<br />

Salman, Charles. "Anthropogony and Theogony<br />

Journal. Forthcoming.<br />

"Platonic Rhetoric."<br />

New York: Edwin Mellen Press, forthcoming.<br />

in Plato's Symposium."<br />

The Classical<br />

In Rhetoric and Ethics: Historical and Theoretical Essavs.<br />

Santas, G. Plato and Freud. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988.<br />

Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Translated by<br />

Payne. New York: Dover Publications. 1969.<br />

E. F. J.


David Hume's Theology<br />

Roger M. Barrus<br />

Hampden-Sydney College<br />

of Liberation<br />

Liberal political philosophy attempts to reform government and society by<br />

separating religion from politics, accomplishing this by curbing the moral pre<br />

tensions of politics. Liberalism rejects the traditional conception of the purpose<br />

of government as the achievement of the complete good life. Instead, it limits<br />

government to the purpose of securing the rights of life, liberty, and property,<br />

the necessary but by no means sufficient conditions of the good life. Limiting<br />

government to securing the prerequisites of the good life means leaving its final<br />

attainment as a matter of individual effort. Included in what is left to each<br />

individual must be the very definition of what it means to be a good human<br />

being. The distinction between the conditions and the fullness of the complete<br />

good life more or less defines the distinction between the public and the pri<br />

vate. Religion, with its concern for ultimate purposes, falls within the sphere of<br />

private right, outside the sphere of public authority. It has for its object, as<br />

Hegel explains, "the highest, the absolute, that which is absolutely true or the<br />

truth itself."<br />

This is to be found in "the region in which all the riddles of the<br />

world, all contradictions of thought, are resolved, and all griefs are healed, the<br />

region of eternal truth and eternal peace, of absolute satisfaction, of truth it<br />

self.'"<br />

Religion belongs in the sphere of the private because it attempts to de<br />

fine the context within which the question of the nature of the complete good<br />

life can be resolved.<br />

The separation between religion and politics in liberal political philosophy<br />

involves, along with the innovations in politics,<br />

Implicit in liberalism is a hostility<br />

a transformation of religion.<br />

towards traditional religion. It rejects the<br />

traditionalist social and political order, in which religion is at the center of<br />

society, defining its purposes, giving it shape, and setting it in motion. The<br />

traditionalist social order is founded on the opinion that society is divinely<br />

ordained. This opinion, in turn, is based on the view,<br />

characteristic of tradi<br />

tionalist religious belief, that there is a divine superintendence of human af<br />

fairs. At the same time, there is implicit in liberalism a kind of religious teach<br />

ing of its own. If only indirectly, it affirms a conception of the complete good<br />

life, what it intends to achieve in political practice through the separation of<br />

religion and politics. This means that at least tacitly there is in liberalism a<br />

conception of the divine according to which the complete good life can be<br />

determined. The religious implications of liberalism's new political science are<br />

interpretation, Winter 1990-1991, Vol. 18, No. 2


252 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

elaborated by the liberal philosophers in a number of works, now largely ig<br />

nored if not entirely forgotten, on the subject of<br />

religion.2<br />

These works are<br />

neglected because the issues with which they deal are no longer alive politi<br />

cally, a measure of the liberal<br />

philosophers'<br />

success in convincing the world<br />

that religion is an essentially private affair, having nothing to do with politics.<br />

Probably the most artistic, if not necessarily the most artful, treatment of<br />

religion in liberal political philosophy is David Hume's Dialogues Concerning<br />

Natural Religion.*<br />

For Hume, the Dialogues was an extremely important work.<br />

He labored on it off and on for over twenty years, from first draft in 1751 to<br />

final revision a short time before his death in 1776. He was occupied during the<br />

last weeks of his life in arranging for its publication. Hume apparently also<br />

considered the Dialogues to be an extremely dangerous work. Not only did he<br />

delay its publication until after his death, but he failed even to mention it in the<br />

short autobiographical sketch that he published just before he died. This is all<br />

the more interesting because he was willing to publish during<br />

his lifetime and<br />

in his own name works of religious scepticism including the Inquiry Concern<br />

ing Human Understanding, the Natural History of Religion,<br />

"Superstition and Enthusiasm,"<br />

"The Immortality<br />

of the Soul."<br />

"The<br />

Further, many<br />

and his essays on<br />

Sceptic," "Miracles," "Suicide,"<br />

and<br />

of the most provocative argu<br />

ments of the Dialogues are drawn from these other works. While Hume no<br />

where explicitly states his intention in writing the Dialogues, it is clearly in<br />

tended to be something more than a mere catalogue of his arguments on<br />

religion. The book has a unity and integrity of its own. It is this that accounts<br />

for the Dialogues'<br />

importance, and its danger, for Hume. The unity and integ<br />

rity of the Dialogues are to be found in its development of what might be called<br />

liberalism's theology of liberation.<br />

The separation of religion and politics is crucial to the success of the project<br />

of liberal political philosophy, the realization of what it conceives as man's<br />

natural freedom through the liberation of mankind from its traditional bond<br />

ages. Human beings from the beginning have sought to subjugate and dominate<br />

one another. This is a nasty consequence of their subjection to nature: the<br />

narrowness of their natural endowment compels them to make use of one an<br />

other to at least partially relieve themselves of the cruel necessities that press<br />

down on them. The enjoyment of human beings of their natural freedom, what<br />

liberalism articulates as their natural rights of life, liberty, and property, is<br />

threatened by the malevolence of man and the enmity of nature, the former<br />

represented by war, and especially civil war, the latter by famine, plague,<br />

pestilence, and the other cataclysms of nature. Liberalism attempts to solve<br />

both these problems, either directly or indirectly, through its invention of the<br />

political system of nonpartisan, representative government.


David Hume's Theology of Liberation 253<br />

The traditional understanding of man's thralldom to man and to nature is<br />

reflected in Aristotle's teaching in the Politics. Aristotle begins his teaching on<br />

politics with the claim that the ultimate moving force in human life is a longing<br />

for the good. "Everyone,"<br />

he asserts, "does everything for the sake of what is<br />

held to be<br />

good."<br />

It is this desire for the good that leads human beings into<br />

association with one another. The most comprehensive form of association is<br />

the political community, which aims at the most comprehensive of goods, the<br />

complete good life. It contains within itself, and perfects, all other forms of<br />

association. These are subordinate to the political community because they<br />

have as their objects only the various partial goods that contribute to the<br />

achievement of the good life. There is an order to the elements that make up<br />

the political community. While perhaps all make contributions that are neces<br />

sary for the accomplishment of the common purpose,<br />

some make contributions<br />

that are more nearly sufficient for it. The latter have a claim to political prece<br />

dence over the former. The political community is, then, an hierarchically<br />

structured whole made up of heterogeneous parts, organized in the light of<br />

some conception of the complete good life.4<br />

Government, for Aristotle, is inherently partisan, the rule of some part of<br />

society over the whole, on behalf of some particular conception of the good<br />

life. For analytical purposes, Aristotle refers to the groups in society as the one,<br />

the few, and the many. Whichever group comes to predominate in a commu<br />

nity gives that community its tone, shape, or order, what Aristotle calls its<br />

regime. Regimes differ not only with respect to who rules in them, but also<br />

with respect to the purposes for which rule is exercised. Every group in society<br />

conceives of the common good in the light of its own specific interests. Again<br />

for analytical purposes, Aristotle distinguishes between regimes in which rule is<br />

for the good of both the rulers and the ruled, and regimes in which rule is for<br />

the good of only the rulers. The former are good regimes, the latter bad. There<br />

are, then, many different regime forms. Aristotle includes six in his theoretical<br />

taxonomy: monarchy, tyranny, aristocracy, oligarchy, polity, and democracy.<br />

Even the good, however, exhibit something of the particular interest of the<br />

ruling part, just as even the bad exhibit something of the universal aspiration<br />

for the good life (see Bk. Ill, esp. 1278b6- 1281al 1).<br />

It is the partisanship of government that is, for Aristotle, the cause of the<br />

fundamental problem of politics. All the groups in society want to be treated<br />

justly, to have their special contributions recognized and their specific needs<br />

filled. While all agree that justice is giving equal things to equal people, they<br />

all disagree about the equalities and inequalities of people and things that must<br />

be taken into account in doing justice. Every part of society is led, then, to<br />

assert its own right to rule,<br />

on behalf of its own conception of the good life.<br />

Political practice is defined by the competition of the various parts of society<br />

for the right to rule over the whole. This competition,<br />

which Aristotle calls<br />

faction, can, if it gets out of hand, become extremely destructive. While Aris<br />

totle suggests a number of strategies to contain the problem of faction, he


254 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

understands that it can never be eliminated from politics. Faction is inherent in<br />

the very nature of political society (see Bk. V).<br />

Aristotle's teaching<br />

on politics leads to the conclusion that there is no re<br />

lease for mankind from the age-old bondages of man to man and man to nature.<br />

At least there is no hope for universal progress or a general improvement in the<br />

human condition. With its aim of actualizing the complete good life, politics is<br />

an expression of the yearning of human beings for the fullness, completion, or<br />

perfection of their existence. This yearning shows itself in politics, however,<br />

principally in the particular claims to rule that are raised by the various parts of<br />

society. The assertion of these claims to rule leads to the disruptiveness of<br />

factional struggle. In politics, efforts to make things better are inevitably ac<br />

companied by conflicts that might well make them worse. The political struggle<br />

leads to the replacement of the rule of one part of society with its own particu<br />

lar conception of the common good by<br />

similarly<br />

the rule of some other part with a<br />

partial view. At best the new government is a marginal improvement<br />

over the old. The domination of man by man, however, continues unchanged.<br />

Political practice moves, then,<br />

within more or less fixed limits. These limits<br />

represent the forces that, from above, hold human beings in subjection. They<br />

make manifest the domination of man by nature. Consideration of the problems<br />

of politics leads to the conclusion that what is most needful for human beings is<br />

an understanding of the limits that define their existence. This involves reflec<br />

tion on the nature of man, the place of man in the order of things,<br />

and the<br />

power or powers that give man his being. The highest expression of the longing<br />

for completion is, therefore, to be found in the activity of contemplation. There<br />

is in this activity a kind of transcendence of the limits that define the life of<br />

man. Only the relatively few individuals, however, who have the leisure, incli<br />

nation, and ability necessary for the contemplative life can obtain this freedom.<br />

Liberalism's project for the emancipation of mankind from its traditional<br />

bondages receives its most comprehensive exposition in Hobbes's Leviathan.<br />

The premise of Hobbes's teaching is his denial that human beings can be under<br />

stood as being moved by the longing for the good. This is the most important<br />

chapters.5<br />

point of the materialist psychology that he elaborates in his first<br />

Hobbes concludes from his psychology that "there is no such Finis itltimis.<br />

(utmost ayme,) nor Summum Bonum, (greatest Good,)<br />

Books of the old Morall Philosophers."<br />

as is spoken of in the<br />

In its place, he proposes as "a generall<br />

inclination of all mankind, a perpetuall and restlesse desire of Power after<br />

power, that ceaseth only in Death."<br />

The cause of this ceaseless striving for<br />

power is that man "cannot assure the power and means to live well,<br />

which he<br />

hath present, without the acquisition of (Ch. 1, pp. 160-61). Politics<br />

does not, then, grow out of the longing for completion, fullness, or perfection.<br />

Rather it grows out of the competition for power understood as not so much the<br />

prerequisite as the substitute for the good. This is expressed in the doctrine of<br />

the state of nature. In the natural condition the competition tor power is unre-


David Hume's Theology of Liberation 255<br />

strained. As a result, there is no security for men in the enjoyment of their<br />

natural rights to life and what conduces to life, liberty, and property. The life<br />

of man in the natural condition is "solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and<br />

Human beings form political society, according to Hobbes,<br />

not to achieve the<br />

complete good life but only in order to escape the horrors of the state of nature<br />

(see Chs. 13-14).<br />

Government when properly organized-that is, in accordance with Hobbes's<br />

new science of politics-is nonpartisan. The exclusion from the public sphere of<br />

the question of the nature of the complete good life makes it impossible for any<br />

part of society to assert, on the basis of its special merits, a right to rule over<br />

the rest. Given that there is no publically accepted and enforced conception of<br />

the good, there is no foundation on which to rest such a claim to political<br />

power. More importantly, the depoliticization of the question of the nature of<br />

the good life has the effect of abolishing, at least for the purposes of politics<br />

and government, the qualitative distinctions among the different parts of soci<br />

ety. With no public definition of the good, there is nothing to make any indi<br />

vidual or group in any way special in the political order. This means that, at<br />

least from the point of view of politics and government,<br />

all human beings are<br />

equal. This in turn implies that, since there is no one who enjoys any<br />

short."<br />

natural or<br />

divine right to rule, all human beings are by nature free. The only legitimate<br />

basis for government authority is the consent of the governed. The governed<br />

presumably will give their consent to the formation of a government that will<br />

limit itself to the purpose of securing them against the dangers to life, liberty,<br />

and property of the state of nature. All legitimate government is, then, repre<br />

sentative in character, embodying<br />

both the consent and the interests of the<br />

whole of society. According to Hobbes, this is the case regardless of the<br />

form monarchic, aristocratic,<br />

Chs. 13, 17, and 19).<br />

or democratic in which it is organized (see<br />

Hobbes in his invention of nonpartisan government attempts what is, accord<br />

ing to the traditional understanding, the impossible: not merely to control but to<br />

solve the problem of factionalism. The cause of faction is the partisanship of<br />

government. The political system of representative government attacks fac<br />

tionalism at the level of its causes by replacing<br />

the partisan government of<br />

traditional society, in which a part rules over the whole in the name of some<br />

particular conception of the complete good life, with an essentially nonpartisan<br />

form of government, in which the whole rules over itself on behalf of goods<br />

that, while in themselves only partial, are universally<br />

desired. It is impossible,<br />

under representative government, for human beings to raise in public the ques<br />

tion of the nature of the good life. It is therefore impossible for them to come<br />

into conflict politically over the great issues that arise from this question, the<br />

issues of who should rule and for what purposes. From the point of view of<br />

representative government,<br />

they all imply something<br />

all opinions about the good life are false because<br />

of a natural or divine right to rule. It would be the


256 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

height of folly, then, to fight in politics over these opinions. Little is left to be<br />

struggled over in the public sphere,<br />

and what is left is not such as to engage<br />

men's most powerful passions. Politics is reduced to the struggle over who gets<br />

what of the essentially instrumental goods of society. It is almost, but not quite,<br />

subsumed by<br />

economics. In this situation human beings will retreat into their<br />

private affairs, which do engage their passions,<br />

and involve themselves in the<br />

public arena only when moved by threats to or opportunities for the advance<br />

ment of their special interests. There is little danger that this kind of politics<br />

will ever get out of hand and endanger the peace of society. This would be the<br />

last thing that its participants, animated primarily by essentially economic con<br />

cerns, would want to see happen. Prosperity accompanies peace. In Hobbes's<br />

new arrangement of political society, the stirring but frequently destructive<br />

clash of great parties is replaced by the unexciting but generally nondisruptive<br />

struggle of interest groups (see Chs. 21 and 24. On the topic of great and small<br />

parties, see Tocqueville, Democracy in America, Vol. I, Part II, Ch. 2, "Par<br />

ties in the United States.).<br />

The resolution of the problem of factionalism in Hobbes's new science of<br />

politics prepares the way for the general improvement of the human condition.<br />

The solution to the problem of faction involves a drastic narrowing of the pur<br />

poses of government, from the achievement of the complete good life to the<br />

security of the instrumental goods of life, liberty, and property. Ironically, this<br />

narrowing opens up<br />

hitherto unimagined possibilities for progress in society.<br />

Factionalism is an evil thing because it threatens the enjoyment by men of their<br />

natural rights, both directly, in the violent conflict that it only too frequently<br />

touches off, and indirectly, in the way that it interferes with the progress of<br />

modern natural science in its effort to conquer and master nature for the relief<br />

of man's estate. One aspect of the competition for political power among the<br />

various factions in society is a tension between the few wise, the philosophers<br />

or scientists, and the many unwise, the nonphilosophers or nonscientists.<br />

Through his system of nonpartisan government,<br />

which makes it impossible for<br />

either the few scientists or the many nonscientists to claim a right to rule over<br />

the other, Hobbes reconciles these two parts of society, guaranteeing to the few<br />

the freedom from interference by the many that they require for their investiga<br />

tions, while assuaging the fears that the many might harbor towards the few on<br />

account of the power that they have at their command. Peace is good not only<br />

as an end in itself but also as a necessary means for the achievement of a<br />

greater end, the emancipation of mankind from the bondage of natural necessity<br />

through the conquest of nature by modern science. On its deepest level,<br />

Hobbes's system of nonpartisan government is a means by which human beings<br />

can ally together to more effectually make war on nature.<br />

The conclusion of this alliance, according<br />

to liberal political philosophy,<br />

requires the separation of religion and politics. The establishment of the system<br />

of nonpartisan government requires the exclusion from the public sphere of the


essentially<br />

David Hume's Theology of Liberation 257<br />

religious question of the nature of the complete good life. This ex<br />

clusion takes the institutional form, in Hobbes's thought, of secular absolutism.<br />

Its more successful institutional form, however, is Locke's system of religious<br />

toleration. Involved in the question of the nature of the complete good life are<br />

issues of cosmic dimensions: the organization of the universe,<br />

man's place in<br />

the order of creation, the power or powers weaving together the whole. Tradi<br />

tional society,<br />

which places the question of the nature of the good life at the<br />

center of its politics, is profoundly religious. This is expressed in its fatalism,<br />

its submission to the given. The religious character of traditional society is<br />

expressed even more forcefully<br />

in its adherence to the contemplative ideal.<br />

Liberalism, by removing the question of the nature of the good life from poli<br />

from its traditional fatalism while<br />

tics, secularizes society. It releases society<br />

its traditional admiration for the contemplative life with a taste for<br />

supplanting<br />

action. Liberalism not only unites but sets in motion traditional society.<br />

Through the separation of religion and politics liberalism intends to bring about<br />

a revolutionary change in the way men are governed, and out of that a radical<br />

transformation of the human condition. The political system of representative<br />

government abolishes the domination of man by man, and makes possible the<br />

abolition of the domination of man by nature. Liberalism is eminently sober in<br />

its politics; its sobriety, however, is in the service of a kind of madness, the<br />

scientific conquest of nature. There is something divine, at least Dionysian, in<br />

the liberal project. The works on religion of the liberal political philosophers,<br />

including Hume's Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, articulate this Di<br />

onysian dimension of liberalism.<br />

Hume's adoption of the dialogue form in his Dialogues Concerning Natural<br />

Religion is a rarity in modern philosophy. One of the characters in the work<br />

asserts that "though the ancient philosophers conveyed most of their instruction<br />

in the form of dialogue, this method of composition has been little practiced in<br />

later ages, and has seldom succeeded in the hands of those who have attempted<br />

it."<br />

Modern philosophy aims at the development of comprehensive systems,<br />

beginning with indubitable first principles and moving by<br />

unbroken chains of<br />

reasoning and evidence to arrive at sure final conclusions. It therefore tends to<br />

slip<br />

ophy<br />

into a "methodical and<br />

didactic"<br />

mode of exposition (p. 3). Modern philos<br />

is systematic because of its intention or purpose to master and conquer<br />

nature: it reforms nature in theory in preparation for its reconstruction in prac<br />

tice. Its principal instrument in this project is modern natural science. Hume<br />

does not, in his own name,<br />

explain his choice of the dialogue form for his<br />

treatment of natural religion. He indicates by his choice, however, that there is<br />

a limit to how far modern philosophy can be made systematic. Natural religion


258 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

is the set of beliefs about God that supposedly can be derived, without the aid<br />

of divine revelation, by reasoning on the observation or experience of the uni<br />

verse. It concerns, then, the cause or ground of all being. Choosing the dia<br />

logue form to present his teaching on natural religion, Hume implies that there<br />

is a problem in the metaphysical foundations of systematic modern philosophy.<br />

This, in turn, implies a problem for the conduct of the modern project of the<br />

scientific conquest of nature. Hume's purpose in the Dialogues is to define and,<br />

to the extent possible, to resolve this problem in the theory and practice of<br />

modernity.<br />

in his own<br />

Hume masks his intentions in the Dialogues by never speaking<br />

device of a narrator who<br />

voice. He accomplishes this by adopting the literary<br />

introduces the discussion,<br />

makes unobtrusive comments on the arguments and<br />

the actions of the interlocutors, and concludes by rendering judgment on the<br />

debate.6<br />

The narrator, the youth Pamphilus,<br />

records for his friend Hermippus a<br />

conversation that he recently overheard on the subject of religion among three<br />

older men, Cleanthes, Philo, and Demea. This conversation is of interest not<br />

only because of the topic with which it deals but also because of the extraordin<br />

ary differences in the characters of its participants. Pamphilus contrasts "the<br />

accurate philosophical turn of Cleanthes"<br />

Philo"<br />

and the "rigid inflexible orthodoxy of Demea"<br />

conversation, Pamphilus, "upon a serious review of the<br />

with the "careless scepticism of<br />

(p. 4). At the close of the<br />

whole,"<br />

decides that<br />

"Philo's principles are more probable than Demea's, but that those of Cleanthes<br />

approach still nearer to the<br />

truth"<br />

(p. 95). This verdict seems curiously obtuse.<br />

Philo is the dominant, or at least the most vocal, participant in the conversa<br />

tion. Many of his arguments are left unanswered. He states the conclusions of<br />

the discussion. If Cleanthes really is the victor in the confrontation with Philo,<br />

he must win by stealth or even fraud rather than by force. It is possible, how<br />

ever, that Pamphilus is not a fit judge for the debate. He is young. He is likely<br />

to be partial towards Cleanthes, his friend and teacher (see pp. 4-5). Perhaps<br />

he underrates the arguments of Demea and Philo while overlooking problems<br />

with Cleanthes'<br />

markably<br />

arguments. At the same time, it is necessary to note the re<br />

Pamphilus'<br />

reserved character of judgment: Cleanthes'<br />

not simply true, but "nearer to the<br />

truth"<br />

than Philo's.<br />

principles are<br />

Pamphilus takes up in his introduction the question of the purpose of writing<br />

dialogues. He claims that the dialogue form is appropriate whenever the issue is<br />

not only "so obvious that it scarcely admits of<br />

that it cannot be too often inculcated,"<br />

dispute,"<br />

but also "so important<br />

the freshness of the presentation making<br />

up for the hackneyed character of the topic. The dialogue form is also appropri<br />

ate when the issue is "so obscure and uncertain that human reason can reach no<br />

fixed determination"<br />

without any decision"<br />

on it. In this case the play of "opposite sentiments, even<br />

offers "an agreeable<br />

amusement<br />

The reader enters into<br />

a kind of community of interest and sympathy with the interlocutors. In this<br />

way the dialogue "unites the two greatest and purest pleasures of<br />

life-<br />

human


study and<br />

David Hume's Theology of Liberation 259<br />

society"<br />

(pp. 3-4). The subject of natural religion combines all these<br />

circumstances: there is no topic so obvious but important as the being of God,<br />

no topic so obscure and uncertain as the nature of God (p. 4). How the dialogue<br />

form might be utilized to "unite study and<br />

society"<br />

is indicated in a comment<br />

by Philo on Galileo's Dialogue of the Two Principal Systems of<br />

the World. In<br />

this book, Galileo has his characters discuss the common or received opinion<br />

that terrestrial and celestial substances are distinct in their nature and behavior.<br />

The dialogue form allows him to meet the "full force of<br />

his "arguments on every side in order to render them popular and<br />

prejudic<br />

by turning<br />

(p. 24). Galileo's intention in the Dialogue, of course, is to demolish the meta<br />

conv<br />

physical foundations of the Ptolemaic conception of the universe and to provide<br />

the metaphysical foundations for the new Copernican conception. Galileo's rev<br />

olution in astronomy contributed, however, to the demise of the traditional<br />

world and the creation of the modern world. Galileo uses the dialogue form,<br />

then, to "unite study and<br />

society"<br />

by refounding society<br />

truths that he has discovered through study.<br />

on the basis of the<br />

Hume reveals his intention in the Dialogues, to the extent that he does re<br />

veal it, in the dramatic structure of the work. This involves, in addition to the<br />

characters'<br />

arguments, their actions and designs. The arguments are so absorb<br />

ing that it is easy to overlook the other elements of the drama. The characters<br />

conceal, or at least do not loudly proclaim, their intentions. They<br />

in their actions, generally speaking showing themselves in nothing<br />

are subdued<br />

but facial<br />

expressions and tones of voice, commented on apparently in passing by Pam<br />

philus. This is altogether appropriate for the situation and the setting: a conver<br />

sation among a few old friends,<br />

on a topic of general rather than immediate<br />

practical interest, carried on in the genial surroundings of the library of one of<br />

the participants. The discussion among Cleanthes, Philo,<br />

and Demea on the<br />

subject of natural religion, however, is no idle chat but a rhetorical contest, a<br />

kind of war, with<br />

Pamphilus'<br />

soul as the prize for the victor. The older men<br />

debate the principles that ought to guide the young men's education. It begins<br />

as a dispute between traditionalist piety and modernist activism. It quickly be<br />

comes a dispute between two fundamentally different conceptions of modernist<br />

activism, however. Demea proposes to Cleanthes a plan, ultimately borrowed<br />

from the ancient moralist Plutarch, for educating Pamphilus. Apparently<br />

troubled by the way Cleanthes is handling<br />

him the "useful"<br />

he is<br />

the youth's education, imparting to<br />

elements of the arts and sciences. For Demea, the point of<br />

education is not action but contemplation. His plan culminates in the study of<br />

"the nature of the<br />

gods."<br />

Before the subject of theology is broached, however,<br />

the mind of the student must be well seasoned with piety. This is accomplished<br />

through a kind of sceptical attack on human reason, by continually pointing out<br />

during the study<br />

thought.<br />

of the other sciences the failures of man's natural powers of<br />

Philo, complimenting Demea on his plan of education, agrees that religious


260 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

faith must be based on scepticism about the capabilities of human reason.<br />

"Those who enter a little into study and inquiry,"<br />

he claims,<br />

all too often come<br />

to believe that nothing is beyond the reason of man; then, "presumptuously<br />

breaking<br />

ple."<br />

through all fences,"<br />

they<br />

"profane the inmost sanctuaries of the tem<br />

Human beings move beyond the reach of their intellectual abilities when<br />

they speculate on religious subjects, in particular the creation of the universe.<br />

The only defense against presumptuousness is to set before them the limits of<br />

human reason, including<br />

ples in all<br />

"the insuperable difficulties which attend first princi<br />

systems"<br />

and "the contradictions which adhere to the very ideas of<br />

matter, cause and effect, extension, space, time,<br />

are better off when they<br />

motion"<br />

(p. 6). Human beings<br />

confine their specualtions to thisworldly<br />

topics, in<br />

cluding trade and politics (p. 9). Cleanthes admits the use of a moderate scepti<br />

cism that considers "each particular evidence<br />

to the precise degree of evidence which<br />

natural, mathematical, moral, and political<br />

cal and<br />

apart,"<br />

and proportions its "assent<br />

occurs."<br />

This is the basis for "all<br />

science."<br />

He insists that "theologi<br />

religious"<br />

science can and must be built up using this same kind of<br />

reasoning. He follows Locke in affirming that "faith [is] nothing but a species<br />

of<br />

reason,"<br />

that "religion [is] only<br />

principles of theology"<br />

a branch of<br />

are established by<br />

those employed in "morals, politics, or<br />

philosoph<br />

and that "all the<br />

"a chain of<br />

arguments"<br />

similar to<br />

physics"<br />

(p. 11-13). Based on the<br />

observation of design in the universe, Cleanthes argues that the "Author of<br />

nature is somewhat similar to the mind of<br />

man"<br />

(p. 17). Demea is scandalized<br />

and Philo somewhat amused by the comparison between the divine and the<br />

human. All three of the participants in the conversation are, then, sceptics of<br />

one sort or another. They derive very different practical and theoretical conclu<br />

sions from their scepticisms, however. Demea is led to the piety and rationalist<br />

theorizing<br />

of traditionalist religiosity. Philo comes to a kind of moderate mod<br />

ern scientific empiricism. He distinguishes between heavenly and earthly mat<br />

ters and restricts the quest for scientific understanding to the latter,<br />

signing<br />

while con<br />

the former to perpetual doubt and uncertainty. Cleanthes is a<br />

thoroughgoing scientific empiricist, who applies the methods of modern science<br />

to the study of all beings, both on the earth and in the heavens (see p. 26). In<br />

spite of their differences, Demea and Philo are able to ally together to combat<br />

Cleanthes, with Philo bearing the heat of the battle, subjecting his arguments to<br />

a barrage of sceptical criticisms.<br />

Two separate conflicts then, shape the drama of Hume's Dialogues. The<br />

first, of course, is the confrontation between the traditional rationalist Demea<br />

and the modern empiricist Cleanthes. The second, and more interesting, is the<br />

confrontation between the two modern empiricists, Cleanthes and Philo. These<br />

separate conflicts are intermingled, however, as a result of the alliance con<br />

cluded between Philo and Demea against Cleanthes. The drama has as its cen<br />

tral motif, then, the rise and fall of the alliance between the modernist sceptic<br />

and the representative of traditionalist orthodoxy. Formed at the beginning of


David Hume's Theology of Liberation 261<br />

Part I, it suffers stresses and strains throughout the dialogue, and finally disin<br />

tegrates at the end of Part XL It falls apart under the pressure of Philo's relent<br />

less sceptical questioning, particularly when he touches on the issue of evil in<br />

the world and what it might or might not imply for the benevolence of the<br />

Deity. The alliance's fate is the result of the fundamental differences between<br />

the two allies. These differences are clearly recognized by Cleanthes at the time<br />

of its formation. He smiles at what he perceives as satire when Philo proclaims<br />

his approval of Demea's approach to education (p. 7). Demea and Philo come<br />

together on the basis of what appears as their mutual scepticism about the reach<br />

of human reason. They differ profoundly, however, over the practical use to<br />

which the theoretical critique of human reason should be put. For Demea, the<br />

use of scepticism is to tame the mind to "a proper submission and self-diffi<br />

dence"<br />

(p. 5). It supports traditionalist piety,<br />

with its resignation to the given.<br />

For Philo, however, scepticism is useful as a discipline for the mind in its<br />

struggle to understand and ultimately to control the world. It leads the mind to<br />

be cautious in its reasonings, especially on the most abstruse topics, and to base<br />

all of its conclusions on the solid foundation of experience. It induces the mind<br />

to restrict its speculations to the sphere of common experience, leaving alone<br />

such transcentental questions as "the two eternities, before and after the present<br />

state of things,"<br />

the "creation and formation of the<br />

universe,<br />

and the "powers<br />

and operations of one universal Spirit existing without beginning and end, om<br />

nipotent, omniscient, immutable, infinite,<br />

and incomprehensible"<br />

(pp. 9-10).<br />

Scepticism supports, then, the modern project of the scientific mastery and<br />

conquest of nature.<br />

The differences between Demea and Philo are summed up in the distinction<br />

introduced by Cleanthes, between vulgar and philosophic<br />

scepticism.7<br />

Vulgar<br />

sceptics "reject every principle which requires elaborate reasoning to prove and<br />

establish."<br />

This sustains "traditional<br />

superstition"<br />

while precluding the ad<br />

vancement of scientific knowledge. Vulgar sceptics "firmly believe in witches,<br />

though they will not believe nor attend to the most simple proposition of Eu<br />

clid."<br />

Philosophic sceptics push their speculations into recondite subjects but<br />

refrain from drawing any conclusions except from hard evidence. They<br />

are led<br />

by their theoretical scrupulousness, however, to assume that the highest ques<br />

tions, in particular theological questions, are beyond the reach of human rea<br />

son. For Cleanthes, men of philosophy or science should be willing when in<br />

vestigating matters of religion to make the same kind of empirically based<br />

judgments that they do with respect to matters of a more mundane character (p.<br />

11). Philo, in contrast, compares philosophers or scientists dealing with reli<br />

gious questions to "foreigners in a strange land to whom everything must seem<br />

suspicious, and who are in danger every moment of transgressing against the<br />

laws and customs of the people with whom they live and<br />

So far<br />

from common experience, all arguments look equally reasonable,<br />

equally<br />

unreasonable. "The<br />

conver<br />

or rather<br />

mind,"<br />

Philo claims, "must remain in suspense


262 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

between<br />

(p. 10).<br />

them,"<br />

and this "suspense or<br />

balance'<br />

Philo and Cleanthes are both partisans of modernity,<br />

is "the triumph of<br />

scientific conquest of nature. They agree on its superiority<br />

giosity and rationalist theorizing<br />

scept<br />

with its project for the<br />

to the pious reli<br />

of traditionalism. This area of agreement is<br />

obscured by the rhetorical concessions that Philo makes to Demea, required by<br />

the alliance between the two. Philo and Cleanthes disagree powerfully, how<br />

ever, in their understandings of the theoretical foundations of modern science.<br />

They differ over the question of whether modern science pertains to only<br />

"earthly"<br />

or to both "earthly" "heavenly"<br />

and<br />

matters that is, whether it pre<br />

supposes a specific theology or metaphysics. This theoretical disagreement has<br />

practical consequences for the conduct of the modern project. If modern sci<br />

ence has no theology or metaphysics of its own, then there is no necessary<br />

conflict between it and traditional belief, and reconciliation between modernity<br />

and traditionalism is at least possible. This is Philo's position. It is reflected in<br />

the alliance he forms with Demea in Part I. If, however, modern science has its<br />

own theology or metaphysics, then conflict between it and traditional belief is<br />

inevitable, and there is no possibility of a reconciliation between modernity and<br />

traditionalism. This is Cleanthes'<br />

position. It is reflected in the withering attack<br />

he makes on Demea's a priori argument on the nature of God in Part IX.<br />

Indicatively, Philo backs away from a frontal assault on Demea in Part IX. He<br />

criticizes Demea's a priori argument, but only on practical grounds. It is un<br />

likely, he claims, to convince anyone except "people of a metaphysical head<br />

who have accustomed themselves to abstract<br />

reasoning.<br />

Cleanthes is, then,<br />

more intransigent or radical in his modernism than Philo. It is Philo, not Cle<br />

anthes, who attempts to compromise with traditionalism. Cleanthes'<br />

radicalism<br />

can easily be overlooked, however, because of his own reserve and because of<br />

Philo's argumentative pyrotechnics (see p. 44).<br />

Hume's Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion presents dramatically the<br />

confrontation of two different practical approaches to the modern project of the<br />

scientific conquest of nature, based on two very different conceptions of the<br />

theoretical foundations of modern natural science. The crucial practical prob<br />

lem is the relationship between modernity and tradition: can the modern project<br />

be pursued within the intellectual, social, and political framework of tradi<br />

tionalism, or does it require the overthrow of traditionalism? The decisive theo<br />

retical issue is the place of theology or metaphysics in the structure of modern<br />

natural science: can modern natural science be constructed on the basis of thor<br />

oughgoing scepticism about the highest questions,<br />

or does it presuppose a cer<br />

tain theology or metaphysics? In the Dialogues, Hume indicates his answers to<br />

these questions in the movement of the drama. The alliance between the ""care<br />

less<br />

sceptic"<br />

Philo and the "rigidly<br />

orthodox"<br />

Demea breaks down, despite all<br />

of Philo's efforts to placate Demea (see, e.g., p. 19). Eventually Demea sees<br />

Philo as perhaps "a more dangerous enemy than Cleanthes himself,"<br />

the result


David Hume's Theology of Liberation 263<br />

into all the topics of the greatest libertines and infidels"<br />

(p. 80).<br />

of his "running<br />

He is so deeply offended that he leaves the conversation. Perhaps Philo care<br />

lessly allows himself to be lured or goaded on in his questioning by Cleanthes<br />

(see, e.g., pp. 44, 71). At any rate it turns out to be simply impossible for him<br />

to sustain his cooperative relationship with Demea. Science ultimately cannot<br />

recognize the distinction between "earth"<br />

and "heaven."<br />

In the end, Philo is left<br />

with Cleanthes, reconciled to him. And even though it is Philo who states the<br />

conclusions of the dialogue, thost'conclusions are essentially Cleanthes'<br />

Philo<br />

limns out a theology or metaphysics based on the understanding that "the cause<br />

or causes of order in the universe probably bear some remote analogy to human<br />

intelligence"<br />

Pamphilus in judging .<br />

(p. 94; compare p. 17). Hume would undoubtedly agree with his<br />

the outcome of the conversation He<br />

is as intransigent or<br />

radical in his modernism as his character Cleanthes. The fact that Hume writes<br />

the Dialogues along with so many other works on religion indicates that he<br />

agrees with the position espoused by Cleanthes. He conveys in the Dialogues a<br />

revolutionary teaching. It is disguised, however, by the reserve of his character<br />

Cleanthes and the apparent radicalism of his character Philo. Hume adopts the<br />

dialogue form in the Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion in order to "unite<br />

study and<br />

foundations and practical consequences of the modern project of the scientific<br />

conquest of nature.<br />

Ill<br />

society"<br />

on the basis of his radical conception of the theoretical<br />

Hume in the Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion develops what has<br />

been called his theology of liberation out of the dialectal confrontation of De<br />

mea, Philo, and Cleanthes. No one of these characters simply speaks for<br />

Hume. All at least on occasion use distinctively Humean arguments (see e.g.,<br />

pp. 20-21 [Philo]; 30-32 [Demea]; 58-59 [Cleanthes]). From Hume's point of<br />

view, however, they all err in important ways. Demea goes astray in his rejec<br />

tion of modern empirical science. Philo is wrong on the fundamental practical<br />

and theoretical issues pertaining to the modern project: modernity cannot come<br />

to terms with traditionalism because it presupposes its own profoundly anti-<br />

traditional theology or metaphysics. While Cleathes is right on the fundamental<br />

practical and theoretical issues, he appears to be overly optimistic about the<br />

prospects for the modern project. The conclusions Cleanthes seems to want to<br />

draw from the relationship between the human mind and the cause of order in<br />

the universe, for example concerning the benevolence towards man of the first<br />

cause, Philo shows by his questioning to be unwarranted (see, e.g., p. 55). If<br />

Hume has a spokesman, it is Pamphilus, who introduces the discussion, com<br />

ments on the characters and actions of the participants, and judges the outcome<br />

of the debate.1*<br />

Hume, however, does what he can to hide this by raising doubts


264 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

about Pamphilus'<br />

judgment, making him young and potentially<br />

biased. At the<br />

end of the discussion, Philo sums up what seem to be its conclusions. "The<br />

cause, or causes of order in the<br />

universe,"<br />

he claims, "probably bear some<br />

remote analogy to human intelligence This proposition, however, does not<br />

allow for "extension, variation,<br />

or more particular<br />

explication."<br />

The analogy<br />

between the mind of man and the cause of order in the universe applies only to<br />

man's intelligence and cannot be transferred to "the other qualities of the<br />

mind,"<br />

by which he means its moral attributes. Finally this proposition "affords<br />

no inference that affects human life, or can be the source of any action or<br />

forbearance"<br />

(p. 94). This cold, even frigid, theology provides the foundation<br />

for the project in liberal political philosophy for the liberation of man from his<br />

traditional bondages to man and to nature.<br />

The pious traditionalist Demea plays a crucial, albeit ironic, role in the de<br />

velopment of the Dialogues'<br />

theology. He of course initiates the discussion of<br />

the subject of religion. This is only the beginning of his influence on the dis<br />

cussion portrayed in the dialogue, however. Demea time and time again<br />

changes the direction of the argument by raising<br />

objections to what he senses<br />

are its unorthodox implications. He cuts off the discussion at sensitive points.<br />

At the same time, and apparently without a clear understanding of what he is<br />

doing, he turns it in new and fruitful directions. This first occurs at the begin<br />

ning of Part II, when Demea rebukes Cleanthes for the tenor of his remarks on<br />

the empirical foundations of religion, taking him to imply that it is necessary to<br />

defend the thesis of the existence of God. Asserting that the existence of God is<br />

something that no man of common sense can doubt, he insists that the debate<br />

be about the nature rather than the being of God. This, he avers, is altogether<br />

incomprehensible to the finite human mind. Cleanthes responds with his design<br />

argument. The next time Demea gets stirred up is at the beginning of Part VI.<br />

Cleanthes'<br />

design argument leaves too much in doubt. It leads to a religion that<br />

is altogether useless for the purposes of life, positing a Deity who is no possible<br />

object of trust, worship,<br />

or obedience. Demea demands an account of the na<br />

ture of God that allows human beings to repose their confidence in Him.<br />

In Part IX Demea, having<br />

seen some of the problems with a posteriori argu<br />

ments concerning the nature of God, tries his hand at an a priori argument. To<br />

this Cleanthes delivers a devastating critique, demonstrating the impossibility<br />

of a priori proof of any matter of fact, including not just the nature but the very<br />

existence of God. Rebounding from this criticism, Demea at the beginning of<br />

Part X attempts his own a posteriori argument. He asserts that the truth of<br />

religion is established not by abstract reasoning but by the sentiments. Human<br />

beings are compelled by the fear of death, pain, and the rest of life's woes to<br />

seek protection from a Supreme Being. Offended by the inferences which Philo<br />

draws out of the reality of human misery, suffering, and sorrow, Demea with<br />

draws from the conversation at the end of Part XI. After Demea departs, Philo<br />

delivers his judgments on the questions of the existence and nature of God,


David Hume'<br />

s Theology of Liberation 265<br />

which are left by Cleanthes to stand as the conclusions of the whole discussion.<br />

Demea's eruptions, then, move the argument through its various themes, giving<br />

it a kind of hidden order or structure. They<br />

divide it into three major sections,<br />

each devoted to a single theme or topic. This perhaps accounts for the peculiar<br />

plural in the title of the Dialogues, which to all outward appearances portrays a<br />

single continuous conversation. Thanks to Demea, while the argument seems to<br />

wander more or less aimlessly, it actually examines the most important teach<br />

ings of traditional or orthodox theism, the omniscience, omnipotence, and be<br />

nevolence of God. It reformulates these teachings in the light of the empiricism<br />

of modern philosophy and science. Its reformulations of the traditional teach<br />

ings on the nature of God comprise a kind of theology of modernity. The<br />

absence of Demea when the conclusions of the argument are stated serves to<br />

underscore the profoundly unorthodox or antitraditional character of this new<br />

theology.<br />

The omniscience of God is the theme of the first section Part II through<br />

Part V of the Dialogues. God, for Demea, is the "supreme Mind,"<br />

but due to<br />

the infirmities of human reason He is altogether incomprehensible to the mind<br />

of man (p. 15). Philo agrees that the only way for "reasonable to think<br />

about the Deity is to assume that He is unknowable. Since nothing<br />

can exist<br />

without a cause, there must be a cause of the universe; the universe's cause,<br />

"whatever it be,"<br />

human beings call God. They piously<br />

impute to Him all<br />

perfection, including thought. Since what they conceive as perfection is relative<br />

to their own experience, however, what they say about the Divinity indicates<br />

nothing about His real nature. Infinitely above the limited understanding of<br />

human beings, the Supreme Being is "more the object of worship in the temple<br />

than of disputation in the<br />

what he calls Philo's<br />

"pious declamations,"<br />

schools"<br />

(p. 16). Ignoring<br />

Cleanthes argues that the nature of the Deity<br />

deduced from the evidence of design, "the curious adapting of means to<br />

can be<br />

throughout the universe. The resemblance of design in God's world to design in<br />

man's works allows for the inference, "by all the rules of<br />

some similarity between the mind of man and the "Author of<br />

Demea objects to Cleanthes'<br />

ends,"<br />

analogy,<br />

that there is<br />

nature"<br />

(p. 17).<br />

argument because, based on experience rather<br />

than abstract reasoning, it gives only a probable and not a necessary proof of<br />

the existence and nature of God. Philo objects not because the argument is<br />

based on experience, nor even because it makes use of analogy, but because the<br />

analogy<br />

it appeals to is weak. The differences between the universe and man's<br />

creations are too great for any legitimate comparisons to be made between their<br />

causes. Philo's concessions to Cleanthes outrage Demea, however, and in order<br />

to placate his ally he restates and strengthens his criticism. The crux of his<br />

argument is that since there are many "springs and principles of the<br />

it is impossible to trace the origin of the universe to any one of them. No<br />

conclusion about the cause of the whole can be derived from observation of the<br />

causes of change in any part. It is as unreasonable for human beings to make


266 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

their own thought the model for the organization of the universe as it would be<br />

for a peasant to make "his domestic economy the rule for the government of<br />

kingdoms"<br />

(p. 22).<br />

Cleanthes rejects Philo's dissociation of human and divine intelligence as<br />

fatal to the progress of science. He reminds Philo, who just before had been<br />

discussing Galileo's Dialogues, that "Copernicus and his first disciples,"<br />

obvi<br />

ously referring to Galileo, were compelled to demonstrate "the similarity of the<br />

terrestrial and celestial matter, because several philosophers, blinded by old<br />

systems and supported by some sensible appearances, had denied this sim<br />

ilarity."<br />

Philo's argument is no better than the "abstruse<br />

who hold that the universe is unchanging,<br />

cavils"<br />

of the Eleatics,<br />

a whole without parts (p. 26).<br />

Philo's argument implies that the universe is nothing but change, parts without<br />

a whole. In neither case is speech or reason about the universe possible. Rea<br />

soning about the universe involves connecting<br />

to require, for Cleanthes, assuming<br />

parts with the whole. This seems<br />

some kind of intention or purpose as the<br />

first cause of the whole. It is necessary, in order to think about the behavior of<br />

the beings that make up the universe, to impute to them some kind of purpose.<br />

The purposiveness of the parts will then be reflected in the structure of the<br />

whole. From Cleanthes'<br />

point of view, human beings, to reason about the uni<br />

verse, have no choice but to make their "domestic<br />

economy<br />

the "rule for the<br />

government"<br />

of the whole. The analogy between the universe and the works of<br />

man is self-evident: they<br />

involve "the same<br />

matter"<br />

and "a like form."<br />

clinches his point with two illustrations, an intelligible voice from the clouds<br />

and a library of naturally propagating books. Both these circumstances would<br />

allow the inference of a superhuman reason or intelligence. There is more evi<br />

dence of design in the works of nature, however, than in any speech or any<br />

book. He demands, then, that Philo "assert either that a rational volume is no<br />

proof of a rational cause or admit of a similar<br />

ever cavils may be<br />

coherent, articulate speech,<br />

design and intention."<br />

He<br />

cause"<br />

to the universe. "What<br />

urged,"<br />

Cleanthes affirms, "an orderly world, as well as a<br />

embarrassed and confounded (pp. 26-29).<br />

Philo apparently accepts Cleanthes'<br />

cussion after a long<br />

will still be received as an incontestable proof of<br />

This argument, according to Pamphilus, leaves Philo<br />

argument. When he returns to the dis<br />

period of silence perhaps the longest in the whole conver<br />

sation he shifts, decisively, the point of his attack. He does not return to his<br />

earlier position, that no conclusion regarding the cause of the universe can be<br />

derived from its visible order. He tacitly accedes to Cleanthes'<br />

essential point,<br />

concerning the theoretical Cleanthes'<br />

necessity of what calls his "hypothesis of<br />

universe"<br />

design in the (p. 41; see also pp. 66, 70, 82). Philo is rescued from<br />

his embarrassment by his ally Demea, who picks up the argument with Cle<br />

anthes. God is incomprehensible to man, according to Demea, because man is<br />

a compound being and God is One. The mind of man, according to Demea, is a<br />

"composition of various faculties, passions, sentiments, ideas."<br />

This is incom-


patible with the "perfect<br />

admits that a perfectly simple being<br />

of the Deity as perfectly<br />

David Hume's Theology of Liberation 267<br />

simplicity"<br />

of the Deity (pp. 31-32). Cleanthes readily<br />

simple are "complete<br />

is incomprehensible. Those who conceive<br />

mystics"<br />

(p. 32). Mystics, of<br />

course, do not reason about the universe and its causes. Cleanthes'<br />

design argu<br />

ment implies that the first cause of all things is not simple but compounded. It<br />

is a whole with parts. The order of the beings in the universe is a reflection of<br />

the order of the elements in the first cause. To reason about the universe and its<br />

causes ultimately means to attempt to find an account of the hidden order of the<br />

causes that displays within itself the manifest order of the universe. When Philo<br />

returns to the discussion, he makes this the point of his criticism of Cleanthes'<br />

argument.9<br />

He restricts himself to pointing out the "inconveniences"<br />

calls<br />

Cleanthes' "anthropomorphism."<br />

of what he<br />

It leads to a multiplicity of possible<br />

causes. There are, in accordance with the "hypothesis of design in the uni<br />

verse,"<br />

many Dieties, many possible orderings of the first cause (p. 41). Philo<br />

admits to Cleanthes that "a man who follows your hypothesis is able, perhaps,<br />

to assert or conjecture that the universe sometime arose from something like<br />

design"; beyond that, however, "he cannot ascertain one single circumstance,<br />

and is left afterwards to fix every point of his theology by the utmost license of<br />

fancy<br />

and hypothesis"<br />

"horror"<br />

but with "pleasure"<br />

(p. 40). Cleanthes views Philo's arguments not with<br />

(p. 41). There is, then, a rational design or order<br />

to the universe; it is up to human beings, however, as part of their effort to<br />

understand scientifically the universe, to say just what that rational design or<br />

order might be.<br />

This raises a question about the omnipotence of God. This is the theme of<br />

the second major section of the Dialogues, from Part VI through Part VIII. The<br />

relationship between the themes of the omniscience and the omnipotence of the<br />

Deity is indicated in the structure of the dialogue in two ways. Philo takes up<br />

the argument in the second section explicitly as an extension of one of his most<br />

important points in the first section, that Cleanthes'<br />

on the premise that "like effects arise from like<br />

design argument is based<br />

causes"<br />

(p. 42). More impor<br />

tantly, Demea's attempt in Part IX at an a priori argument on the nature of<br />

God, so out of place in the dialogue as a whole, effectively brackets together<br />

the first and second sections. Philo points out that, on Cleanthes'<br />

"like effects like<br />

premise of<br />

causes,"<br />

it is possible to conceive of the universe as an<br />

animal, since it has many of the properties of animals, including the orderly<br />

connection of parts to the whole. This makes the Deity the soul of the universe,<br />

"actuating it, and actuated by it."<br />

Cleanthes demurs, but only slightly, to sug<br />

gest that the analogy is even stronger to plants. Both animals and plants have<br />

their own internal principles of order and change. Philo argues, then, that it is<br />

plausible to "ascribe an eternal inherent principle of order in the world, though<br />

attended with great and continual revolutions and<br />

is "a theory that we must sooner or later have recourse to,<br />

alteration<br />

This, he claims,<br />

whatever system we<br />

embrace."<br />

In the world of Philo's theory, there is no room for chance (pp. 42-


268 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

46). There are, however, many principles of motion in the universe, including<br />

reason, instinct, generation, and vegetation. It is possible, he asserts, for hu<br />

man beings to choose any one of these as the basis for a "system of cos<br />

mogony."<br />

Any account of the whole involves a choice about first principles or<br />

causes. He illustrates his point by referring<br />

(pp. 49-51). This argument conceals a fallacy, however,<br />

to Greek and Hindu cosmologies<br />

which Cleanthes at<br />

least dimly perceives (see p. 51). The fallacy is in Philo's claim that there is no<br />

room for chance in the universe. Chance exists, if nowhere else, in the choice<br />

of first principles by human beings. This is by no means an inconsequential<br />

matter, as is indicated by the examples of the Greek and Hindu cosmologies.<br />

Human beings create great civilizations through the cosmologies they pose for<br />

themselves. These civilizations, in turn,<br />

shape the ways of life of their peoples.<br />

This means that human beings in effect create themselves through their choices<br />

of first principles. The first cause of all things is, then, some kind of combina<br />

tion of necessity and chance. These two together are perhaps omnipotent.<br />

While they are immutable, however, they allow for the mutability<br />

of human<br />

history, its movement reflecting the combination of the fundamental principles<br />

of chance and necessity. The first cause is, then, essentially the transhistorical<br />

ground of history, expressing itself and its power particularly in the self-mak<br />

ing, historical activity of human beings.<br />

The question of the benevolence of the Deity is taken up in the last section<br />

of the Dialogues, in Parts X and XI. This issue arises out of a consideration of<br />

evil in the world. Nature, according to Demea, has kindled a ""perpetual<br />

among all living<br />

war"<br />

creatures. Human beings can protect themselves from at least<br />

some of nature's threats by uniting in society. Philo points out, however, that<br />

this only creates new evils for them. By coming together in society they are<br />

able to surmount all their "real<br />

enemies"<br />

and make themselves masters of "the<br />

whole animal creation"; at the same time, however, they<br />

"imaginary<br />

enemies,"<br />

the "demons"<br />

of their imagination,<br />

"superstitious terrors and blast every enjoyment of life."<br />

raise for themselves<br />

who haunt them with<br />

Society<br />

also sets hu<br />

man beings against each other. Afflicting one another with "oppression, injus<br />

tice, contempt, contumely, violence, sedition, war, calumny, treachery, fraud,"<br />

they would quickly dissolve society<br />

if it were not for the evils that would come<br />

with separating (p. 63). Philo challenges Cleanthes to maintain his "anthro<br />

pomorphism"<br />

in the face of the reality of evil in the world. It is impossible, he<br />

argues, to claim that the "moral attributes of the Deity,"<br />

including<br />

His benevo<br />

lence, are "of the same nature with these virtues in human (p. 66).<br />

Cleanthes admits the importance of the issue. There would be no purpose in<br />

demonstrating<br />

be left "doubtful and<br />

ness of<br />

the "natural attributes of the Deity"<br />

if His moral attributes should<br />

uncertain."<br />

He therefore denies the "misery and wicked<br />

man."<br />

The good outweighs the bad in human life (pp. 67-68).<br />

Philo cautions Cleanthes that by taking his stand on this line he is "introduc-


ing<br />

David Hume's Theology of Liberation<br />

- 269<br />

a total scepticism into the most essential articles of natural and revealed<br />

theology."<br />

Even assuming the preponderance of good over evil, this is insuffi<br />

cient to prove the benevolence of the Deity. If He is infinitely powerful, there<br />

should be no evil whatsoever in the world (pp. 68-69). Cleanthes attempts to<br />

save the benevolence of the "Author of<br />

nature"<br />

by positing that He is finitely<br />

powerful. He is benevolent, but limited by necessity (p. 71). Philo shows,<br />

however, that while the thesis of the finitude of the Deity might save His<br />

benevolence as an hypothesis, it cannot establish it as a fact. No inference<br />

concerning<br />

the benevolence of the first cause of the universe can be drawn from<br />

the mixture of good and evil in the world. The presence of evil is the result of<br />

a number of circumstances in the organization of the universe that might or<br />

might not be necessary to it. These circumstances include the use of "pains, as<br />

well as to "excite all creatures to action"; the "conducting<br />

world by general laws"; the "frugality<br />

of the<br />

with which all powers and faculties are<br />

distributed to every particular being"; and the "inaccurate workmanship of all<br />

the springs and principles of the great machine of<br />

nature"<br />

(pp. 73-77). From<br />

his consideration of the causes of evil, Philo concludes that "the original Source<br />

of all things is entirely indifferent to all these principles,<br />

and has no more<br />

regard to good above ill than to heat above cold, or to drought above moisture,<br />

or to light above heavy"<br />

(p. 79). Recognizing the force of Philo's argument,<br />

Cleanthes comments to Demea that "it must be confessed that the injudicious<br />

reasoning of our vulgar theology<br />

(p. 80).<br />

cule"<br />

has given him but too just a handle of ridi<br />

The first cause of all things, whatever it might be deemed to be, has no<br />

particular concern for man. The Deity is a disinterested observer of the universe<br />

and the beings, including man, that compose it. This disinterestedness, how<br />

ever, can be interpreted as at least a kind of negative benevolence towards man.<br />

It is possible to argue, as Philo hints, that the causes of evil in the universe are<br />

"necessary and<br />

unavoidable,"<br />

at least for the sake of man's development (see p.<br />

73). At one point in his argument, he claims that to "cure most of the ills of<br />

human life"<br />

it would be necessary to increase only one "power of faculty"<br />

man's soul, his "propensity to industry and<br />

labor"<br />

of<br />

or his "bent to business and<br />

application."<br />

For human beings to be induced to labor, they must feel both the<br />

lash of fear and the lure of hope: the fear of what they will suffer if they do not<br />

stir themselves to action; the hope that by their actions they will actually be<br />

able to improve their situation. The disinterestedness of the first cause provides<br />

the grounds for both hope and fear. It induces human beings to labor by not<br />

revealing<br />

whether it is benevolent or hostile towards them. It distributes to<br />

them both pleasures and pains (p. 73). Because the first cause is indifferent<br />

towards human beings, it does not interfere in the course of nature to care for<br />

their needs. It thus makes it possible for them to employ their powers of reason<br />

"in the conduct of life"<br />

(p. 74). More like a "rigid than an "indulgent


270 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

son and<br />

towards human beings, it bestows on them no advantages except "rea<br />

sagacity."<br />

It thus forces them to use their reason to gain everything<br />

they need or want (pp. 75-76). Finally, by allowing a certain "disorder or<br />

confusion"<br />

in the operations of nature, it leaves to man the opportunity, by the<br />

employment of his reason and the application of his industry, to manipulate the<br />

course of nature (p. 77). The disinterestedness of the first cause moves human<br />

beings to labor. They would have no reason to undertake the struggles to mas<br />

ter, create, cultivate, and build the arduous efforts by which civilization is<br />

constructed if it were either particularly careful or actively hostile to them. It<br />

forces them to act but leaves them free to determine for themselves how to act.<br />

Giving them nothing but their wits, the first cause of all things literally compels<br />

them to make something of themselves.<br />

The theology or metaphysics developed in Hume's Dialogues Concerning<br />

Natural Religion supports both elements of the liberal project, nonpartisan gov<br />

ernment and the scientific conquest of nature. What Cleanthes calls the "Author<br />

of<br />

nature"<br />

not only does not oppose the endeavor by<br />

human beings to master<br />

and control nature, it invites them and even compels them to undertake it. The<br />

first cause of all things constrains man to become his own first cause. God in<br />

effect demands of man that he make himself into a god. Human beings can<br />

make the most of themselves if they cooperate with the first cause and choose<br />

to organize themselves in society in such a way as to expose themselves to the<br />

lash of fear and the lure of hope. This occurs only under the liberal political<br />

system of nonpartisan government, in which no individual or group has a spe<br />

cial place in the order of society. Nonpartisan government, in turn, requires the<br />

separation of religion from politics. The secularization of politics is not just<br />

possible but absolutely necessary according to the theology elaborated by<br />

Cleanthes and Philo. The Deity<br />

revealed in the discussion does not-indeed<br />

cannot-rule directly over human beings. He gives no commandments to them.<br />

He has no will that must be enforced on them, either by Himself directly or by<br />

His earthly representatives. He cannot be used, then, by any<br />

one to claim a<br />

right to rule over the rest of society. The political implications of this theology<br />

are reflected in Cleanthes'<br />

comment that "the proper office of religion is to<br />

regulate the heart of men, humanize their conduct, infuse the spirit of toler<br />

ance, order, and<br />

obedience."<br />

When it "acts as a separate principle over<br />

however, "it has departed from its proper sphere and has become only a cover<br />

to faction and<br />

ambition"<br />

(p. 88). The theology of the Dialogues purges religion<br />

of its political pretensions. This contributes to the elimination of the evils of the<br />

rule of man over man adumbrated by Philo (see p. 63). As illustrated in Philo's<br />

rhetorical reconciliation of "the<br />

theist"<br />

and "the<br />

atheist,"<br />

it makes possible the<br />

achievement of peace in society (see pp. 85-86). Hume's Dialogues Concern<br />

ing Natural Religion articulates the theological or metaphysical presuppositions<br />

of the Dionysian project for the scientific conquest of nature at the same time<br />

that it lays the political foundations necessary for the project's accomplishment.


CONCLUSION<br />

David Hume's Theology of Liberation 211<br />

Liberal political philosophy, which seeks in practice to separate religion and<br />

politics, culminates in theory in a kind of religious teaching of its own. This<br />

religious teaching implies a more or less specific conception of the complete<br />

good life for man. It is, of course, possible to question how "complete"<br />

conception of the good life really is. Unfortunately, liberalism cannot give a<br />

good answer to this question. As is clear from Hume's elaboration of the theol<br />

ogy of liberalism in his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, liberal politi<br />

cal philosophy abolishes all standards both natural and divine by which it might<br />

be answered. What this might lead to is reflected in Philo's last speech in the<br />

Dialogues:<br />

But believe me, Cleanthes, the most natural sentiment which a well-disposed mind<br />

will feel on this occasion is a longing<br />

this<br />

desire and expectation that Heaven would be<br />

pleased to dissipate, at least alleviate, this profound ignorance by affording some<br />

particular revelation to mankind, and making discoveries of the nature, attributes,<br />

and operations of the Divine object of our faith. A person, seasoned with a just<br />

sense of the imperfections of natural reason, will fly to revealed truth with the<br />

greatest avidity, while the haughty dogmatist, persuaded that he can erect a<br />

complete system of theology by the mere help of philosophy, disdains any further<br />

aid and rejects this adventitious instructor, (p. 94)<br />

Man might imitate the God of the Bible and organize the world by the word of<br />

his mouth; he cannot, however, like the Biblical God give the organized world<br />

meaning and value by simply calling<br />

it good. From Hume's other writings on<br />

religion, in particular the Natural History of Religion, it is clear that he would<br />

by<br />

no means welcome the flight to revealed religion. It is possible to under<br />

stand the development of political philosophy after liberalism, and with it the<br />

course of political development in the modern world, as the result of this yearn<br />

ing<br />

for a new revelation from the ground of all Being.<br />

NOTES<br />

1. G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the <strong>Philosophy</strong> of Religion, edited with an introduction by<br />

of California Press, 1984), p. 83.<br />

Peter C. Hodgson (Berkeley: University<br />

2. See, inter alia, Hobbes, Leviathan Parts III and IV; Locke, First Treatise of Government and<br />

Reasonableness of Christianity; Spinoza, Theological and Political Treatise.<br />

3. David Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, edited with an introduction by Henry<br />

D. Aiken (New York: Hafner Publishing Co., 1966).<br />

4. See Aristotle, Politics, translated with an introduction by Carnes Lord (Chicago: University<br />

of Chicago Press, 1984), Bk. I, esp. 1252al-23.<br />

5. See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, or the Matter, Forme, and Power of a Common-Wealth<br />

Ecclesiastical! and Civill, edited with an introduction by<br />

Books, 1968), Chs. 1-8.<br />

C B. MacPherson (Baltimore: Pelican


272 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

6. The structure of the Dialogues perhaps indicates something about the dimensions of its<br />

subject matter, relating it to three of the greatest of Plato's dialogues, the Symposium, Theaetetus,<br />

and Parmenides. Appropriately, the Symposium is the only Platonic dialogue on a god, the god<br />

Eros. The Theaetetus and Parmenides deal with what are now called epistemology and ontology.<br />

Commentators tend to associate the Dialogues with Cicero's De Natura Deorum. The resemblance<br />

is not so strong, however, as to the Platonic dialogues. In De Natura Deorum, Cicero in his own<br />

name recounts a conversation that he heard. In the Symposium, Theaetetus, and Parmenides, like<br />

Hume's Dialogues, the conversation is recalled by one of the author's characters. There are a<br />

number of references to Plato in the Dialogues. There is also a clear reference to Parmenides.<br />

7. "Demea"<br />

means something like "common."<br />

There is a joke about a "Demea"<br />

in Plato's<br />

Gorgias. There is much that could be done with the names of the other characters in the Dialogues.<br />

The most interesting question about names in the Dialogues in why Hume gave his arch-sceptic the<br />

name of a Jewish Platonist.<br />

8. Pamphilus'<br />

judgment in the introduction on the characters of the interlocutors should be<br />

carefully noted. Most commentators take Philo as Hume's spokesman in the Dialogues; a very few<br />

take Cleanthes.<br />

9. See P. S. Wadia, "Philo Confounded,"<br />

in McGill Hume Studies, edited by David Fate<br />

Norton, et al. (San Diego: Austin Hill Press, 1979), pp. 283-87, for a rather different interpreta<br />

tion of Philo's show of embarrassment. Wadia is one of the few commentators on the Dialogues<br />

who takes at all seriously the drama of the work.


Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs:<br />

John Quincy<br />

Greg Russell<br />

Adams and the Moral Sentiments of a Realist<br />

Northeast Louisiana University<br />

Commemorating the Jeffersonian heritage in American diplomacy, one inex<br />

tricably tied to the lawful purposes of civil government, is certainly appropriate<br />

at a time when leading officials salute democratic revolutions throughout Eu<br />

rope, South Africa, and Latin America. Recent political and ideological up<br />

heavals throughout the Soviet empire and Eastern bloc nations challenge anew<br />

the national purpose as much as the national security of the United States. The<br />

need to redefine the national interest "beyond<br />

duty<br />

containme<br />

carries with it the<br />

to reconsider the historical basis of American moral and political leader<br />

ship in a troubled world. Since the earliest days of the republic, the struggle for<br />

human rights has inspired partisans to invoke the "verdict of history"<br />

and pro<br />

claim the "inextinguishable human<br />

spirit"<br />

as inseparable from the moral fiber of<br />

the American union. "From the time of the Declaration of our Independence,"<br />

according to Henry Kissinger, "Americans have believed that this country has a<br />

moral significance for the<br />

conscious act by<br />

world"<br />

(p. 59). The United States was created in a<br />

a people dedicated to a set of political and ethical principles<br />

they held to be of universal meaning.<br />

A new generation of American statesmen, looking beyond Cold War rivalry,<br />

are called upon to affirm certain truths to be virtually self-evident: that the<br />

United States is a great power with a unique national identity; that what we do<br />

will affect not only our own survival but the fate of Western civilization as<br />

well; that men fighting for freedom are moved by great ideals; and that, for<br />

these reasons, it is urgent that we see ourselves and that others see us as acting<br />

in accord with ideals which are sharable and worthy of respect. Today, Jeffer<br />

son's common human faith in the rights of man will certainly find acceptance<br />

in a wider immediate circle than he ever dreamed of.<br />

Convinced that the republican is the only form of government which is not<br />

eternally at open or secret war with the rights of mankind, my prayers and efforts<br />

shall be cordially distributed to the support of that we have so happily established.<br />

It is an animating thought, that while we arc securing the rights of ourselves<br />

and our posterity, we are pointing out the way to struggling nations, who wish like<br />

us to emerge from their tyrannies also. Heaven help their struggles, and lead them,<br />

as it has done us, triumphantly through them. (Quoted in Koch, p. 151).<br />

interpretation. Winter 1990-1991. Vol. 18, No. 2


274 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

ing<br />

The two great religious-moral traditions that infused early American think<br />

New England Calvinism and Virginian Jeffersonianism arrive at similar<br />

conclusions about the meaning of American national character and destiny. In<br />

Wonder Working Providence of Zion'<br />

s Saviour (1650), Edward Johnson spoke<br />

of New England as the place "where the Lord would create a new heaven and a<br />

new earth,<br />

new churches and a new commonwealth<br />

altogeth<br />

A century later<br />

Ezra Stiles of Yale preached a sermon on "The United States elevated to glory<br />

and<br />

honor"<br />

in which he defined the nation as "God's American Israel."<br />

Jeffer<br />

son and John Adams called the amalgam "the dictates of reason and pure<br />

Americanism"<br />

(To Edward Rutledge, June 24, 1797, Jefferson [1903], IX,<br />

409. For "Americanism"<br />

in John Adams see his letter to Benjamin Rush, July 7,<br />

1805, in Schutz and Adair, p. 30.) The self-interpretive symbols of American<br />

nationhood look in two directions: "towards the truth of man's existence per<br />

sonally, socially, and historically, on the one hand; and toward the persuasive<br />

and evocative articulation of that truth in the foundation myth of the new com<br />

munity, on the other<br />

hand."<br />

The vision at the center of American politics, then,<br />

is structured by insights into human reality "taken to be universally valid for all<br />

mankind, even as they are adapted to the concrete conditions of time and place<br />

at the moment of the articulation of the new nation as an entity politically<br />

organized for action in history"<br />

(Sandoz, pp. 35, 35-36, 38, 83-84, 105, 1 14-<br />

15, and 123. For the theories of articulation and representation here, see<br />

Voegelin, Chs. 1-3.)<br />

Jefferson's conception of the innocence and virtue of the new nation was not<br />

informed by<br />

the Biblical symbolism of the New England tracts. His religious<br />

faith was a form of Christianity which had passed through the rationalism of the<br />

French Enlightenment. His moral transcendence was expressed in the belief of<br />

the power of "nature's God"<br />

over the vicissitudes of history. Jefferson was<br />

moved to acknowledge that nature's God had a very special purpose in found<br />

ing this new community. America had a political mission to fulfill, for itself<br />

and before the eyes of the world: to prove that reason, order, and law are the<br />

genuine fruits of an educated people governing themselves.<br />

the eyes of the virtuous all over the earth are turned with anxiety on us, as the<br />

only depositories of the sacred fire of liberty, and that our falling into anarchy<br />

would decide forever the destinies of mankind, and seal the political heresy that<br />

man is incapable of self-government. (To John Hollis, Esq., May 5, 1811,<br />

Jefferson 11903], XIII, 58)<br />

Every<br />

nation has its own form of spiritual pride. These examples of Ameri<br />

can self-appreciation could be matched by corresponding<br />

sentiments in other<br />

nations. To know that nations are subject to the moral law is one thing, while<br />

to pretend to know with certainty what is good and evil in the relations among<br />

nations is quite another (Morgenthau [1973],<br />

p. 11). "Power,"<br />

John Adams


Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs 275<br />

wrote, "always thinks it has a great soul and vast views beyond the comprehen<br />

sion of the weak: and that it is doing God's service when it is violating all His<br />

laws"<br />

(quoted in ibid., pp. 90-91). The tragic conception of politics and diplo<br />

macy, however, need not recommend cynicism or complacency with respect to<br />

fundamental moral choices. Indeed, it will make a difference whether the par<br />

ticular culture in which the policies of nations the actions of statesmen are<br />

formed is only as deep and as high as the nation's highest ideals, or whether<br />

there is a dimension in the culture from which the element of vanity in all<br />

human achievements is discerned. Jefferson's memorable assertion in his First<br />

Inaugural "we are all republicans, we are all federalists"<br />

was perhaps less<br />

important as a conciliatory overture than as a subtle intimation of the moral<br />

resources in American politics and statecraft.<br />

That the national unity of all Americans carried a distinctive message for<br />

between power and morals in<br />

mankind can be seen by noting the relationship<br />

Jefferson's philosophy. Of particular importance is how the natural and inalien<br />

able rights of man are derived from, or connected with,<br />

natural law. For exam<br />

ple, Jefferson affirmed the rights of man on a preponderantly moral basis of<br />

preference and appropriateness to human<br />

interpersonal context of other selves, may<br />

nature.1<br />

Self-realization, always in the<br />

be the natural moral goal. The impli<br />

cations of Jefferson's concept of rights for the conduct of men and nations were<br />

detailed by one historian in the following terms:<br />

Natural law is the system of governing norms, rules, and duties that bind<br />

man the correlative, in short, of the natural rights which he claims. Natural law<br />

in its widest legal sense (what Jefferson referred to as "the law of nature and<br />

nations") includes this meaning plus the usages and customs of nations dealing with<br />

other nations in the interest of peace and under the controlling ideal of more<br />

humane and civilized practice. (Koch, pp. 44-45)<br />

The enduring moral principles (e.g., the worth of every human being, equal<br />

ity of consideration to which all are entitled in society, justice, and fraternity)<br />

are in no way limited to a given time or society but invoke the vision of a<br />

brotherhood of man. The important point is that one hereby<br />

asserts a moral<br />

limit on power politics; one condemns force and violence as an extensive,<br />

wholesale instrument of national or international policy. Jefferson urged justice<br />

upon nations if they would have the firm friendship<br />

Britain, unable to win allies in the great battle with Napoleonic France, Jeffer<br />

of other countries. Of Great<br />

son wrote that she was a living example "that no nation however powerful, any<br />

more than any individual,<br />

can be unjust with impunity. Sooner or later public<br />

opinion, an instrument merely moral in the beginning, will find occasion physi<br />

cally<br />

to inflict its sentence upon the<br />

"useful to the weak as well as the<br />

Jefferson [1892-99], VIII, 300).<br />

unjust."<br />

The lesson, he believed, was<br />

strong"<br />

(To James Madison, April 23, 1804,


276 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

The law of nature and nations, then, becomes another illustration of Jeffer<br />

son's theory<br />

of natural rights. Each nation "forms a moral<br />

member of a nation is "personally<br />

responsible for his<br />

person"<br />

and each<br />

society."<br />

The continental<br />

tradition of raison d'etat, the historical debate about ethical "dualism"<br />

from<br />

Machiavelli to Bismarck, is hardly compatible with a theory of rights so ex<br />

state"<br />

pressed. Briefly summarized, the heritage of "reason of holds that the<br />

state is subject to no rule of conduct but the one which is dictated by its own<br />

self-interest. Salus publica suprema lex. When the statesman is confronted with<br />

a choice between two actions, the one ethical, the other not, of which the latter<br />

has a better chance of bringing about the desired result, he must choose the<br />

latter. When he acts in a private capacity, however, he, like any other private<br />

individual, must choose the former; "for,<br />

while political action is free from<br />

ethical limitations, private action is subject to them. The individual as such is<br />

moral by nature; political society is amoral, also by<br />

[1946], p. 176).<br />

nature"<br />

(Morgenthau<br />

Jefferson rejected any dual ethical standard and argued that the limits upon<br />

the moral conduct of the nation are the same as those upon relations between<br />

man and man.<br />

The moral duties which exist between individual and individual in a state of nature,<br />

them into a state of society, and the aggregate of the duties of all the<br />

accompany<br />

individuals composing the society constitutes the duties of that society towards any<br />

other; so that between society and society the same moral duties exist as did<br />

between individuals composing them, while in an unassociated state, and their<br />

maker not having released them from those duties on their forming<br />

themselves into<br />

a nation. ("Opinion on the Question Whether the United States Has a Right to<br />

Intervene to Renounce Their Treaties with<br />

France"<br />

[1903], III, 227)<br />

Jefferson's counsel merely points to the fact that it is always the individual who<br />

acts, either with reference to his ends alone or with reference to the ends of<br />

others. "I know but one code of morality for men, whether acting singly or<br />

collectively."<br />

If the morality of a solitary individual "produces a just line of<br />

conduct in him why should not the morality of 100 men produce a just line<br />

of conduct in them acting<br />

together?"<br />

(To James Madison, August 28, 1789<br />

[1903], VII, 448-49). The action of a society or nation has no empirical exis<br />

tence at all. What empirically exists are always the actions of individuals who<br />

perform identical or different actions with reference to a common end.<br />

The only exception to the laws of nature and nations is the transcendent right<br />

to resist self-destruction. As there are circumstances which sometimes excuse<br />

the nonperformance of contracts between man and man, so nations may annul<br />

their obligations "if performance becomes self-destructive to the<br />

"the law of self-preservation overrules the laws of obligations in<br />

("Opinion<br />

"<br />

party."<br />

Only<br />

[1903], III, 228). In addition, Jefferson was enough of a realist<br />

to see clearly that no nation can fully transcend its own interests. "All know the<br />

others


Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs 277<br />

influence of interest on the mind of man, and how unconsciously his judgment<br />

is warped by<br />

influence" ("Autobiography,"<br />

that [ 1903] , I, 120). In 1812, when<br />

Napoleon was at the pinnacle of his power, Jefferson was unprepared to con<br />

template moral principles apart from the political exigencies of American na<br />

tional security. His was the hope that "the powers of Europe may be so poised<br />

and counterpoised among themselves, that their own security may require the<br />

presence of all their forces at home, leaving the other quarters of the world in<br />

tranquility"<br />

undisturbed<br />

(quoted in Morgenthau [1951], pp. 20-21).<br />

This was also a realism that made room for political ideals and declarations<br />

of rights. The Thomas Jefferson who wrote in 1809 that "1 am persuaded no<br />

constitution was ever before so well calculated as ours for extensive empire and<br />

self-governm<br />

could also write in 1817 that America's role in the world was<br />

to "consecrate a sanctuary for those whom the misrule of Europe may compel<br />

to seek happiness in other<br />

but moral in nature: "This refuge once known,"<br />

climes."<br />

America's influence was not to be military<br />

happiness even of those who remain there, by warning<br />

he declared, "will produce<br />

their taskmasters that<br />

another Canaan is open where there subjects will be received as brothers"<br />

(quoted in Bellah, p. 89. See also Germino.) The moves and countermoves in<br />

the struggle for political power must be intelligible as a dialectic movement<br />

toward the realization of justice. Consider in this connection Jefferson's admo<br />

nition that "<br />

. it<br />

is true, that nations are to be judges for themselves; since no<br />

nation has the right to sit in judgment over another, but the tribunal of our<br />

consciences remains, and that also of the opinion of the<br />

world"<br />

("Opinion<br />

[1903], III, 228).<br />

Modern perspectives of realism and idealism in American diplomacy often<br />

sharpen the power-morality dichotomy in such a fashion as to ignore the man<br />

ner in which a statesman's political responsibility is inseparable from his role as<br />

a moral witness to the actions of his nation. Implicit in the Jeffersonian world<br />

view is the prescription that America's dual importance, as a native achieve<br />

ment and worldwide example, must embody an element of restraint and pay<br />

proper respect to the varieties of possible political experience elsewhere. For<br />

the diplomatist, the Jeffersonian legacy is not a doctrine or mere ideological<br />

credo; rather, his contribution (although not alone here among the Founding<br />

Fathers) underscores the centrality of political ethics for relating the national<br />

interest to structures of community and justice beyond the parochial nation<br />

state. The issue is one that points to the need for a meeting ground upon which<br />

the philosopher and statesman can momentarily converge.<br />

JOHN QUINCY ADAMS AND AN ETHICS OF CIRCUMSPECTION<br />

Arthur Schlesinger, Jr., refers to John Quincy Adams, and several of his<br />

contemporaries, as honest Jeffersonians (p. 313). Admittedly, the categoriza<br />

tion is arguable in light of several profound differences in political and philo-<br />

"


278 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

sophical orientation; however, Schlesinger's paradox is not entirely lost with<br />

reference to a common intellectual inclination on the part of both leaders to<br />

affirm, however precariously, the moral basis of American power and expan<br />

sion. Moreover, they arrived at this conclusion by divergent paths, even while<br />

disagreeing<br />

on the origins and merits of republican and democratic politics.<br />

"We are . as Mr. Jefferson forty years ago said,<br />

cans, but not all Democrats,<br />

all federalists all republi<br />

no more that we are all Aristocrats or Monar<br />

chists"<br />

(Adams [1842], p. 30). Yet Adams, the only federalist in the United<br />

States Senate to support Jefferson's purchase of the Louisiana territory, ac<br />

knowledged in this transaction<br />

Fortune claims to herself the lion's share. To seize and to turn to profit the<br />

precise instant of the turning tide, is itself among the eminent properties of a<br />

Statesman, and if requiring less elevated virtue than the firmness and prudence that<br />

withstand adversity, or the moderation which adorns and dignifies prosperity, it is<br />

not less essential to the character of an accomplished ruler of men. (Adams [1850],<br />

pp. 83-84)<br />

Adams, with Jefferson, knew too well that "the selfish and the social passions<br />

are intermingled in the conduct of every man acting in a public<br />

(Memoirs, August 20, 1809, II, 13). Moreover, the good which an individual<br />

can do for his fellow citizens "is seldom proportioned to his dispositions and<br />

the inclination to do good itself, unless enlightened by a clear perception,<br />

guided by a discriminating judgment, and animated by<br />

capacity"<br />

active resolution,<br />

evaporates in the dreams of imagination (Memoirs, March 4, 1820, V,<br />

13).<br />

The intellectual universe of John Quincy Adams,<br />

a compound of Christian<br />

faith in the gospel of modern liberal reason, discloses the unique resources that<br />

would help mold the diplomatic achievements of America's greatest Secretary<br />

of State in the nineteenth century. What has been described as the Golden Age<br />

of American diplomacy, the 1814-1828 era, forms the backdrop for Adams's<br />

diplomacy during the Madison and Monroe administrations. During these<br />

years, the United States signed the treaty of peace ending the War of 1812,<br />

issued the Monroe Doctrine,<br />

and strengthened its maritime power through an<br />

agreement with Britain to clear the Great Lakes of warships and by obtaining<br />

rights to fish off the coast of Labrador and Newfoundland. Americans extended<br />

their continental reach through the annexation of Florida, by removing Russian<br />

influence from the southwestern coast of North America, through the establish<br />

ment of the American-Canadian boundary from the Great Lakes to the Rockies,<br />

and by staking their first claims to the Pacific coast (La Feber, p. 13).<br />

Adams was a central figure in all these transactions and, in each instance,<br />

saw a larger moral message for the exercise of power in defense of the national<br />

interest. Inasmuch as the voluminous record of Adams the diplomatist has been<br />

treated at length elsewhere (see Bemis, Graebner, and Lang and Russell), this


Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs 279<br />

essay looks more towards Adams the ethicist and his unfailing regard for the<br />

morality of state behavior. His inability to countenance an "irremediable<br />

between the principles of ethics and diplomacy provides a useful point of de<br />

parture to rethink the moral prerogatives of the American statesman. Adams's<br />

quality as a human being has a direct and obvious relation to his political and<br />

social thinking. He viewed the moral and intellectual qualities of others from<br />

unassailable heights whereon he felt himself for the most part secure, despite<br />

occasional lapses of penetrating self-analysis. He was, however,<br />

moralist; he also felt the promptings of desire for success and place:<br />

I want the seals of power and place,<br />

The ensigns of command,<br />

Charged by<br />

To rule my native land.<br />

the people's unbought grace<br />

Nor crown, nor sceptre would I ask<br />

But from my country's will,<br />

By day, by night, to ply the task<br />

Her cup of bliss to fill. (Adams [1848], p. 22)<br />

no ascetic<br />

Adams first entered the political arena with the publication of his "Letters of<br />

Publicola,"<br />

demolishing Thomas Paine's Rights of Man. These papers, which<br />

grew out of the controversy between Paine and Edmund Burke concerning the<br />

French Revolution, exemplify<br />

Adams's reliance on natural law to illumine the<br />

foundations of liberty and to defend minority rights in republican government.<br />

Like the writings of his father, his seek to oppose the extreme views of Paine<br />

and of the French Revolution and yet to retain faith in the American theory of<br />

natural rights. Adams many times expresses his allegiance to the principle of<br />

natural rights, including<br />

the "unalienable right of resistance to<br />

tyranny."<br />

not the basic premise of Paine's book to which he is opposed, but the conclu<br />

sions which Paine infers from them. This "commentary upon the rights of<br />

man,"<br />

he says, draws "questionable deductions from unquestionable princi<br />

It is<br />

Paine, as the controversy develops, acknowledged "that which a whole<br />

nation chooses to do, it has a right to do."<br />

Adams responded with the belief<br />

that "it is of infinite consequence that the distinction between power and right<br />

should be fully acknowledged,<br />

principles of legislators."<br />

and should be admitted as one the fundamental<br />

This principle, that a whole nation has a right to do whatever it pleases, cannot in<br />

any sense be admitted as true. The eternal and immutable laws of justice and of<br />

morality are paramount to all human legislation. The violation of those laws is<br />

certainly within the power, but it is not among the rights of nations. The power of<br />

a nation is the collected power of all the individuals which compose it. If,<br />

therefore, a majority<br />

are bound by no law human or divine, and have no other<br />

mle but their sovereign will and pleasure to direct them, what possible security can


280 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

any<br />

citizen have for the protection of unalienable rights? The principles of<br />

liberty must still be the sport of arbitrary power, and the hideous form of despotism<br />

must lay aside the diadem and the scepter, only to assume the party-colored<br />

garments of democracy. (II "Publicola,"<br />

also Wright, pp. 168-71.)<br />

11 June 1791, Writings, I, 69-71. See<br />

The half-century of public life as diplomatic emissary, Secretary of State,<br />

President, and Congressman led him to defend the rights of property and<br />

tradition while opposing slavery and the southern interest. Between the two<br />

commitments, Adams saw no essential contradiction. "The True Theory of<br />

Government,"<br />

he wrote to George Bancroft in 1835, "is that which provides<br />

alike for the protection and security both of persons and<br />

property<br />

("Letters,"<br />

pp. 246-47). He died painfully conscious of his failure to accomplish any of<br />

those high hopes for American national character upon which he had expended<br />

his life. Judging Adams'<br />

credentials as a conservative thinker, one author<br />

writes: "It is hard to reproach this inspiring man with the collapse of his<br />

ideals; but the fact remains that he expected more from men than any true<br />

conservative should expect, and he got from them less than many a leader<br />

immeasurably Adams'<br />

moral inferior can<br />

obtain"<br />

(Kirk, pp. 257-58). Adams<br />

was forever tormented by the thought of what he should have been, destroyed<br />

by a nation and a superintending Providence unable or unwilling<br />

vision of national grandeur.<br />

to heed his<br />

If my intellectual powers had been such as have been sometimes committed by the<br />

Creator of men to single individuals of the species, my diary would have been,<br />

next to the Holy Scriptures, the most . . valuable book ever written by human<br />

hands, and I should have been one of the greatest benefactors of my country and of<br />

mankind. I would, by Almighty<br />

the irresistible power of . .<br />

God, have banished<br />

war and slavery from the face of the earth forever. But the conceptive power of<br />

mind was not conferred upon me by my Maker, and I have not improved the<br />

scanty portion of His gifts as I might and ought to have done. (Quoted in H.<br />

Adams, pp. 34-35)<br />

He sensed that his duty was the conservation of America's moral worth; he<br />

knew his age for a time of transition; but how to contend with this grim sphinx,<br />

he never properly discovered.<br />

That Adams as thinker has been largely ignored by most standard works on<br />

America's intellectual traditions may be explained, to some degree, by the<br />

manner in which his world view cut across conventional theoretical guideposts.<br />

Henry Adams considered that his grandfather had been a political man, actu<br />

ated by ordinary feelings; whereas Brooks Adams judged him an "idealistic<br />

philosopher who sought with absolute disinterestedness to put the Union upon a<br />

plane of civilization which would have averted the recent War; who failed,<br />

as all men must fail who harbor such a purpose,<br />

and who . resigned himself


and his ambitions to fate"<br />

Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs 28 1<br />

(quoted in H. Adams, p. vii. See also Nevins, p.<br />

ix.). Adams's social and political philosophy derived in great measure from his<br />

own reading and converse with eighteenth-century thinkers, in particular John<br />

Locke, but it constituted as well a special synthesis of old ideas. He was also<br />

obligated to the "long tradition of medieval political thought, back to St.<br />

Thomas, in which the reality of moral restraints on power, the responsibility of<br />

rulers to the communities which they ruled, and the subordination of govern<br />

ment to law were<br />

axiomatic."<br />

His combination of the Lockean position with an<br />

important emphasis upon the vigorous role to be played by<br />

government in a<br />

program of internal improvements; his combination of a strong nationalism<br />

based upon a sense of moral rectitude with an insistence upon self-restraint,<br />

equality, and a recognition of moral laws in the relations of nations; his combi<br />

nation of a religious faith in the natural-law concept with an empirical and<br />

skeptical view in the realm of science made Adams unique among public fig<br />

ures of his day in the United States (Lipsky, p. 328; Sabiiie, p. 523).<br />

Adams has been aptly described as "the classic example of the political<br />

moralist in thought and word, who cannot help being a political realist in ac<br />

tion."<br />

His international thought was anchored in the realist tradition of Wash<br />

ington and Hamilton; yet he did the better part of his work in statecraft in an<br />

atmosphere saturated with Jeffersonian principles. Between Adams's moral<br />

principles and his conception of the national interest of the United States there<br />

was hardly ever a conflict. The moral principles, as Hans J. Morgenthau sug<br />

gested, were nothing but political interests formulated in moral terms, and vice<br />

versa ([1951]), pp. 19, 22). Adams'<br />

seminal contributions to the American<br />

diplomatic tradition freedom of the seas, the Monroe Doctrine, and Manifest<br />

Destiny are evidence of this achievement. For example, the legal principle of<br />

freedom of the seas was a weapon through which an inferior naval power tried<br />

to safeguard its independence from Great Britain. Similarly, the Monroe Doc<br />

trine's moral postulates of nonintervention (and anti-imperialism) were negative<br />

conditions for the security and prestige of the United States. Their fulfillment<br />

insulated the United States from the power struggles in Europe and, through it,<br />

ensured the predominance of the United States in the Western Hemisphere.<br />

Manifest Destiny<br />

was the moral and ideological incentive for American conti<br />

nental expansion and subjugation of native inhabitants (ibid., pp. 22-23).<br />

Morgenthau's analysis, however,<br />

speaks more to effect and less to cause.<br />

The clear implication of his commentary is that realism and idealism need not<br />

always be treated as mutually exclusive categories or criteria from which to<br />

judge the words and deeds of the statesman. Equally<br />

important in this connec<br />

tion is whether moral desiderata above the nation state function only as an<br />

ideological apology for the powerful (the homage that vice pays to virtue) or as<br />

an exercise in costly self-deception for the weak. Is the statesman ill-advised to<br />

derive norms of national conduct from some other source than mundane politi<br />

cal reality? It must be noted that these questions are rarely, if at all, felt and


282 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

confronted by the statesman in a way that can be easily<br />

transformed into the<br />

systematic analysis of hypothetical possibilities. While Adams may have<br />

avoided systematic expression, he evolved a conception of life, God, and the<br />

universe into which his attitude on all the problems of his political time may be<br />

fitted. Even if Adams could not disengage himself entirely from the singular<br />

heat of political passions, his legacy substantiates the normative and philosoph<br />

ical core of all serious political thinking. Of no small significance here is how<br />

his reflection on man's nature and the moral tasks of governance relates to the<br />

duties of American national interest in world affairs.<br />

He found the world about him confined and controlled by a paramount law<br />

of nature, superior to the regulations of humans, a law which the logical mind<br />

could discern and apply to the political fortunes of nations. For example, he<br />

rejected the demand pressed on the Washington Administration that the United<br />

States support France against the combined powers of Europe in 1793. America<br />

was commanded by the "law of nature, which is paramount to all human legis<br />

lation, or compact, to remain at peace, and to content ourselves with wishing<br />

that laureled victory may sit upon the sword of justice, and that smooth success<br />

may<br />

August 24, 1793, Writings, I, 145-46). In this philosophical scheme the<br />

always be strewed before the feet of virtuous Freedom"<br />

(III "Marcellus,"<br />

United States occupied a unique position, for it was the first nation in history to<br />

announce foundation principles embedded in the "law of<br />

nature"<br />

(see Adams,<br />

[1831]). The Declaration of Independence announced "the one People, assum<br />

ing their station among the Powers of the Earth, as a religious, civilized and<br />

Christian People acknowledging themselves bound by the obligations, and<br />

claiming the rights to which they were entitled by the Laws of Nature and<br />

Nature's God."<br />

The laws of nature, according to Adams, applied to the social<br />

intercourse between sovereign communities and found expression in the Euro<br />

pean law of nations. These laws are "all derived from three sources: the .<br />

dictates of justice; usages, sanctioned by custom; and treaties, or national cove<br />

nants."<br />

In addition, Adams acknowledged that the "Christian nations, between<br />

themselves, admit, with various latitudes of interpretation, and little consis<br />

tency of practice, the laws of humanity and mutual benevolence taught in the<br />

gospel of Christ"<br />

(II "Marcellus,"<br />

. .<br />

Writings, I, 129). Americans "laid the foun<br />

dation of their government upon the eternal and unalterable principles of human<br />

rights."<br />

That government's essential purpose the very reason for which it is<br />

instituted is to secure the "natural rights of<br />

mankind"<br />

ensured that the struc<br />

tures of power would be "subordinate to the moral supremacy of the People"<br />

([1837], pp. 20-22).<br />

Nor is Adams's devotion to the precepts of natural law invalidated by point<br />

ing out that, on occasion, he could specifically sanction departure from princi<br />

ple, although the departure was explained in terms of moral and legal obliga<br />

tion. Concerning the acquisition of Louisiana, Adams believed that, although<br />

the consent of the inhabitants should have been gained, it would have been


Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs - 283<br />

impracticable to try to obtain it prior to the treaty and that "theoretic principles<br />

of<br />

government"<br />

had to be modified to meet the "situations of human events and<br />

human<br />

concerns"<br />

("Notes on Speech on Motion,"<br />

Writings, III, 28-29). The<br />

treaty-making power had been used constitutionally in acquiring the territory; a<br />

plebiscite might have denied the results of the treaty. Yet the United States<br />

could not be relieved of the obligation to procure the consent of the inhabitants<br />

after the treaty.<br />

And as nothing but necessity can justify even a momentary departure from those<br />

principles which we hold as the most sacred laws of nature and of nations, so<br />

nothing can justify extending the departure beyond the bounds of necessity. From<br />

the instant when that [necessity] ceases the principle returns in all its force, and<br />

every further violation of it is error and crime, (ibid.)<br />

The law of nature, then, determines the extent of deviation that necessity may<br />

occasion from its precepts. Adams once wrote in his Memoirs that principles<br />

should be adhered to strongly only to the degree of their importance and of the<br />

importance of results deriving from their application (December 22, 1833, IX,<br />

58). Neither intentions nor results are, by themselves, a moral guarantor of the<br />

national interest. Adams would not accept our dichotomy of realism and ideal<br />

ism; he would, as Nathan Tarcov explains, emphasize the complementary rela<br />

tion of principle and prudence. "Principles are not self-applying: They<br />

tell you what to do. They<br />

Prudence is not self-sufficient either; it requires principles for<br />

cov,<br />

p. 48).<br />

do not<br />

require prudence and judgment for their application.<br />

guidan<br />

(Tar<br />

The competing claims of power and principle to which Adams alluded were<br />

nowhere better exemplified than in his own defense of General Jackson's 1818<br />

invasion of Spanish territory in Florida and the storming of Pensacola. On the<br />

one hand, Adams stood alone in the Cabinet in holding that the action had been<br />

"defensive,"<br />

neither an act of war nor in violation of the Constitution (Mem<br />

oirs, July 17, 1818, IV, 111), that the capture of Pensacola was in anticipation<br />

of a threat from the Spanish governor to drive Jackson out of the province that<br />

he had entered in pursuance of his orders. He cited chapter and verse from<br />

Martens on international law in support of his convictions. On the other hand,<br />

he wrote of the Administration's moral and political "dilemma"<br />

self unable to escape the judgment of power at hand.<br />

and was him<br />

The Administration were placed in a dilemma from which it is impossible for them<br />

to escape censure by some, and factious crimination by many. If avow they and<br />

approve Jackson's conduct, they incur the double responsibility of having<br />

commenced a war with Spain, and of warring in violation of the Constitution<br />

without the authority of Congress. If they disavow him, they<br />

must give offence to<br />

all his friends, encounter the shock of popularity, and have the appearance of<br />

truckling to Spain. But the mischief of this determination lies deeper: 1. It is


284 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

weakness, and confession of weakness. 2. The disclaimer of power in the<br />

Executive is of dangerous example and of evil consequences. 3. There is injustice<br />

to the officer in disavowing him when he is strictly justifiable. (Nevins, pp. 196<br />

200)<br />

Adams's position, elaborated further in a momentous state paper to the Ameri<br />

can Minister in Spain, won the enthusiastic endorsement of Jefferson. This was<br />

"among the ablest compositions [he had] ever seen, both as to logic and style<br />

and was a vivid illustration of the level of American statecraft (from<br />

Jefferson to President Monroe, January 18, 1819, in Adams, Writings, VI,<br />

502). Intervening circumstances, particularly slavery and the annexation of<br />

Texas (the "apoplexy of the Constitution"), led Adams some three decades later<br />

to reverse his position and disclaim the power of President Polk's "aggression"<br />

against Mexico in 1846. Adams viewed the war as an attempt by Polk to move<br />

beyond proper continental limits through the use of force and expansion of<br />

slavery.<br />

With respect to the first principles of philosophy and theology, as apart from<br />

science, Adams was less given to questioning the reasons for things than his<br />

father, with whom he discussed the issue. John Quincy Adams spoke of never<br />

having "much relish for the speculations of the first philosophy"; his mind was<br />

not one that took delight "in reasoning high upon 'Fix'd fate, free will, and<br />

foreknowledge<br />

absolute' "<br />

(To John Adams, October 29, 1816, Writings, VI,<br />

111-12). Disavowing the metaphysics of doctrinal schisms within his own<br />

faith, Adams declared that "the only importance of religion to my mind counts<br />

mankind"<br />

in its influence . . . upon the conduct of (VII, 90). Adams believed<br />

in "the genuine doctrines of Christianity<br />

happiness."<br />

in their application to the pursuit of<br />

In addition, he cited the "Socratic and Ciceronian moral philosophy<br />

as the most exalted system of human conduct ever presented to the<br />

(Memoirs, April 17, 1813, II, 462). This synthesis of classical and Christian<br />

dimensions is broadly compatible with the moral-legal precepts shaping the<br />

Founders'<br />

faith in a constitution grounded in principles of "higher law."<br />

Its tenets were beyond the ordinary level of human infirmity; and so are those of<br />

Christianity. It made the essence of virtue to consist in self-subjugation; and so<br />

does Christianity. It gave out a theory of perfection to the aim of man, and made<br />

the endeavor to attain it duty; so does Christianity. The perfect example . was<br />

not given, as by Christ; not even Socrates. Yet he, and Cicero .<br />

eminence of practical virtue. . (ibid.)<br />

did<br />

attain an<br />

It was among the obligations of statesman, Adams believed, to "aim in so far<br />

as their abilities extend towards the moral purification of their country from<br />

besetting<br />

sins."<br />

This would be accomplished, in the first instance, "by setting<br />

the example of private morality"; and, second, "by promoting the cause in<br />

every way that they can lawfully act on<br />

others"<br />

(To James Lloyd, October 1,<br />

world"


Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs 285<br />

1822, Writings, VII, 312-13). For Adams, natural religion was not a product<br />

of a spontaneous understanding in the heart, but was a learned body of princi<br />

ples in the keeping of society and brought to each generation by<br />

civic education.<br />

the forces of<br />

In Adams's political theory, the Creator had made man a "social being,"<br />

blended his happiness with that of his fellow man, and government was a nec<br />

essary instrumentality<br />

had<br />

for the effectuation of this liaison. Yet he differed from<br />

the general spirit of his day, which was manifested in either a conservative<br />

desire for a government only strong enough to keep the enemies of social order<br />

in harness, or a more radical and Jacksonian opposition to strong govern<br />

ment, except insofar as it must be used to keep the economic oligarchy from<br />

tyranny. Seeing in any<br />

political order the hopes and aspirations of human na<br />

ture, Adams looked upon reason as the foundation from which "we participate<br />

of the divine nature itself."<br />

In his inaugural lecture as Harvard Professor of<br />

Rhetoric in 1805, Adams observed: "It is by the gift of reason, that the human<br />

species enjoys the exclusive privilege of progressive improvement, and is<br />

able to avail itself to the advantages of individual discovery"<br />

([1962], pp. 13-<br />

14). Civil society merely reflected the prevailing concepts of character and<br />

virtue among its members. Government did represent "a restraint upon human<br />

action, and as such, a restraint upon<br />

Liberty."<br />

The constitutional framers were<br />

"aware that to induce the People to impose upon themselves such binding liga<br />

ments, motives were not less cogent than those from which the basis of human<br />

association were . . .<br />

necessary"<br />

([1850], pp. 34-35). A theory of rights, there<br />

fore, is inconceivable without a corresponding conception of obligations. A<br />

passage from Adams's first State of the Union address is worth quoting at<br />

length.<br />

The great object of the institution of civil government is the improvement of the<br />

condition of those who are parties to the social compact, and no government<br />

can accomplish the lawful ends of its institution but in proportion as it improves the<br />

condition of those over whom it is established. But moral, political, and<br />

intellectual improvement are duties assigned by the Author of Our Existence to<br />

social no less than individual man. For the fulfillment of these duties governments<br />

are invested with power, and for the attainment of the end . . the<br />

delegated power is a duty<br />

criminal and odious. ([1966], I, 243-44)<br />

exercise of<br />

as sacred . as the usurpation of powers not granted is<br />

By no means, however, was Adams's tribute a ceremony<br />

of national self-<br />

congratulation. He believed that the doctrine of internal improvement had more<br />

than an American application. He was, for example, filled with admiration for<br />

Peter the Great as the genius who had built St. Petersburg according to a mag<br />

nificent plan. Peter applied his energies through government, and the capital<br />

was suited to the leadership that was reorienting Russia in a new direction. As<br />

Secretary of State, Adams admonished the Columbians to think little of Colum-


286 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

bia as a center of empire but to give due regard to the bounties of nature. "God<br />

to thee has done his part do<br />

thine"<br />

(National Archives, IX, 297-98). No<br />

negative suspicion of government limited his conception of what men could<br />

accomplish through its agency. He enjoined men of all lands to apply their<br />

skills through government to the task of internal improvement.<br />

Like Jefferson, Adams was unwilling to admit of any dual morality in the<br />

uses of politics and diplomacy i.e., by setting the political sphere apart from<br />

the private one for purposes of ethical evaluation. In his Harvard commence<br />

ment address upon graduating in 1787, Adams took up the problem in a speech<br />

Community."<br />

on the "Importance of Public Faith to the Well-Being of a He<br />

was troubled by the suggestion "that nations are not subjected to those laws,<br />

which regulate the conduct of individuals; that national policy commands them<br />

to consult their interest, though at the expense of foreigners,<br />

or of individual<br />

citizens."<br />

Could there, he asked, be more than one kind of justice and equity?<br />

Could "honor and probity be qualities of such an accommodating nature that<br />

they<br />

will like the venal sycophant at court suit themselves to all times to the<br />

interests of the prevailing<br />

ings, I, 34-35). Adams thought of the nation as a "moral<br />

party?"<br />

(To Jeremy Belknap, August 6, 1787, Writ<br />

person"<br />

in the family<br />

of nations. This moral person, in view of the international law governing the<br />

subject, was possessed of external rights and obligations that remained un<br />

changed by any<br />

"internal revolution of government."2<br />

In this context, he de<br />

scribed as a new maxim in the law of nations the principle, especially devised<br />

by the victors to apply to Napoleon, that a sovereign by the breach of a treaty<br />

should forfeit "all legal right to<br />

existence."'<br />

Adams was, of course, exposed to the political temptation of acting on a<br />

felicitous coincidence between the best interests of the United States and eternal<br />

verity.<br />

Nothing do<br />

that we could .<br />

would remove this impression until the world shall<br />

be familiarized with the idea of considering our proper domain to be the continent<br />

of North America. From the time we became an independent people it was as much<br />

a law of nature this should become our pretension as that the Mississippi should<br />

flow to the sea. (Memoirs, IV, 437-39)<br />

Moreover, he conceived of the law of nature and nature's God as requiring the<br />

eventual achievement of most "liberal"<br />

principles of commercial relations and<br />

exchange, in particular resulting in the opening up of South American ports to<br />

the commerce of the world and in relaxing imperial commercial restrictions. He<br />

especially importuned the British to liberalize their system, and propounded a<br />

policy<br />

of mutual exclusions upon British commerce in order to force conces<br />

sions. He described the policy of the United States with regard to South Amer<br />

ica as based upon the two principles of "entire and unqualified<br />

recipro<br />

and<br />

permanent most-favored-nation treatment, which were necessary to the achieve-


Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs 287<br />

ment of South American independence (National Archives, VIII, 241. See also<br />

Adams [1900], II, 288). In negotiating treaties of commerce,<br />

a nation should<br />

seek not only to satisfy its own interests but should also be willing "to concede<br />

liberally<br />

Message,"<br />

Regarding<br />

to that which is adapted to the interest of the<br />

p. 380).<br />

other"<br />

("Third Annual<br />

British and Spanish possessions upon the northern and southern<br />

borders, Adams thought it "impossible that centuries should elapse without<br />

finding<br />

them annexed to the United States."<br />

Few of Adams's contemporaries<br />

would be so quick to stake out the moral high ground by vigorously protesting<br />

that this did not involve "any<br />

Any<br />

spirit of encroachment or ambition on our<br />

effort on the part of the United States "to reason the world out of a belief<br />

that we are ambitious will have no other effect than to convince them that we<br />

add to our ambition hypocrisy"<br />

(Memoirs, IV, 439).<br />

Adams recognized that the nature of international politics often entailed<br />

making a distinction between methods and purposes in diplomacy. The nation<br />

may be a moral person; however, self-preservation was also the first law of<br />

nature. Nations acknowledged no judge between them on earth. Their govern<br />

ments "from necessity,<br />

must in their intercourse with each other decide when<br />

the failure of one party to a contract to perform its obligations, absolves the<br />

other from the reciprocal fulfillment of its<br />

"committed many great<br />

ernment with those of external<br />

own"<br />

([1839], p. 68). America had<br />

errors"<br />

in "confounding the principles of internal gov<br />

relations."<br />

Adams never extended normative<br />

sanction to the presence of self-interest in political life. But there "must be<br />

force for the government of mankind,<br />

and whoever in this world does not<br />

choose to fight for his freedom, must turn Quaker or look out for a<br />

part."<br />

master"<br />

(To<br />

William Vans Murray, July 22, 1798, Writings, II, 344). Adams disclaimed<br />

"as unsound all patriotism incompatible with the principles of eternal justice."<br />

Fiat justitia, pareat coelum. Yet this line of reasoning was not precisely appli<br />

cable to the diplomatic craft, inasmuch as negotiation and political compromise<br />

were rooted in a prudent disposition to reconcile conflicting values in changing<br />

situations.<br />

Adams was acutely conscious of the significance and implication of diplo<br />

matic maneuver,<br />

and his first contacts with the British government provided<br />

him with early experience in the art. Sir Charles Bagot was the most successful<br />

British minister he had known. This fact impressed him because success was<br />

perhaps based on the minister's mediocre talents, and this possibility staggered<br />

Adams's "belief in the universality of the maxim that men of the greatest tal<br />

ents ought to be sought out for diplomatic<br />

Adams noted<br />

missions."<br />

In a revealing profile,<br />

The principal feature of his character is discretion, one of the most indispensable<br />

qualities of the good negotiator. His temper is serious, but cheerful. He has no<br />

depth of dissimulation, though enough to suppress his feelings when it is for his


288 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

interest to conceal them. To neutralize fretful passions and soothe prejudices, a<br />

man of good breeding, inoffensive manners, and courteous deportment is nearer to<br />

the tme diplomatic standard than one with the genius of Shakespeare, the learning<br />

or the wit of Swift.<br />

of Bentley, the philosophical penetration of Berkeley,<br />

(Memoirs, April 14, 1819, IV, 339)<br />

Adams understood the delicacy and danger in bestowing diplomatic confi<br />

dences; "but, crafty and fraudulent as the trade has the reputation of being, I<br />

. give it as the result of my experience that confidence . judiciously . bestowed<br />

negotiation"<br />

is one of the most powerful and efficacious instruments of<br />

(May<br />

28, 1819, p. 377). Adams also knew that improper methods, or morally ques<br />

tionable means, may exact a high price. What is here done with good intentions<br />

but unwisely and hence with disastrous results is morally defective; for it vio<br />

lates the ethics of responsibility to which action affecting others, and political<br />

action par excellence, is subject (Morgenthau [1946],<br />

p. 186).<br />

ADAMS AND THE AMERICAN MISSION: FINAL THOUGHTS<br />

Adams joined with Jefferson in affirming natural rights as the moral com<br />

pass of the union; he quoted Madison's "pride and boast of America, that the<br />

rights for which she contended, were the rights of human<br />

nature"<br />

([1850], p.<br />

22). His world view was one that could rarely decouple the expression of na<br />

tional interest from underlying values of national purpose. From the horizon of<br />

ethics, Adams was reluctant to condone any essential difference between public<br />

and private moral acts. Perhaps the most that can be said concerning the moral<br />

character of a private, as over against a political,<br />

action is that an individual<br />

acting in one capacity may be more or less moral than when acting in the other.<br />

Adams's political and diplomatic career was conspicuous by his belief in a<br />

vital connection between America's commitment to mankind and clear limits to<br />

the moral authority of the nation's power in world affairs. As a realist, he<br />

understood the restraints imposed by an anarchic world arena in which America<br />

would only be a minor (but not always unimportant) player in the European<br />

balance. As an idealist, he exhorted his countrymen to uphold the public virtues<br />

of republican rule as a model for other nations to emulate. In other words,<br />

America's success in the world for which a prudent and modestly conceived<br />

national interest was necessary was a function of the nation's own moral and<br />

spiritual stamina in its self-governance. America, Adams wrote in 1816, was<br />

"the strongest nation upon the globe for every purpose of justice."<br />

Yet he could<br />

not "ask of heaven success, even for my country, in a case where she would be<br />

in the<br />

of right,<br />

wrong."<br />

He hoped America might "be armed in thunder for the defense<br />

and self-shackled in eternal impotence for the support of<br />

John Adams, August 1, 1816, Writings, VI, 60-62).<br />

Adams would even more forcefully<br />

wrong"<br />

(To<br />

accentuate the importance of national<br />

self-restraint in his July 4, 1821, oration before the citizens of Washington. His


Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs - 289<br />

address was in answer to the question, What has America done for the benefit<br />

of mankind? In the assembly of nations, the United States has "held forth to<br />

them the hand of honest friendship, of equal freedom,<br />

of generous<br />

recipr<br />

Furthermore, for over a half-century, the nation "abstained from interference in<br />

the concerns of others, even when conflict has been for principles to which she<br />

clings. . .<br />

Whenever the standard of freedom and independence has or shall be unfurled, there<br />

will her heart, her benedictions, and her prayers be. But she goes not abroad, in<br />

search of monsters to destroy. She is the well-wisher to the freedom and<br />

independence of all. She is the champion and vindicator only of her own. (Quoted<br />

in LaFeber, pp. 42-46)<br />

Adams's remarks point to a concern for the consequences of intervention in<br />

wars "of interest and intrigue, of individual avarice, envy, and ambition, which<br />

assume the colors and usurp the standard of freedom."<br />

dominion, but liberty. Her march is the march of the<br />

America's glory "is not<br />

mind."<br />

Adams's concept<br />

of international ethics illustrates how universal principles of right and obliga<br />

tion in foreign policy take a direct bearing from the moral and political order of<br />

civil society.<br />

NOTES<br />

1 . Jefferson's<br />

convictions were concisely stated in the following terms:<br />

We believed, with them, that man was a rational animal, endowed by nature with<br />

rights, and with an innate sense of justice; and that he could be restrained from wrong and<br />

protected in right, by moderate powers, confided to persons of his own choice, and held to<br />

their duties by dependence on his own will.<br />

To Judge William Johnson, June 12, 1823, Writings, (1903), XV, 441.<br />

2. National Archives, IX, 8. To Don Dionisio Vives, State Department, May 8, 1820, Writ<br />

ings, VII, 18: He asserted that Spain could not be relieved of an obligation to ratify a treaty that<br />

had been signed by a plenipotentiary, even though he had acted on unqualified instructions of a<br />

sovereign whose authority was subsequently limited by a legislative body asserting a new constitu<br />

tional power to pass on treaties.<br />

3. To Abigail Adams, April 22, 1815, Writings, V, 302. Adams, without ever explicitly deal<br />

ing with the point at length, distinguished between the sovereign "moral<br />

person,"<br />

the nation, sus<br />

ceptible of no act incompatible with the necessities of the moral system of which it was a part, and<br />

the physical sovereign in a monarchy, who could be sovereign only in a fashion subordinate to the<br />

level of a nation. Annals of Congress, 9th Congress, 1st session, March 3, 1806, pp. 145-61.<br />

REFERENCES<br />

Adams, Charles Francis, ed. Memoirs of John Quincy Adams. Philadelphia: J. B. Lip-<br />

pincott, 1874-77.<br />

Adams, Henry. The Degradation of Democratic Dogma. New York: Macmillan, 1920.<br />

Adams, John Quincy. "First Annual Message."<br />

In Fred L. Israel, ed., The State of the<br />

Union Messages of the Presidents, 1790-1966. New York: Chelsea House, 1966.


290 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

"First Annual Message."<br />

In James D. Richardson, ed., A Compilation of the<br />

Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 1789-1897. Congress, 1900.<br />

The Jubilee of the Constitution, a Discourse Delivered at the Request of the<br />

New York Historical Society, in the City of New York on Tuesday, the 30th of April<br />

1839; being the Fiftieth Anniversary of the Inauguration of George Washington as<br />

President of the United States, on Thursday, the 30th of April, 1789. New York:<br />

Samuel Colman, 1839.<br />

Lectures on Rhetoric and Oratory. New York: Russell and Russell, 1962.<br />

The Lives of James Madison and James Monroe. Boston: Phillips, Sampson<br />

and Co., 1850.<br />

July, 1831 .<br />

An Oration Addressed to the Citizens of the Town of Quincy on the Fourth of<br />

Boston: Richardson, Lord and Holbrook, 1831.<br />

An Oration Delivered before the Inhabitants of the Town of Newburyport at<br />

their request, on the Sixty-first Anniversary of the Declaration of Independence, July<br />

4, 1837. Newburyport: Charles Whipple, 1837.<br />

The Social Compact, Exemplified in the Constitution of the Commonwealth of<br />

Massachusetts; with Remarks on the Theories of Divine Right by Hobbes and Filmer,<br />

and the Counter Theories of Sidney, Locke, Montesquieu and Rousseau concerning<br />

the Origin And Nature of Government. Providence: Knowles and Vose, 1842.<br />

"Third Annual Message."<br />

In James D. Richardson, ed., A Compilation of the<br />

Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 1789-1897. Congress, 1900.<br />

"The Wants of Man,"<br />

and Buffalo: Miller, Orton and Mulligan, 1848.<br />

stanza xxii. In Poems of Religion and Society. Auburn<br />

The Writings of John Quincy Adams. Edited by<br />

York: Macmillan, 1913-17.<br />

Annals of Congress, 9th Congress, Ist Session, March 3, 1806.<br />

Worthington C. Ford. New<br />

Bellah, Robert N. The Broken Covenant. New York: Seabury Press, 1975.<br />

Bemis, Samuel Flagg, John Quincy Adams and the Foundations of American Foreign<br />

Policy. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1949.<br />

Germino, Dante. Unpublished paper delivered at the Claremont Institute Conference on<br />

the American Bicentennial, Claremont, CA, February 23-25, 1984.<br />

Graebner, Norman A., ed. Tradition and Values: American Diplomacy, 1790-1865.<br />

Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1985.<br />

Jefferson, Thomas. The Writings of Thomas Jefferson. Edited by Albert E. Bergh and<br />

Andrew Lipscomb. Washington, DC: Jefferson Memorial Association, 1903.<br />

The Writings of Thomas Jefferson. Edited by Paul Leicester Ford. New York:<br />

G. P Putnam's Sons, 1892-99.<br />

Kirk, Russell. The Conservative Mind. Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1953.<br />

Kissinger, Henry A. Power."<br />

"Morality and In Ernest W. Lefever, ed., Morality and<br />

Foreign Policy. Washington, DC: Ethics and Public Policy Center of Georgetown<br />

University, 1977.<br />

Koch, Adrienne. Power, Morals, and the Founding Fathers. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Uni<br />

versity Press, 1961.<br />

LaFeber, Walter, ed. John Quincy Adams and American Continental Empire. Chicago:<br />

Quadrangle Books, 1965.<br />

Lang, Daniel G., and Greg Russell. "The Ethics of Power in American Diplomacy: The<br />

Statecraft of John Quincy Adams."<br />

Review of Politics (Winter, 1990): 3-31.


"Letters of John Adams and John Quincy<br />

Library X (April 1910): 246-47.<br />

Jeffersonian Ethics in Foreign Affairs 291<br />

Adams."<br />

Bulletin of the New York Public-<br />

Lipsky, George P. John Quincy Adams, His Theory and Ideas. New York: Thomas Y.<br />

Crowell, 1950.<br />

Morgenthau, Hans J. In Defense of the National Interest. New York: Alfred A. Knopf,<br />

1951.<br />

1946.<br />

Politics Among Nations. 5th ed. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1973.<br />

Scientific Man vs. Power Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,<br />

National Archives, Records of the Department of State, Diplomatic Instructions, All<br />

Countries.<br />

Nevins, Allan, ed. The Diary of John Quincy Adams, 1794-1845. New York: Long<br />

mans, Green, 1928.<br />

Sabine, George H. A History of Political Theory. New York: Henry Holt, 1937.<br />

Sandoz, Ellis. A Government of Laws: Political Theory, Religion, and the American<br />

Founding. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1990.<br />

Schlesinger, Arthur M., Jr. The Age of Jackson. Boston: Little, Brown, 1945.<br />

Schutz, John A., and Douglass Adair, eds. Spur of Fame: Dialogues of John Adams and<br />

Benjamin Rush, 1805-1813. San Marino, CA: Huntington Library, 1980.<br />

Tarcov, Nathan. "Principle and Prudence in Foreign Policy: The Founders'<br />

tive."<br />

The Public Interest LXXVI (Summer, 1984): 48.<br />

Perspec<br />

Voegelin, Eric. New Science of Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952.<br />

Wright, Benjamin F., Jr. American <strong>Interpretation</strong>s of Natural Law. New York: Russell<br />

and Russell, 1931.


Feminist Theory<br />

Daryl McGowan Tress<br />

Trinity College<br />

and Its Discontents<br />

In the wide-ranging work of his late career, Civilization and Its Discontents,<br />

Sigmund Freud speaks of the malaise bred in the individual and in culture by<br />

the denial and suppression of the forces of irrationality. These instincts, aggres<br />

sive and sexual, are experienced as dangerous and so are repressed. But, Freud<br />

insists, to repress these forces is not to eliminate them. What is denied and<br />

forgotten lurks beneath the surface of conscious and cultural life, constantly<br />

undermining and threatening to destroy the glorious constructions of self and<br />

civilization (see especially Chs. 6 and 7).<br />

I would like to borrow in a limited way from Freud's lesson in Civilization<br />

and Its Discontents and consider what it is that feminist theory has come to<br />

perceive as threatening to its enterprise, what it is that feminist theory believes<br />

it needs to defend itself against. From the contemporary feminist point of view,<br />

it is not the forces of irrationality that are threatening, but instead reason and<br />

rationality are viewed as masculine and as the foes against which women must<br />

defend themselves. Increasingly, feminist theory fixes its attention on passion<br />

and power, on the nonrational, at the expense of reason. The history of feminist<br />

thought, along with a major current in history of ideas generally over the last<br />

two hundred years, reveals a growing tendency to draw positive significance<br />

and value from the irrational while looking<br />

threatening<br />

aspects of "the<br />

to expose the full negative and<br />

rational."<br />

But, as I hope to show, the denial of<br />

reason can be no more successful than the denial of the irrational; it inevitably<br />

leads to contradictions and instability, especially<br />

identity<br />

as feminism requires for its<br />

what it condemns and denies as oppressive. The inconsistencies and the<br />

discomfort they generate are signs of a serious failure in feminist theory's intel<br />

lectual ancestry, and this is what I will trace.<br />

Feminism has made some very valuable strides for women. The organized<br />

efforts of women to win the vote, for example,<br />

variety<br />

and to put an end to a wide<br />

of forms of legal and economic discrimination against women are most<br />

worthy of respect. The exposure by feminists of more private but nonetheless<br />

pernicious forms of maintaining women's subordination has been beneficial,<br />

even if sometimes disruptive and painful. Lately, though, feminism has fallen<br />

on hard times. One sign of this, surely, is the reluctance of many women today<br />

This paper was originally<br />

Lecture at Trinity College.<br />

interpretation, Winter 1990-1991, Vol. 18, No. 2<br />

presented in April, 1989 as the Blanchard William Means Memorial


294 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

to identify<br />

themselves as "feminists,"<br />

even while they do support the promotion<br />

of women's interests. (See Chadwick or Fleming for differing generational<br />

views of feminist ideals as presented in the general media.) For a movement<br />

that sees itself necessarily as a popular, broad-based political one, lack of popu<br />

lar appeal is a most serious problem. And while feminist theory has attracted a<br />

good deal of attention in academic and publishing circles, it is currently in<br />

internal disarray, experiencing disputes, for example, over liberal, integrating<br />

political strategies versus radical, revolutionary ones, and over efforts to reev<br />

aluate positively women's traditional activities while simultaneously calling for<br />

radical reformations of social life that gave those traditional activities meaning.<br />

In addition to these deep differences regarding aims, the latest work in feminist<br />

theory adopts the very skeptical stance characteristic of some contemporary<br />

European philosophical movements and launches an attack on "logocentrism,"<br />

or, with its feminist twist, "phallogocentrism."<br />

These are the pejorative terms<br />

applied to the philosophical tradition which claims the superiority of reason.<br />

According to feminist theorists, phallogocentrism, representing the reign of the<br />

phallus, i.e. masculinity, is in its insistence on rationality repressive, dominat<br />

ing, and violent. Rationality<br />

is seen from this new feminist point of view as the<br />

source of many, if not all, of the different forms of oppression in the modern<br />

world (e.g. sexism, racism, and imperialism)<br />

threat to women's safety and happiness.'<br />

and so is viewed as a powerful<br />

As a philosopher I have been both troubled and puzzled by the hostility<br />

towards reason in recent feminist theorizing, and the increasing erosion of the<br />

place of reason in feminist work. If, in trying to understand this development,<br />

one examines the genesis and growth of feminist theory, one discovers that this<br />

is not a new trend but is really the inevitable culmination of a long process.<br />

Feminist theory's current troubling state springs inexorably<br />

atic origins.<br />

from its problem<br />

What I will try to show is that the development of feminist theory reflects<br />

the intellectual history of the past three centuries, i.e., feminist theory comes<br />

into being<br />

as a modernist movement and the course of its development mirrors<br />

the vicissitudes of the modern intellectual era. Especially evident in the history<br />

of feminist theory is the very unsteady state of reason and rationality in late<br />

modernity. (See the differing perspectives on this phenomenon of Strauss, Mac<br />

lntyre, Cascardi and Lang.)<br />

Two troubling general consequences of the elevation of passion and power<br />

and the reduction or elimination of reason can be noted at the start: the first is<br />

that appropriate aims for desire and political action cannot be determined and<br />

these areas of life become chaotic. A second difficulty is that the categories one<br />

looks to defend or revitalize begin to unravel, that is, they become internally<br />

inconsistent and their explanatory power is weakened (for example, the basic<br />

feminist concept of "gender"<br />

is currently coming undone. See "Editorial.").<br />

Modernism makes feminism both necessary and possible, that is, the modern<br />

intellectual era provokes it into being and provides it with a set of intellectual


Feminist Theory<br />

and its Discontents 295<br />

tools to construct itself. But at the same time, feminist theory is also heiress to<br />

all debts and problems of the modern intellectual era,<br />

and these have come to<br />

manifest themselves in the current confusion which riddles feminist theory.<br />

Let me specify what I mean by "modernism"<br />

(and point out parenthetically<br />

what will soon become obvious: that I am working with very broad historical<br />

categories, and so I have simplified what are in fact very<br />

complex systems of<br />

ideas). I distinguish three major movements within it: early modernism, anti-<br />

modernism, and postmodernism. "Early<br />

modernism"<br />

here designates the world-<br />

views originating in the West in the seventeenth century and maturing<br />

in the<br />

Enlightenment era of the eighteenth century which expressly repudiated re<br />

liance on the earlier classical and medieval-theological traditions. These tradi<br />

tions had been based on a divinely ordered cosmos and an immaterial human<br />

essence or soul which had its own natural ends. Early modern thought placed<br />

confidence not in the authority of tradition but instead in the knowing subject<br />

and in the subject-as-knowable. The subject can know, grasp, and conquer<br />

nature, and can come, as well, to know himself or herself with certainty be<br />

cause the subject now is regarded as secular and as operating according to<br />

scientific rather than divine laws. "Antimodernism"<br />

designates modernism's<br />

turn against itself, its rebellion against the Enlightenment preoccupation with<br />

reason and scientific knowledge. The spirit of antimodernism is expressed in<br />

nineteenth century Romanticism's embrace of the imagination and in the revo<br />

lutionary political urging of praxis or activity<br />

as superior to theory. In the<br />

antimodern period, history and nature are regarded as surpassing rational, indi<br />

vidual efforts at control. Finally<br />

"postmodernism,"<br />

the most recent intellectual<br />

current, is one that consciously defies definition; its spokespersons, Derrida,<br />

Lacan, Foucault, and Rorty, to name a few, set postmodernism in opposition to<br />

the values of both early modernism and antimodernism, in particular to the<br />

confidence the previous modernisms display in the solidity and self-sufficiency<br />

of the subject. For postmodernists,<br />

a fragmented subject moves in a de<br />

naturalized world where everything is a construction of language or an opera<br />

tion of power, and the denaturalization of which intellectuals and artists are<br />

obligated to express and promote in their work. (Jardine's study is partic<br />

ularly illuminating<br />

sources of "postmodern"<br />

on the "denaturalization"<br />

feminist theory.)<br />

of postmodernism and on the<br />

At these three modernist pressure points, certain features characteristic of<br />

the modern intellectual period can be detected: the rejection of tradition and the<br />

desire for "new"<br />

solutions, the overarching attitude of opposition and rebellion,<br />

the atmosphere of crisis, the priority given to analysis of power and its opera<br />

tions, the emphasis placed, on the one hand, on the defense of the autonomous<br />

subject independently willing and choosing his or her own ends, and on the<br />

other, a preoccupation with a political and/or sociological analysis of power<br />

groups and their dynamics, and finally, a disillusionment with and rejection of<br />

all these categories and the difficulties they represent.<br />

These features of the modernist program, all of which mark feminist theory,


296 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

can be contrasted with the premodern,<br />

classical philosophical outlook. The<br />

classical view holds to the notion of human essence which is timeless in its<br />

nature. Because some aspects of human nature are timelessly true, tradition and<br />

its thinking are valuable for us; the problems we confront now are not so terri-<br />

fyingly new, nor, perhaps, do they have the dramatic exigency that modernism<br />

insists upon. Classical philosophy focuses its concern on the human essence or<br />

psyche, and makes the object of its inquiry not discontent, power, needs, and<br />

preference but rather virtue, that is, what makes a person, or people, excellent,<br />

what is it that we do best to desire.'<br />

Since all human beings as human beings<br />

possess a similarly structured psyche, relationship and community<br />

are possible<br />

and desirable; we are neither atomistic individuals nor social constructions,<br />

according<br />

to this view. The classical outlook maintains that the ground of real<br />

ity is stable essence or form or substance, and hence is intelligible and access<br />

ible, to some extent at least, by means of open dialogue and patient, rational<br />

reflection. It places priority on these rather than on willing, acting, changing<br />

the world.<br />

Feminist theorists have been highly wary<br />

"Central to feminism,"<br />

of essentialism from the start.<br />

Anne Donchin writes, "is the disavowal of the concep<br />

tion of the essential self (p. 92). The allegiance of feminist theorists, almost<br />

exclusively, has been and continues to be to a view of women as constructed by<br />

social and historical conditions. Alison Jaggar, a feminist philosopher, suc<br />

cinctly states the reason for this allegiance: "Invariably, anti-feminists have<br />

justified women's subordination in terms of perceived biological differences"<br />

(p.21). The idea of an invariant feminine or human nature or essence, then, is<br />

regarded as grounding the injustices of the status quo and perpetuating<br />

women's subordination.<br />

It is correct, of course, that essentialist models have been used against<br />

is founded<br />

women. But the alternative, modernist model which feminist theory<br />

upon is deeply problematic and will not yield a coherent theory of women. I<br />

believe that once the defects of modernism in all its versions are made plain, a<br />

reconstruction of feminist theory on a classical foundation can begin.<br />

Let us now examine at greater length each of the three modernist stages in<br />

the development of feminist theory and consider its implications.<br />

Mary Wollstonecraft, who lived her relatively short life at the end of the<br />

eighteenth century, generally is placed at the beginning of the lineage of mod<br />

ern feminism. Writing her bold Vindication of the Rights of<br />

Woman in 1792,<br />

she faced the challenge of opposing the popular Enlightenment-era view that<br />

men and women have fundamentally different natures a view developed, for<br />

example, by Rousseau in his best-seller, Emile and using Enlightenment prin<br />

ciples and values to undercut the Enlightenment notion of a basic and thorough<br />

going distinction between the sexes.


Feminist Theory and its Discontents 297<br />

Wollstonecraft saw Rousseau and others arguing on the basis of the apparent<br />

differences in male and female natures that different educational programs and<br />

different political entitlement were not only permissible but beneficial to every<br />

one involved. What seemed obvious to Enlightenment thinkers like Rousseau<br />

and Edmund Burke and others was that women, while possessing<br />

some mea<br />

sure of intelligence and reason, are nevertheless more instinctual, emotional,<br />

and imaginative creatures than men are, and that women are constituted by<br />

nature for the domestic life of pleasing men and caring for children. What was<br />

decisive, of course, was women's deficiency with respect to reason, since enti<br />

tlement to human rights (such as autonomy, freedom of choice, privacy) de<br />

pended upon full possession of rationality.<br />

The notion of different male and female natures posited by<br />

Rousseau and<br />

others can be seen as an expansion upon and intensification of the mind-body<br />

distinction elaborated by some philosophers in the seventeenth century. The<br />

split within subjectivity that is basic to some early modern intellectual models<br />

is externalized and applied to the sexes: mind is more and more strongly associ<br />

ated with men and masculinity, while body is consistently taken as the primary<br />

determinant of women and femininity (see Riley, Ch. 2). As this polarization<br />

becomes more vivid,<br />

and the superior regard for mind and inferior regard for<br />

the body become more boldly prominent in the writings of the eighteenth cen<br />

tury, some intrepid women at least were bound to be provoked to response. The<br />

very easy,<br />

confident expression of women's subordination so popular at the<br />

time can be seen as the provocation which necessarily gave rise to the modern<br />

feminist response.<br />

Mary Wollstonecraft, agreeing with her fellow eighteenth-century thinkers<br />

that, generally, women appear to be deficient in reason, employed standard<br />

eighteenth-century<br />

arguments even Rousseauian arguments to explain that<br />

appearance, namely that women have been made unequal, have been denied<br />

expression of their rationality and consigned to the body by<br />

corrupt public<br />

institutions and by debased interpersonal relationships. Her reformist plan was<br />

to restore women to their full status as rational agents by means of a substantial<br />

education which would be equal to that provided for men. The aim was to<br />

permit women to become free, autonomous, assertive individuals, the equals of<br />

men. The contemporary feminist theorist Carol C. Gould echoes and expands<br />

Wollstonecraft and the spirit of the eighteenth century when she writes her<br />

recommendation for feminism today:<br />

I think the preeminent value that ought to underlie the feminist movement is<br />

freedom, that is, self-development. This arises through the exercise of agency, that<br />

is, through the exercise of the human capacity for free choice, in forms of activity<br />

undertaken to realize one's purposes and to satisfy one's needs. (P. 4)<br />

In this contemporary expansion of the early modernist defense of women,<br />

the emphasis on the self, on free choice, on action to fulfill one's own needs


298 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

and create one's own life are all in evidence. What the self should choose, what<br />

it should do, who it should be would not be specified as part of this paradigm;<br />

values are to be freely and subjectively chosen. One can, to quote Gould once<br />

again, "appropriate any<br />

on one's free<br />

one's choices.<br />

traits for one's own self-development, depending<br />

choice"<br />

(p. 15). There are, in other words, no natural limits to<br />

Wollstonecraft herself wrote courageously and eloquently to vindicate<br />

women and women's rights, and it is important to add, she herself was con<br />

cerned about equality of reason as a path to equality of virtue in men and<br />

women. Her use of an Enlightenment notion of human nature to establish<br />

women's integrity could not succeed, however. I want to suggest that Woll-<br />

stonecraft's failure to persuade stemmed in part from the fact that the split of<br />

subjectivity along sexual lines was already so deep by<br />

the close of the eigh<br />

teenth century that it was no longer possible, strategically, to challenge it from<br />

within. The Enlightenment model of human nature and its ideal of political<br />

equality required a community of individuals who could think and judge coolly<br />

without the obstruction of prejudice or passion. It served the model importantly<br />

to displace such human tendencies both in theory and in practice onto a<br />

separate group. So when Wollstonecraft made her seemingly innocuous pro<br />

posal, that women and men both possess minds so both require education, I<br />

believe she herself was aware, to some extent at least, of how implausible this<br />

would sound to her contemporaries.<br />

"Mind"<br />

had already become evidently<br />

masculine, in ways that the classical soul which it replaced had not been, and<br />

her proposal was bound to strike her audience as bizarre. A clue to Wollstone-<br />

craft's own awareness of the desperation of this situation was her own occa<br />

sional sliding away from her basic commitment to the fundamental equality of<br />

male and female mind to the appeal in the Vindication that men, after all, will<br />

be happier with educated wives than with the delicate,<br />

superficial creatures<br />

whom she saw as the degraded feminine product of Rousseau's unequal educa<br />

tional<br />

program.'<br />

Doubtful about its persuasive possibilities, in other words, she<br />

let her argument become a plea.<br />

Mary<br />

Wollstonecraft's Vindication did not turn the modernist tide. Instead,<br />

due to its own internal dynamics, modernism turned against itself in the nine<br />

teenth century, as it would again in the twentieth with the advent of postmod<br />

ernism. An intellectual shifting of gears took place in the nineteenth century<br />

which produced a wariness about Enlightenment ideals of human rationality<br />

and autonomy and a disillusionment with eighteenth-century political ideals of<br />

self-interested individualism. Some of the important values of the Enlighten<br />

ment were preserved, such as equality and progress, but the notion developed<br />

that radical means were required for their realization. Other Enlightenment<br />

values, however, were rejected, for example the supremacy and independence<br />

of scientific reason. Could there be a more striking and appropriate symbol in<br />

this context of the souring of eighteenth-century optimism about reason and the


Feminist Theory and its Discontents 299<br />

dream of progress and human control of the natural world than this: the classic<br />

nineteenth-century tale of the soulless monster created by the mad, mega-<br />

lomaniacal scientist, the story of Frankenstein, written by Mary Shelley, the<br />

daughter of Mary Wollstonecraft'.'<br />

Two major trends of great consequence for feminism flourished in the nine<br />

teenth century: revolutionary politics, especially Marxism, and Romanticism.<br />

These movements display the extremes of world-views dependent,<br />

hand, on political power,<br />

on the one<br />

and on the other on emotional subjectivity. Both<br />

oppose the ideals of the eighteenth century and particularly the early modern<br />

ideal of reason on the grounds that a hidden, privileged process (i.e., power or<br />

"life"), inaccessible to Enlightenment reason alone, is the true ground of real<br />

ity.<br />

A radical departure made by<br />

stratum in human beings. Instead of having<br />

Karl Marx is his elimination of a natural sub<br />

a basic nature which has been<br />

obscured and spoiled by social conditions an eighteenth-century view<br />

Marx's proposal is that human beings are thoroughly determined, not by the<br />

tangle of their desires but by external social, political, and economic forces.<br />

The complete, thoroughgoing<br />

dependence of human beings on these forces<br />

means that their proper ordering is of the utmost urgency. Capitalism is the<br />

current exploitative arrangement that shapes modern life, according<br />

and Marxists; it is a system which requires a revolutionary overthrow.<br />

to Marx<br />

This political model recommends itself as pledged to equality among people<br />

and between the sexes; it regards apparent differences in mentality as the effect<br />

of differing<br />

material conditions. Since there is no human nature prior to social<br />

influences in its view, there is no natural base in which significant mental or<br />

rational differences between women and men could permanently inhere. With<br />

the aim in mind of establishing women's full humanity, this revolutionary polit<br />

ical model might seem promising, and a large number of contemporary femi<br />

nists, such as Nancy Hartsock, Juliet Mitchell, Evelyn Reed, and others, have<br />

followed the classic application of the Marxist approach to women's condition,<br />

namely, Frederick Engels'<br />

The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the<br />

State. In this work he tells the story of the beginnings of the exploitation and<br />

oppression of women as coinciding with the beginnings of capital and private<br />

property.<br />

The sources of all traits, according to this model,<br />

made visible. Thus "sex,"<br />

male and female, is greatly minimized by way<br />

from<br />

"gender,"<br />

are external and can be<br />

the apparently inescapable biological determinant of<br />

of this model and separated<br />

the social determination of masculine and feminine; "gender"<br />

becomes the concept basic to feminist discourse. And we can come not only to<br />

see the externally imposed sources of inequality but, more significantly, do<br />

something<br />

to change the situation of exploitation and subjugation. The principle


300 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

(answering perfectly to certain Enlightenment desires) is that what has been<br />

humanly produced can be humanly grasped, altered, overthrown.<br />

There are, however, a number of serious problems generated by the use of<br />

this political model for understanding women. The first is connected with the<br />

Marxist concept of<br />

"ideology"<br />

(see Mah). The divided self of the early modern<br />

period, in Marxism, is realigned and mind and body are assigned a new hier<br />

archy, namely, that mind and its output, theory, are effects of material causes.<br />

The material relations in the world, according to Marx, produce ideas. Ideas<br />

and theory are not, in this view, autonomous and dependable guides for arrang<br />

ing human worldly affairs, but instead are necessarily saturated with class inter<br />

est and self-interest, as well as a measure of fantasy and wishful thinking typ<br />

ically permitted by abstract thought which holds itself aloof from specific,<br />

material conditions.<br />

The concept of ideology thus articulated in Marxist work is a volatile one,<br />

however. It does allow feminists to claim that the reigning set of ideals of<br />

female inferiority are ideological, i.e., self-serving for the power elite and<br />

hence suspect, thereby challenging Enlightenment assumptions. But this "ideol<br />

therapy"<br />

kills the patient along with the disease. Ultimately, the implica<br />

ogy<br />

tion of the concept of ideology is that ideas and theory cannot be trustworthy;<br />

they are always contaminated by class interest, always pretending to be supe<br />

rior to the world when they are, after all, only<br />

expressions of prior economic<br />

and power relations. By borrowing this concept, then, feminist theory in effect<br />

abandons any expectation of firmly establishing its ideas regarding women's<br />

full humanity. No set of ideas, no theory is immune from the charge of ideol<br />

ogy. Ideas and philosophy are further disparaged in this model, since the aim,<br />

as stated in Marx's overquoted epitaph, is not to understand but to change the<br />

world. According to this view, one must be able, above all, to do and act;<br />

philosophy, which regards itself as nonpartisan inquiry, indulges in self-decep<br />

tion and lends itself as a tool of the oppressors. This sentiment is echoed by the<br />

contemporary feminist theorists such as Andrea Nye, who wonders resignedly<br />

whether feminist practice might have to be sufficient for feminism since theory<br />

has a sexist history which can never be eliminated, and Kathryn Pyne Ad-<br />

delson, who chastises feminists who have forgotten that feminist practice pro<br />

duces feminist theory, not the other way around, and that feminist practice has<br />

one goal: to change the material conditions of women. Given these principles,<br />

how an adequate theory could ever be available or what its real value would be<br />

if one could develop it is extremely hard to see. Indeed, in this world-view<br />

where power is reality and takes the form of conflicting interests, any disin<br />

terested inquiry such as philosophy is bound to appear useless at the very best,<br />

blindly and dangerously<br />

manipulative at worst.<br />

One other feature of the Marxist model deserves attention in relation to<br />

feminist theory. This is that Marx's is a social theory rather than a theory of<br />

individuality. It is one which tells the story of class conflict, the story that the<br />

basis of the "real<br />

world"<br />

is the group dynamics of money and power, and that


Feminist Theory and its Discontents 301<br />

this is a dynamic of conflict and exploitation. Thus, this world-view is one of<br />

groups pitted against one another under capitalism; the attention to large social<br />

patterns of oppression calls for women to unite and rise up against a common<br />

oppressor. By shifting attention away<br />

from individual experience of subordina<br />

tion and unhappiness to the common features of oppression, the Marxist politi<br />

cal outlook allows women to unite against social injustice and or "feminism"<br />

a political force to be born. A problem with this political or sociological lens is<br />

that it filters out personal difference and the texture of individual lives, or<br />

perceives the personal and intimate according to the categories of economics<br />

and politics. So, for example, Nancy<br />

Reproduction of Mothering, talks of mothers "investing"<br />

187), and Paula Rothenberg<br />

between the sexes; by "political<br />

Chodorow in her widely-read work The<br />

speaks of the "political"<br />

as<br />

in their children, (p.<br />

nature of the relations<br />

relationship"<br />

Rothenberg means one which<br />

"involves a struggle for control between individuals of unequal power and sta<br />

tus, who confront each other with essentially opposed interests"<br />

(p. 205. The<br />

criticism of Chodorow is made by Elshtain, p. 292; see also Ch. 5 for a lengthy<br />

critique of radical, liberal, Marxist, and psychoanalytic feminisms.).<br />

Trouble also arises specifically within Marxism when trying to conceive of<br />

women as a "class,"<br />

"Class"<br />

since women are members of every economic class.<br />

is basic identity in this model,<br />

and that it might be impossible to ade<br />

quately identify women within Marxism has been disconcerting<br />

nents. (Eventually, the notion of "the<br />

for its propo<br />

patriarchy"<br />

seemed to offer a sufficiently<br />

generalized antagonist for generating women's political solidarity across all<br />

classes.)<br />

This political outlook, in insisting that power is basic and that class conflict<br />

is everywhere,<br />

and fosters a "conflict<br />

certainly<br />

requires and deepens an adversarial and oppositional attitude<br />

consciousness"<br />

of the world in general. Questions can<br />

be raised about how comfortable most women are with a generalized<br />

adversarial sensibility and whether women believe themselves sufficiently de<br />

fined by the rhetoric oppression,<br />

which allows women the narrow options of<br />

being either victims, victim-resisters, or collaborators. Finally,<br />

we can notice<br />

here, as we did with the Marxist concept of ideology, the corrosive effect this<br />

political, adversarial attitude has an open, philosophical questioning. Feminism<br />

becomes a "cause"<br />

that demands loyalty and can be criticized only<br />

with the<br />

utmost delicacy. One aims here, above all, not to understand but to act, to right<br />

wrongs, to air grievances, to avenge, to punish, to defend the oppressed and to<br />

deprive the oppressors of power, to promote the revolution, to change the<br />

world. In the bargain for political effectiveness, the price paid is a diminished<br />

respect and capacity for rational thought which is reflective and reserved.<br />

The other major nineteenth-century intellectual trend of importance for femi<br />

nist theory is Romanticism. Romanticism's rebellion took this general form:<br />

discursive thought and scientific reason were rejected and replaced by emotion


302 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

and imagination. Romanticism turned its attention fully to the self, the subject<br />

in his or her personal experience. It valued achieving one's true home or iden<br />

tity, recovering<br />

as most genuine was "Life"<br />

oneself and the world at its most genuine. What was regarded<br />

or nature or passion in its wildness and sponta<br />

neity. The metaphor of the journey or passage inward took on special meaning<br />

for the Romantics, the arduous journey which can be undertaken only by the<br />

remarkable Romantic hero or heroine who is proud, smart, strong, defiant,<br />

and emotionally and imaginatively sensitive. The Romantic hero or heroine<br />

stands apart from and above others, but exactly as a result of his or her superior<br />

sensitivity is likely to be a social outcast, misunderstood and mistreated by the<br />

many out of their ignorance and envy. (We might note, parenthetically, in this<br />

other,"<br />

outlook the longing to be "the the deep desire to be outside the dull<br />

routine of ordinary existence. Yack's book is of interest here.) The novels of<br />

the Bronte sisters offer examples of the Romantic heroine. We may appreciate<br />

the adroitness of the venerable heroines such as Jane Eyre, but we may also<br />

note, as others such as Virginia Woolf have, the resentment in these characters<br />

and the sense of grievance bred by their assurance of their own emotional and<br />

imaginative superiority, particularly when it is not validated by others or when<br />

they perceive that its full development is hindered by material conditions which<br />

do not match their natural entitlement (Thurman).<br />

The Romantic attitude was absorbed into feminism as an alternative way of<br />

answering the problems, persistent since the early modern period, regarding<br />

male-female difference and the inequality bred male-<br />

by the associations of<br />

mind, female-body. What I identify as the Romantic solution to the problem is<br />

the acceptance of these different associations, and the claim, unlike that of the<br />

Enlightenment and Marxist approaches, that the masculine-mind, feminine-<br />

body<br />

associations are indeed "natural."<br />

The Romantic feminist strategy is to<br />

reevaluate positively the body, and the domains of emotion and imagination,<br />

and to assert the superiority of these to abstract, calculating, scientific reason.<br />

Women, according to this narrative, are different, but better.<br />

Romanticism recommends itself in several ways: it endorses a distinctly<br />

feminine sensibility of intuition and sympathy, as the Enlightenment and Marx<br />

ist models did not and could not. It upholds the ideas of women's subjective<br />

experience, of women's privileged access to the natural, powerful wisdom of<br />

sexuality and childbirth, of separate domains in which feminine nature takes<br />

precedence. Furthermore, since women are so different from men, according to<br />

this model, women are in a privileged position to speak for and about women's<br />

experience. Romantic feminism also provides an explanation for the rarity in<br />

history of great public achievements by women, insisting that women's work<br />

has been thwarted and suppressed consistently by the jealous, coarse, and ag<br />

gressive nature of men.<br />

The Romantic view of women as superior, sensitive victims has strongly<br />

influenced contemporary feminism. The victimization model has become very


Feminist Theory and its Discontents 303<br />

familiar in feminist writing over the past twenty years: Susan Brownmiller, for<br />

example, in her book Femininity, analyzes the feminine as a form of constric<br />

tion and suppression, and the feminist philosopher Sandra Lee Bartky writes:<br />

Feminist consciousness is consciousness of victimization [sicj. To apprehend<br />

oneself as victim is to be aware of an alien force which is responsible for the<br />

blatantly unjust treatment of women and to be aware, too, that this<br />

victimization, [is] in no way earned or deserved. .<br />

(P<br />

254)<br />

There is a branch of contemporary romantic feminist theorizing called "cul<br />

tural feminism''<br />

which maintains that there is an essential woman. The nemesis<br />

of the essential woman, as Linda Alcoff writes, is "not merely a social system<br />

or economic institution or a set of backward beliefs but masculinity itself and in<br />

some cases male biology"<br />

(p. 408). Cultural feminists may be more or less<br />

adversarial in approach one might contrast, for example, the gentle goddess-<br />

worship proposals of Carol Christ with the harder-hitting and sometimes hateful<br />

positions of Mary Daly or Adrienne Rich who hold (or have held) that male<br />

nature is in itself deeply defective. Despite differences in tone, what these<br />

feminists have in common is a vision of the future world deeply transformed<br />

and made true somehow by the recovery and release of the power of the femi<br />

nine (Alcoff, p. 408).<br />

Romantic feminism has been criticized by representatives of the liberal-En<br />

lightenment, Marxist, and postmodernist views for positing<br />

a female essence<br />

and a static, immutable feminine difference. The trouble with the Romantic<br />

position as they see it is that it appears to undercut political drives for equality,<br />

particularly<br />

when experience shows that "different"<br />

so often means "inferior,"<br />

or that it is intellectually naive. My own concern, however, is with the valori<br />

zation within Romantic feminism of the nonrational and the distrust this out<br />

look displays towards rationality. It is not uncommon for feminists today to<br />

address an audience which has come to share their assumption that rational<br />

thinking, including conceptual categorization, logic,<br />

and an ordered progres<br />

sion of ideas is, in its severity, its demand for precision and control, and its<br />

subordination of feeling and particularity,<br />

a masculine form of thought and is<br />

inherently domineering and destructive. Jessica Benjamin, for example, can<br />

write about "rational<br />

violence,"<br />

which she and some other feminists believe has<br />

its roots in masculine gender formation of early childhood (p. 42. Also see<br />

Gilligan). The poet Adrienne Rich expresses the Romantic feminist denuncia<br />

tion of masculine forms of thought:<br />

"His mind is too simple, 1 cannot go on sharing his<br />

nightmares<br />

(p. 156).<br />

Carol Gilligan's interesting and influential work on women's voice in ethics,<br />

In a Different Voice, regards as sufficient, and it seems, as preferable, the<br />

immediate living and the simple telling or dramatizing of one's lived expe-


304 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

rience, rather than the more arduous and often less immediately satisfying tasks<br />

of analysis and explanation.<br />

The serious shortcoming of this position, however, is that it precludes judg<br />

ment and full assessment of oneself and one's situation. What is offered instead<br />

is an immersion in an aestheticized subjectivity, a supposedly feminine subjec<br />

tivity of experience which is sometimes strikingly<br />

sentimental or self-congrat<br />

ulatory in conception, and presents, in its extreme forms, the danger of solip-<br />

sistic self-absorption which feminists feared from technical, unfeeling reason.<br />

In this model where subjective experience is primary, the means to reflect upon<br />

and question the limitations of that experience are denied. Describing and de<br />

fending the validity of one's experience becomes a substitute for inquiry into<br />

the benefits and shortcomings of one's way of experiencing. The result is that<br />

responsibility<br />

cept.<br />

for one's views and actions becomes difficult to assign and ac<br />

Another and not unrelated liability<br />

of Romantic feminism is its encourage<br />

ment of a certain set of emotional and attitudinal responses as the correct femi<br />

nist ones. There is, for one thing, self-righteousness, as one sees oneself as the<br />

superior but deeply wronged and injured party. This attitude is not only fos<br />

tered among women but becomes the posture of feminism itself as women's<br />

voice. Anger and resentment breed in this atmosphere; the tone becomes impe<br />

rious and punishing. A smug "enemy-consciousness"<br />

is generated which filters<br />

into all aspects of life. The simplistic and reductive romantic categories<br />

"woman"<br />

stands for goodness and purity, "man"<br />

stands for the envious, brutal<br />

aggressor have the effect of precluding discussion or debate. A richer or more<br />

complex understanding of women and men than the one these simplistic catego<br />

ries allow becomes impossible.<br />

Finally, there are problems in achieving the stated aims of feminism, such as<br />

social transformation, within this paradigm. Because of the priority<br />

the personal and because of its distrust of generalization,<br />

it grants to<br />

which it associates<br />

with dominating reason, there is no evident way to move effectively from sub<br />

jective experience to the politically unified activism which feminism expects.<br />

The most recent modernist alternative, embraced by a number of contempor<br />

It is re<br />

ary feminist theorists, takes the broad label "postmodern feminism."<br />

garded by some feminists as a corrective which is nevertheless still faithful to<br />

feminism's ancestry, but other feminists see it as a deep threat to the move<br />

ment. Postmodernism, I will suggest, is just the latest, decayed form modernist<br />

principles and values have taken. As such, it does not offer a solution to the<br />

problems vexing feminism since its modernist beginnings, nor does it represent<br />

a new threat. Postmodernism, emerging fairly recently from some crosscurrents<br />

in European intellectual life, refuses a single definition, but what is notable is<br />

its denial that there is any essence, any persistent identity to be found beneath


Feminist Theory and its Discontents 305<br />

appearances or even below layers of social oppression. The social construction<br />

of the self runs all the way down, according to this view, and any<br />

attempt to<br />

posit a true, stable identity or authentic subject only has the effect of solidifying<br />

the illusion of self and the subjugation that this illusion permits and perpetu<br />

ates. Not only are human subjects fully the byproduct of the forces of history<br />

and language, but reason too is seen as just one more constricting offshoot of<br />

social processes. Postmodern thinkers particularly call into serious question the<br />

conceptual structuring of rationality which depends, they claim, upon binary<br />

oppositions good and bad, self and other, reason and emotion, and so forth<br />

which always contain partially disguised value judgments and hierarchies of<br />

power (see Wilmore and Alcoff)-<br />

Male-female is, of course, one of the many items in the table of binary<br />

oppositions, and the postmodern style of thought is adopted by some feminist<br />

theorists primarily as a way of deconstructing the problems about male and<br />

female natures that propel modern feminist theory. Postmodernism is deeply<br />

anti-essentialist and skeptical, and so its approach differs fundamentally both<br />

from Enlightenment feminist theory, which preserves a notion of humanity of<br />

which women must be counted as full members,<br />

and from all varieties of Ro<br />

mantic feminism which universalize feminine traits. It also differs from nine<br />

teenth-century revolutionary politics in that it abandons expectations regarding<br />

the permanent liberation of an oppressed class. Postmodernism's insight of par<br />

ticular relevance to feminism is this: merely turning the conceptual tables by,<br />

for example, regarding feminine traits as superior rather than inferior or by<br />

wresting power away from men and giving it to women, is to agree to play by<br />

the same old binary rules. Postmodernism demands the highly radical move of<br />

dismantling entirely the categories of male, female, masculine, and feminine.<br />

Postmodernism sets itself against the oppositional strategies of the nine<br />

teenth century in an interesting manner. It looks as if the postmodern approach,<br />

in this way, might be interested in eliminating the rigidly opposed categories of<br />

oppressor and oppressed, insider and outsider, us and them. Such an aim has<br />

led feminists such as Jane Flax, Luce Irigaray, Jane Gallop, Denise Riley, and<br />

others to engage in a postmodernist analysis in their feminist work. But in<br />

reality, postmodernism is much more deeply<br />

any<br />

oppositional in its outlook than<br />

of the earlier schools of modernism. Since deconstruction involves a desta-<br />

bilization of all concepts and identities, no notions at all and no political or<br />

ethical category is permitted to stand. The postmodernist program is to expose<br />

the instability of any idea that is presented as natural, obvious, or authoritative.<br />

Feminist theory is now utterly cornered: it can neither affirm that women are<br />

something (since nothing is in any common, identifiable way), nor can it elimi<br />

nate the category of "women"<br />

(since, in that case, feminism would be meaning<br />

less). All that's left is raw opposition,<br />

the intellectual attitude evident in na<br />

scent form in early modernism's rejection of the classical tradition that has, in<br />

postmodernism, become an end in itself. Julia Kristeva, speaking<br />

position, puts the matter succinctly:<br />

from this


306 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

It follows that a feminist practice can only be negative [my emphasis |, at odds with<br />

what already exists so that we may say "that's not it"<br />

(P 137)<br />

and "that's still not<br />

This feminism that Kristeva offers subverts the self-assured positions taken<br />

by some earlier feminists, but does so only by developing one that is only and<br />

necessarily<br />

inisms came to rest somewhere in the vision of a realized communist state or<br />

negative and oppositional. But whereas the earlier oppositional fem<br />

a woman's counterculture, for example postmodernism proffers permanent<br />

instability without foundation of any kind. Postmodernism may appear to sup<br />

port the desire for a highly liberated, pluralistic feminism, one that is un<br />

bounded by the limits of earlier theory. But the desire for feminist theory to<br />

take such a formless form itself represents certain values and a certain concep<br />

tion of freedom which still fall within the compass of modernism. Unfortu<br />

nately, by this point in its modernist descent, feminist theory has no positive<br />

vision and no genuine understanding or affirmation of women to offer.<br />

Postmodernism not only fails to step beyond modernism as it sees itself<br />

doing, but is modernism in the extreme, the nadir of modernism. Postmodern-<br />

ism's fragmentation of the self is the culmination of the early modern fracturing<br />

of the self into mind and body. Postmodernism's destabilization of the world<br />

and knowledge of it is the outcome of the gradual modern erosion of substance<br />

and essence. Postmodern skepticism, which leaves one unable to sustain any<br />

level of trust in the world as one meets it, so that one must constantly create a<br />

new world, is the exaggerated fulfillment of the modern desire to have the past<br />

disappear. Postmodernism's appeal to the "play"<br />

it."<br />

of language and of power is<br />

an extreme and twisted appropriation of the emphasis placed on freedom by<br />

earlier modern thinkers. In all these respects, postmodernism seeks to make a<br />

virtue of the internal collapse of the modern outlook. But as yet one more<br />

version of modernism, postmodernism is in no position to help feminism out of<br />

its modernist difficulties.<br />

I hope to have shown the pervasiveness of a modernist sensibility of opposi<br />

tion, rebellion, crisis, and urgency, and a general distrust of reason in the<br />

ancestry of feminist theory, and to have indicated, albeit briefly, some of the<br />

shortcomings of this sensibility for developing a satisfactory theory regarding<br />

women. What would serve better than the modernist approach, in my view, is a<br />

commitment to intelligibility and stability<br />

such as is found in the classical<br />

philosophical approach. Basic to classical philosophy is an acknowledgment of<br />

the nature of things and in particular, human nature, its stable identity and<br />

ground of unification, along<br />

with an acceptance of the vulnerabilities of this<br />

nature. Only with this stability as a premise can there be a stability and truth to<br />

our speech, which in turn provides the basis for the meaningful discussion of


Feminist Theory<br />

and its Discontents 307<br />

ethical and political goods. (This argument is developed by Rosen.) Classical<br />

philosophy lacks the exigent tone of modern intellectual work; its mode is one<br />

of patient reflection on and discussion of aims prior to action and change.<br />

Unlike modern philosophy, which makes human willing and choosing primary<br />

without being able to specify<br />

what it is best to will and choose and what the<br />

limits of human choice must be, classical philosophy recognizes human nature<br />

to have certain basic capacities such as reason with natural ends and excel<br />

lences, and that the achievement of these ends is either helped or hindered by<br />

political circumstances. The intent of classical philosophizing, as I see it, is to<br />

speak about what would be the harmony<br />

of freedom and natural limitation,<br />

emotion and intelligence, equality and necessary hierarchy, desire and restraint,<br />

practice and theory, the subject and that which grounds the subject, male and<br />

female,<br />

life.4<br />

as all of these manifest themselves in human A complete theory<br />

of human nature, expanded and fully inclusive of women, would ground the<br />

commonalities of men and women in such a way as to permit differences in<br />

masculine or feminine style or position to be acknowledged without the immi<br />

nent risk of devaluing or overvaluing one or the other, and thus dislodging one<br />

or the other from the realm of the fully<br />

human. A fuller account of male and<br />

female commonalities would also subdue the antagonism between the sexes,<br />

although, due to some ineliminable differences, there inevitably are elements of<br />

tension and mystery between women and men.<br />

Women cannot afford to accept the fashionable rejection of reason as simply<br />

masculine and oppressive. Just as Freud held that the denial of the irrational led<br />

to a generalized malaise, the attempt to suppress or eliminate reason is similarly<br />

"theory"<br />

a morbid endeavor. Any which moves in this direction undermines<br />

itself, and any theory which tells women that the nonrational is their special<br />

province or exclusive obligation denies women their status as full human be<br />

ings. A reconstruction of feminist theory, away from discontent, involves reha<br />

bilitating our understanding of reason and human nature.<br />

NOTES<br />

1. For example, Diana Meyers indicates the opposing feminist viewpoints regarding the status<br />

of "the traditional woman's<br />

life,"<br />

as either an oppressive, coerced state or a freely chosen, desirable<br />

way of life. Andrea Nye (1986) points out "the self-<br />

incompatibility between materialism and<br />

assertion"<br />

in the feminist work of Simone deBeauvoir without, however, commenting on the in<br />

compatibility of these larger trends within feminist theory generally.<br />

The radical, thoroughgoing skepticism regarding reason is most evident in the "new French<br />

feminists"<br />

and those influenced by them. Elaine Marks and Isabelle de Courtivron write, "Many<br />

women who refer to themselves as radical Marguerite Duras, Christiane Rochefort, Claudine<br />

Herrmann are convinced that the will to theory is the most pernicious of male<br />

activitie<br />

(p. xi).<br />

And, "Their own analyses [Cixous, Kristeva, Clement, Irigaray, and Herrmann] 'of the status of<br />

womanhood in Western Theoretical discourse'<br />

have led them to a variety of startling conclusions,<br />

among which the most frequently shared and propagated is that only one sex has been represented,


308 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

that the projection of male libidinal economy in all patriarchal systems language, capitalism,<br />

socialism, monotheism has been total; women have been<br />

absent"<br />

(p. xii).<br />

Other feminist objections to reason are based on psychoanalysis or politics, or both.<br />

The challenge to rationality based on psychoanalytical theory has been widely adopted by femi<br />

nist theorists. The feminist interpretation of it, briefly, is that rational thinking is the outcome and<br />

reflection of masculine gender development in early childhood, i.e., the process whereby the boy<br />

distinguishes himself as "boy"<br />

and separates from the mother who is perceived as sexually differ<br />

ent. The basic feminist statements of this view are Nancy Chodorow and Dorothy Dinnerstein. This<br />

approach is applied to ethics in Carol Gilligan's In A Different Voice Psychological Theory and<br />

Women's Development. It also has been applied to the history of philosophy, notably by Susan<br />

Bordo. Without dependence on the psychoanalytic model, Genevieve Lloyd argues that the ideal of<br />

reason has been a masculine one from the beginning of the history<br />

of philosophy. Lloyd's reliance<br />

on Francis Bacon, a father of the modern intellectual era, to bring the masculine nature of reason<br />

into focus is telling in the context of the argument developed in this paper, i.e., of feminist theory's<br />

own pervasive reliance on a modernist lens.<br />

A challenge to the notion of objectivity and scientific reason is mounted on political grounds by<br />

Sandra Harding's work in feminist philosophy of science. The political criticism of rationality looks<br />

at the differing interests that knowledge serves and differing class access to knowledge, asking<br />

"whose knowledge?"<br />

Also prominent in feminist philosophy of science, Evelyn Fox Keller leans<br />

more heavily on the psychoanalytic interpretation of gender development than on political argu<br />

ments for making her case. For a critique of the attempted feminist revision of science and epis<br />

temology see Alison Wylie and the less sympathetic, "Feminist <strong>Philosophy</strong> of Science: A Critical<br />

Look,"<br />

Margaret Levin.<br />

by<br />

The feminist philosopher Iris Marion Young, invoking Theodor Adorno, offers a politically-<br />

inspired criticism of reason as unrelentingly reductive of difference, and as inherently controlling<br />

and dominating: see especially pp. 60-63.<br />

The American Philosophical Association Newsletter on Feminism and <strong>Philosophy</strong> (March 1989)<br />

takes as its topic "gender and<br />

phy on the subject.<br />

rationality"<br />

and contains several short articles as well as a bibliogra<br />

2. The contrast between the classical focus on virtue and the modern focus on needs, desires,<br />

preferences, and ultimately, effectiveness is developed by Alasdair Maclntyre. See especially Ch.<br />

5, "Plato and Rational Inquiry."<br />

3. Her argument about equality of reason and virtue is made forcefully, but frequently in the<br />

text she asserts that her proposals will make for more stable marriages; see pp. 29 and 34-35 for<br />

examples. For further discussion of Wollstonecraft see Korsmeyer, Rogers (pp. 18 1-86), and Tong<br />

(pp. 13-17).<br />

4. Catherine H. Zuckert discusses the classical philosophical approach to problems of politics<br />

and power with special attention to the situation of modernity. Her discussion closes with a call to<br />

philosophical mediation between extremes (pp. 1-29).<br />

REFERENCES<br />

Addelson, Kathryn Pyne. "Comment on Rigelheim's 'Women and the Holocaust: A<br />

Reconsideration of Research.'"<br />

Signs 12:830, 1987.<br />

Alcoff, Linda. "Cultural Feminism versus Post-structuralism: the Identity<br />

inist Theory."<br />

Signs 13:405, 1988.<br />

Crisis in Fem<br />

American Philosophical Association Newsletter on Feminism and <strong>Philosophy</strong> 88, March<br />

1989.<br />

Bartky, Sandra Lee. "Toward a Phenomenology of Feminist Consciousness."<br />

In Philos<br />

ophy and Women, ed. Sharon Bishop and Marjorie Weinzweig. Belmont, CA: Wads-<br />

worth Publishing Co., 1979.


Feminist Theory and its Discontents 309<br />

Benjamin, Jessica. "The Bonds of Love: Rational Violence and Erotic Domination."<br />

The Future of Difference, ed. Hester Eisenstein and Alice Jardine. New Brunswick,<br />

NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1987.<br />

Bordo, Susan. "The Cartesian Masculinization of Thought."<br />

Cascardi, Anthony<br />

1987.<br />

J. "Genealogies of Modernism."<br />

<strong>Philosophy</strong><br />

Signs 11:439, 1986.<br />

In<br />

and Literature 11:207,<br />

Chadwick, Ina. "A Feminist's Daughter. '<br />

New York Times, April 16, 1989.<br />

Chodorow, Nancy. The Reproduction of Mothering: Psychoanalysis and the Sociology<br />

of Gender. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978.<br />

Dinnerstein, Dorothy. The Mermaid and the Minotaur: Sexual Arrangements and Hu<br />

man Malaise. New York: Harper and Row, 1977.<br />

Donchin, Anne. "Concepts of Women in Psychoanalytic Theory."<br />

In Beyond Domina<br />

tion: New Perspectives on Women and <strong>Philosophy</strong>, ed. Carol C. Gould. Totowa, NJ:<br />

Rowman and Allanheld, 1983.<br />

"Editorial."<br />

Signs 13:399, 1988.<br />

Elshtain, Jean Bethke. Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and Political<br />

Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981.<br />

Flax, Jane. "Postmodernism and Gender Relations in Feminist Theory."<br />

Signs 12:621,<br />

1987.<br />

Fleming, Anne Taylor. "Younger Women Are Sisters, Too."<br />

New York Times Maga<br />

zine, June 19, 1988.<br />

Freud, Sigmund. Civilization and Its Discontents. Translated by<br />

York: W.W. Norton and Co., 1961.<br />

James Strachey. New<br />

Gallop, Jane. The Daughter's Seduction: Feminism and Psychoanalysis. Ithaca, NY:<br />

Cornell University Press, 1982.<br />

Gilligan, Carol. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Development.<br />

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982.<br />

Gould, Carol C. "Private Rights and Public Virtues: Women, the Family, and Democ<br />

racy."<br />

In Beyond Domination: New Perspectives on Women and <strong>Philosophy</strong>, ed.<br />

Carol C. Gould. Totowa NJ: Rowman and Allanheld, 1983.<br />

Theory."<br />

Harding, Sandra. "The Instability of the Analytical Categories of Feminist<br />

Signs 11:645, 1988.<br />

"Is Gender a Variable in Conceptions of Reality?"<br />

In Beyond Domination: New<br />

Perspectives on Women and <strong>Philosophy</strong>, ed. Carol C. Gould.<br />

1986.<br />

.. "Why<br />

The Science Question in Feminism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press,<br />

Has the Sex/Gender System Become Visible Only<br />

Now?"<br />

In Discover<br />

ing Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology and<br />

<strong>Philosophy</strong> of Science, ed. Sandra Harding<br />

Reidel Publishers, 1983.<br />

and Merrill B. Hintikka. Dordrecht: D.<br />

Hartsock, Nancy. "Feminist Theory and the Development of Revolutionary Strategy."<br />

In Women and Values, ed. Marilyn Pearsall. Belmont CA: Wadsworth Publishing<br />

Co., 1986.<br />

Irigaray, Luce. Speculum of the Other Woman. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press,<br />

1985.<br />

Jaggar, Alison M. "Human Biology in Feminist Theory: Sexual Equality Reconsidered."


310 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

In Bevond Domination: New Perspective on Women and <strong>Philosophy</strong>, cd. Carol C.<br />

Gould. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld, 1983.<br />

Jardine, Alice. Gynesis: Configurations of Women and Modernity. Ithaca, NY: Cornell<br />

University Press, 1985.<br />

Keller, Evelyn Fox. "Gender and<br />

Science."<br />

In Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspec<br />

tives in Epistemology. Metaphysics. Methodology and <strong>Philosophy</strong> of Science, ed.<br />

Sandra Harding<br />

and Merrill B. Hintikka. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing, 1983.<br />

amd Christine R. Grontkowski. "The Mind's Eye."<br />

In Discovering Reality: Fem<br />

inist Perspectives in Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology and <strong>Philosophy</strong> of<br />

Science, ed. Sandra Harding<br />

ing, 1983.<br />

and Merrill B. Hintikka. Dordecht: D. Reidel Publish<br />

Korsmeyer, Carolyn. "Reason and Morals in the Early Feminist Movement: Mary<br />

Wollstonecraft."<br />

In Women and <strong>Philosophy</strong>, ed. Carol C. Gould and Marx W. War-<br />

tofsky. New York: G.P. Putnam's Sons, 1976.<br />

Kristeva, Julia. Interview, "Woman Can Never Be Defined."<br />

In New French Femi<br />

nisms: An Anthology, ed. Elaine Marks and Isabelle de Courtivron. Amherst: Univer<br />

sity of Massachusetts Press, 1980.<br />

Lang, Berel. "Postmodernism in <strong>Philosophy</strong>: Nostalgia for the Future, Waiting for the<br />

Past."<br />

In Literature and the Question of <strong>Philosophy</strong> ,<br />

J. Cascardi. Bal<br />

timore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1987.<br />

Levin, Margaret. "Feminist <strong>Philosophy</strong><br />

per, Yeshiva University.<br />

Lloyd, Genevieve. The Man of Reason: "Male and<br />

ed. Anthony<br />

of Science: A Critical Look."<br />

Female"<br />

Unpublished pa<br />

in Western <strong>Philosophy</strong>.<br />

Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984.<br />

Maclntyre, Alasdair. Whose Justice? Which Rationality? Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame<br />

University Press, 1988.<br />

Mah, Harold. The End of <strong>Philosophy</strong> and the Origin of<br />

Crisis of the Young Hegelians. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987.<br />

Marks, Elaine, and Isabelle de Courtivron, eds. New French Feminisms: An Anthology.<br />

Amherst: University<br />

Meyers, Diana T. "Personal Autonomy<br />

Journal of <strong>Philosophy</strong> 84:619, November 1987.<br />

of Massachusetts Press, 1980.<br />

"Ideology"<br />

: Karl Marx and the<br />

and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization."<br />

Mitchell, Juliet. Women's Estate. New York: Vintage Books, 1973.<br />

Nye, Andrea. "Introduction."<br />

York: Croom Helm, 1988.<br />

In Feminist Theory and the Philosophies of Man. New<br />

"Preparing the Praxis."<br />

Way for a Feminist Hypatia 1:101, 1986.<br />

In <strong>Philosophy</strong> of Woman, ed.<br />

Reed, Evelyn. "Women: Class, Caste or Oppressed Sex?"<br />

Mary Briody Mahowald. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.. 1983.<br />

Rich, Adrienne. "August."<br />

In Diving into the Wreck. Quoted in Claire Keyes, The<br />

Aesthetics of Power: The Poetry of Adrienne Rich. Athens: University<br />

Press, 1986.<br />

Riley, Denise. "Am I That Name?"<br />

Feminism and the Category of "Women"<br />

tory. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988.<br />

of Georgia<br />

in His<br />

Rogers, Katherine M. Feminism in Eighteenth-Century England. Chicago: University of<br />

Chicago Press, 1982.<br />

Rosen, Stanley. Nihilism. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1974.<br />

"<br />

Rothenberg, Paula. "The Political Nature of Relations Between the Sexes.<br />

In Beyond


Feminist Theory and its Discontents -311<br />

Domination: New Perspectives on Women and <strong>Philosophy</strong>, ed. Carol C. Gould.<br />

Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld, 1983.<br />

"Introduction."<br />

<strong>Philosophy</strong> and Law: Essays Toward the Understanding of<br />

Maimonides and His Predecessors. New York: Jewish Publication Society, 1987.<br />

Strauss, Leo.<br />

Thurman, Judith. "Reader I Married Him."<br />

"A Critic At Large"<br />

Review of Rebecca<br />

Fraser, The Brontes: Charlotte Bronte and Her Family. The New Yorker, March 20,<br />

1989,<br />

pp. 109-14.<br />

Tong, Rosemarie. Feminist Thought: A Comprehensive Introduction. Boulder, CO:<br />

Westview Press, 1989.<br />

Wilmore, S.J. "Skepticism and Deconstruction."<br />

Man and World 20:437, 1987.<br />

Wollstonecraft, Mary. A Vindication of the Rights of Woman. Edited by<br />

Poston. New York: W.W. Norton and Co., 1975.<br />

Carol H.<br />

Wylie, Alison. "The <strong>Philosophy</strong> of Ambivalence: Sandra Harding on The Science Ques<br />

tion in Feminism."<br />

In Science, Morality & Feminist Theory, ed. Marsha Hanen and<br />

Kai Neilsen. Canadian Journal of <strong>Philosophy</strong>, 1987 (Supplement), pp. 59-73.<br />

Young. Iris Marion. "Impartiality<br />

Critiques of Moral and Political Theory."<br />

In Feminism as Critique: On the Politics of<br />

and the Civic Public: Some Implications of Feminist<br />

Gender, ed. Seyla Benhabib and Drucilla Cornwell. Minneapolis: University of Min<br />

nesota Press, 1987.<br />

Yack, Bernard. The Longing for Total Revolution: Philosophic Sources of Social Dis<br />

contentfrom Rousseau to Marx and Nietzsche. Princeton: Princeton University Press,<br />

1986.<br />

Zuckert. Catherine H. "On the Role of Spiritedness in Politics."<br />

In Understanding the<br />

Political Spirit: Philosophical Investigations from Socrates to Nietzsche, ed. Cath<br />

erine H. Zuckert. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1988.


Discussion<br />

Reply<br />

to Lowenthal<br />

Christopher A.Colomo<br />

Rosary College<br />

In his comment on my recent article in <strong>Interpretation</strong>, David Lowenthal<br />

argues that I contradict myself. The alleged contradiction is between my asser<br />

tion that God is the absolutely other and the biblical account, wherein God is<br />

the provider-judge, the God whose goodness men trust. I contradict myself,<br />

according to Lowenthal, because I try to combine the absolutely other and the<br />

provider-judge, the biblical God, in one account of God.<br />

I admit to being puzzled provider-<br />

by the assumption that I treat God as the<br />

judge (a phrase I never used). I would have thought that my remark about<br />

sinners in the hands of an angry God indicates only that imagination can ob<br />

scure one's reason [<strong>Interpretation</strong> 18 (1990): 149]. I believe I am perfectly<br />

imagination. If<br />

candid in confessing that I would not want to be misled by my<br />

my reference to an angry God is the only<br />

support for the claim that I treat God<br />

as the provider-judge, then I regret misleading my reader, but think myself<br />

absolved of the contradiction in question.<br />

Since the provider-judge cannot be simply hidden, perhaps Lowenthal char<br />

acterized God as the provider-judge in order to explain why I speak of God as<br />

revealed. In any case, if God is revealed, then He cannot be the absolutely<br />

other. What is absolutely other cannot be revealed, since in the instant that it is<br />

revealed it ceases to be simply or completely other. According to Lowenthal, I<br />

contradict myself by treating God as both revealed and absolutely<br />

readily<br />

other. I<br />

agree that an account of God that ascribed to Him both these charac<br />

teristics would in this respect be self-contradictory. But this is a contradiction I<br />

point out (ibid. p. 148 bottom), not one I fall into.<br />

Perhaps Lowenthal's main point is that the contradiction between provider-<br />

judge and absolutely other whether or not I see it as a contradiction is one<br />

of my own making. More specifically, he claims that this contradiction is not<br />

traceable to the Bible. He writes that I leave the biblical view of God "far<br />

behind"<br />

when I treat God as the absolutely other. He recognizes that by calling<br />

God the absolutely other, I refer to God's utter mysteriousness or unintel-<br />

interpretation, Winter 1990-1991, Vol. 18, No. 2


314 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

ligibility. The claim that I leave the Bible "far behind"<br />

is based on the view that<br />

the biblical God is not mysterious and unintelligible. (So far as I can see,<br />

Lowenthal does not attempt to show that I am wrong about the Christian God,<br />

who is three in one, very God and very man.)<br />

Something is amiss here because in his review of Strauss's book, Lowenthal<br />

writes that the Bible extends God's mystery "'as far as<br />

possible.<br />

He recognizes<br />

that the biblical God of power and mystery is in tension with the God of love<br />

and justice (the provider-judge of his comment), since the moral concerns of<br />

the latter must be intelligible to man. Indeed, he calls this tension "a fundamen<br />

tal psychological difficulty<br />

within the Bible as a<br />

whole"<br />

[<strong>Interpretation</strong>, 13<br />

(1985): 317].The contradiction Lowenthal reads into my position is the contra<br />

diction that he himself sees in the Bible as a whole.<br />

Perhaps a "fundamental difficulty"<br />

is not a contradiction. In his comment.<br />

Lowenthal suggests that in the Bible "God's ways are indeed mysterious, but<br />

this does not mean He Himself is inherently and totally<br />

mysterio<br />

The prin<br />

ciple of contradiction is here brought into play in order to say that God is<br />

mysterious in one way but not in another. But is it persuasive to claim that<br />

God's ways, His actions in history, are mysterious and miraculous, but that He<br />

Himself is knowable (consider Exodus 33: 20 and Hebrews 11: 1)? Maimonides<br />

interprets the Bible in just the reverse sense, suggesting that God's ways can be<br />

known but not His essence (Guide I 54). The insistence that God's essence<br />

cannot be known seems to me necessary if God is to be perfect yet one and of<br />

infinite power. That these characteristics belong to God seems to me to be a<br />

reasonable interpretation of what the Bible says. On the assumption that God's<br />

essence is unknowable, Maimonides goes on to say that "One must likewise of<br />

necessity deny, with reference to Him, His being similar to thing"<br />

any existing<br />

(Guide I 55, Pines tr.). By implication God does not even exist in the same<br />

Lowenthal in his comment<br />

way that other existing things do (an equivocality<br />

appears to reject). This radical dissimilarity to any existing thing is what I tried<br />

other."<br />

to capture in the phrase "absolutely<br />

Lowenthal and I see the same contradiction between the claim to be re<br />

vealed, just, and loving and the claim to be hidden, unseen, or mysterious. We<br />

disagree in so far as he is certain that an argument is refuted if one finds a<br />

contradiction in it. I am not sure that this is the case with respect to a truly<br />

fundamental argument or position. When Socrates claims to know that he<br />

knows nothing, he contradicts himself to the extent that he must know what<br />

knowing<br />

is. But does this paradox refute him?<br />

A self-contradictory statement could be defended only if reality itself some<br />

how contained a contradiction. If "reality"<br />

is the world we see and touch, then<br />

Plato seems to have thought that reality to be so obviously self-contradictory as<br />

to justify him in positing another reality, the "ideas,"<br />

which, we are told, are<br />

not self-contradictory (though to many readers they no doubt seem to be one of<br />

the most self-contradictory things in Plato). While Plato's surface teaching in


Reply<br />

to Lowenthal -315<br />

itself proves nothing, it does raise the question how we would prove that the<br />

reality of the every day world is not self-contradictory. Could we use the prin<br />

ciple of contradiction in our argument? Or would the use of this principle to<br />

prove that reality conforms to the principle be an instance of circular and,<br />

hence, invalid reasoning? (Nowhere does Lowenthal address the detailed argu<br />

ment I make about the contradictory nature of reality on pages 149-50 of my<br />

article.)<br />

From Maimonides and Aquinas to Kierkegaard and Bultmann, believers<br />

who are aware of philosophy have stressed the mysterious aspect of God in<br />

order to clearly differentiate between faith and philosophic knowledge. No<br />

doubt, in so doing, they expose just the kind of fundamental difficulty Low<br />

enthal discusses (e.g., S. Th. I, q.4, a.3, reply 4). In so far as they continue to<br />

believe, they<br />

whether the believing<br />

continue to live with or in contradiction. It is another question<br />

mind is the one that can best understand and accept this<br />

situation or whether the believer is not at bottom always seeking release into<br />

the clear either/or of Kierkegaard's choice. Lowenthal, at least, seems to think<br />

that it is the philosopher who must resolve contradiction; a man who would be<br />

rational "must go one way or the<br />

other."<br />

Perhaps so, yet I puzzle over the<br />

seemingly contrary view expressed by Leo Strauss in his reply<br />

Tyranny (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988), p. 210|.<br />

to Kojeve [On<br />

<strong>Philosophy</strong> as such is nothing but genuine awareness of the problems. It is<br />

impossible to think about these problems without becoming inclined toward a<br />

solution. Yet as long as there is no wisdom but only quest for wisdom, the<br />

evidence of all solutions is necessarily smaller than the evidence of the problems.<br />

Therefore the philosopher ceases to be a philosopher at the moment at which the<br />

"subjective<br />

certainty"<br />

of a solution becomes stronger than his awareness of the<br />

problematic character of that solution. At that moment the sectarian is born.


Book Review<br />

Public-<br />

Charles Sherover, Time, Freedom, and the Common Good: An Essay in<br />

<strong>Philosophy</strong>. (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1989). xiii +314<br />

pp.; cloth $59.50, paper $19.50<br />

Maureen Feder-Marcus<br />

State University of New York<br />

Old Westbury<br />

Contemporary political life, marked by conflicting claims to entitlement,<br />

requires clear normative principles for evaluating these claims. Yet few con<br />

temporary<br />

philosophers outside the province of the Left have advanced a sys<br />

tematically worked out, comprehensive view of our social being rigorous<br />

enough to function as an ontological framework for making such evaluations.<br />

Professor Sherover goes far in accomplishing this. Time, Freedom, and the<br />

Common Good is a carefully conceived and tightly argued work and may well<br />

be foundational for current political debates.<br />

Drawing from the phenomenological and pragmatic traditions, Sherover pre<br />

sents an "authentic descriptive<br />

tered on what he calls the "three principles of<br />

understanding<br />

of our actual social being cen<br />

polity,"<br />

i.e., the existential cate<br />

gories of our actual social life. This descriptive task comprises the first section<br />

of the book. The second part sets out some of the normative criteria which flow<br />

from these categories, and a last section, "The Discipline of Freedom,"<br />

up specific issues in contemporary public policy, including<br />

takes<br />

an agenda to be<br />

discharged and an appropriate method to be used for evaluating social programs<br />

if we are genuinely to pursue a common good.<br />

Sherover puts forth three categories which he takes to be constitutive of our<br />

social being: membership, temporality,<br />

and freedom. These are derived in sev<br />

eral ways: as a thoughtful appropriation from our political heritage as grounded<br />

in the Greeks, through a phenomenological, i.e., rigorously descriptive, ap<br />

proach to ordinary experience, and dialectically as a transcendental analysis of<br />

those structures grounding the very possibility of social being itself. Thus the<br />

book founds the notion of membership, for example, on an Aristotelian concep<br />

tion of the polis and the primacy of the social, on the notion of individual<br />

identity as requiring linguistic community and social membership, and on a<br />

Roycean notion of self-consciousness as an emergent from the social whole. In<br />

each case, these multiple perspectives are mutually reinforcing and add up to a<br />

carefully<br />

elaborated notion of our social being.<br />

interpretation. Winter 1990-1991, Vol. 18, No. 2


318- <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Assuming<br />

for the moment that these categories are both comprehensive and<br />

exhaustive, they provide the basis for inferring a clear set of normative guide<br />

lines for deciding questions of power, organization, and procedure in a free<br />

society. Sherover's reasoning moves here from the existential notion of mem<br />

bership to the political one of citizenship, from temporality<br />

to the power to<br />

control time, i.e., governance, and from freedom to the activities flowing from<br />

it, primary among these being<br />

livelihood. His discussion of the first of these<br />

political concepts, citizenship, is, in fact, very rich, entailing a whole series of<br />

substantive conclusions about equality and rights which can be used as a mea<br />

sure for weighing the legitimacy of various contemporary<br />

Sherover argues for a Burkean notion of "prescriptive<br />

Thomas Hill Green, reminding<br />

political claims.<br />

rights,"<br />

as emended by<br />

the reader that there is a tradition of positive<br />

rights, i.e., those enabling protections which provide the means by<br />

society takes its members as citizens,<br />

which a<br />

within the conservative tradition which<br />

stands between the Lockean notion of abstract natural rights and the centraliza<br />

tion of power marking the paternalistic state.<br />

Given the second of his three principles of polity, Sherover is able to infer<br />

the legitimacy and necessity<br />

of republican government as it developed from<br />

Machiavelli and Montesquieu through The Federalist. Since time, conceived<br />

both ontically as a fact of experience and transcendental ly as the ground for the<br />

construction of all meaningful experience, is a constitutive element of our so<br />

cial being, the best government is one which allows the greatest openness toward<br />

the future and the greatest control of time to its citizens. Given a realistic<br />

conception of power, the pluralization of centers of power is the best way to<br />

secure and protect such openness and what Madison called the diverse "faculties<br />

of<br />

men."<br />

Indeed, our form of pluralism which checks even the possibility of<br />

legislative dominance through which a majority can move to complete power,<br />

becomes virtually a moral imperative for political life.<br />

Finally, the three principles of polity generate a defense of a commercial<br />

economy functioning by<br />

means of the free market but one in which government<br />

can interfere as the "guarantor of the general interest"<br />

along<br />

the lines conceived<br />

by Hamilton. The efficacy of the dispersion of property within the framework<br />

of capitalism provides the empirical verification for Sherover's conceptual<br />

view, reinforcing the notion of the primacy of pluralism already<br />

chapter on governance.<br />

made in the<br />

Given the assumption that the three principles of polity are sufficient for<br />

characterizing our social being, Sherover's arguments in the second section of<br />

his book are tight and well founded. It may be that these do not, by themselves,<br />

account for man's full socialness, however. If no other, the notion of social<br />

labor might have to be considered labor seen not simply as an area left over<br />

for individual pursuit once social life is constituted but labor as essentially<br />

constitutive of our social being itself.<br />

The fact that labor is conceptualized as a residual and individual activity


Book Review 3 1 9<br />

takes its toll on the book's overall argument. For in the course of his work,<br />

Sherover refers on a number of occasions to the fact that his analysis must<br />

"faithfully"<br />

speak to our actual social experience, including the actual kinds of<br />

personal lives that an organized society permits and encourages. I would have<br />

expected the book to undertake such a concrete analysis at some point, if in no<br />

other place, in the section on "Livelihood."<br />

not, I think, "faithfully"<br />

Unfortunately<br />

this chapter does<br />

speak to our actual experience. Rather it veers off in<br />

the direction of abstract exhortations to free enterprise. As a result, Sherover's<br />

argument remains most compelling when the threat to freedom is posited in its<br />

starkest terms, namely a planned society with a centralized monopoly of power<br />

and authority. Sherover's initial categories allow this discrimination very well.<br />

However, they may be inadequate for catching<br />

the more subtle but nonetheless<br />

serious deformations of freedom arising from, among other places, the free<br />

market itself. It would be essential then to offer or at least to refer to a physiog<br />

nomy of the contemporary soul, for the concrete historical instantiation of Sher<br />

over's categories is, itself, the measure of just how well we really are nourish<br />

ing<br />

the life of freedom and the notion of a common good.<br />

It is precisely because Sherover eschews the tradition of atomistic liberalism<br />

and takes the notion of the common good as central, that some more concrete<br />

analysis of the structures which form and support it is warranted. He seems to<br />

speak as if these structures are self-developing: "A free economic order has,<br />

indeed, increasingly provided the material basis for moral or virtuous behavior<br />

and for a social commitment to individual happiness consonant with responsible<br />

social life"<br />

(p. 220). And in a footnote in his chapter on livelihood, he as<br />

sumes, with Michael Novak, that we can take as a given a moral-cultural sys<br />

tem to restrain and check the economic system without noting how the market<br />

can erode the valuational systems counted on for its restraint.<br />

Even if we assume the more optomistic picture, a society of individuals with<br />

decent, even actively sympathetic impulses, we still must address the question<br />

of how these individual affects can be formed into a public will to discharge the<br />

political agenda Sherover sets out. Thus there seems to be an omission in his<br />

analysis, even if we assume that the structures of consciousness and our affec<br />

tive life are such that there is a substratum of feeling or virtue to be mobilized.<br />

Certainly<br />

the issue becomes even more problematic if we take to heart Allan<br />

Bloom's description of contemporary interiority, its insularity and trivialization<br />

of feelings and ideas, summed up in his telling phrase, "the dreariness of the<br />

family's spiritual<br />

landscape."<br />

contemporary<br />

A similar point is raised by James Miller. Commenting on Arendt's On<br />

Revolution, Miller notes:<br />

For might not contentment with civil liberties, which protect the private pursuit of<br />

happiness, slacken the thirst for public freedom? Might not the very perfection of<br />

the governmental mechanism breed apathy, and create the conditions for a retreat


320 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

into those insular concerns that have become the image of<br />

"happiness"<br />

in America?<br />

Have not the generous circumstances attending the American experiment actually<br />

helped generate a fatal vacillation between an active commitment to freedom and<br />

the passive enjoyment of prosperity? Has not America become the perfect<br />

model of a two-party plutocracy where (and directly quoting from Arendt) "public<br />

happiness and public freedom have become the privilege of the few"?1<br />

And from Arendt herself:<br />

It was precisely because of the enormous weight of the Constitution and of the<br />

experiences in founding a new body<br />

politic, that the failure to incorporate the<br />

townships and the town-hall meetings, the original springs of all political activity in<br />

the country, amounted to a death sentence for them. Paradoxical as it may sound, it<br />

was under the impact of the Revolution that the revolutionary spirit in this country<br />

began to wither away, and it was the Constitution itself, this greatest achievement<br />

of the American people, which eventually cheated them of their proudest<br />

possession.2<br />

Certainly<br />

an analogous point can be made about the common good. Political<br />

life, in its highest sense, requires acting within the human community, an act,<br />

as Arendt points out, of self-revelation requiring courage and faith. Yet even if<br />

we take a less heroic and more modest view of politics as the institutionaliza<br />

tion of procedures for persuasion and mutual accomodation, the structures of<br />

individual consciousness and social life must exist to make these possible as<br />

well. What institutions, organs, rituals, even public spaces are necessary for<br />

forming<br />

a public will dedicated to freedom and the common good? To assume<br />

that these structures exist and to lay out a political philosophy accordingly, may<br />

not be sufficient. Rather, the question may be how to theorize the proper or<br />

gans of will formation consonant with a free society. It is all the more timely<br />

for believers in individual freedom to do this,<br />

question from the Left has been so resoundingly defeated.<br />

since the attempt to answer this<br />

1. James Miller, "The Pathos of Novelty: Hannah Arendt's Image of Freedom in the Modem<br />

World,"<br />

in Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of The Public World, ed. Melvyn Hill (New York: St.<br />

Martin's Press, 1979), p. 195.<br />

2. On Revolution (New York: The Viking Press, 1965), as quoted in Miller, p. 201.


INTERPRETATION<br />

A JOURNAL OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY<br />

Queens College, Flushing, NY 11367-0904 U.S.A. (718) 520-7099<br />

Subscription rates per volume (3 issues): individuals $21<br />

libraries and all other institutions $34<br />

students (five-year limit) $12<br />

Postage outside U.S.: Canada $3.50 extra; elsewhere $4 extra by surface mail<br />

(8 weeks or longer) or $7.50 by air.<br />

Payments: in U.S. dollars and payable by the U.S. Postal Service or a financial<br />

institution located within the U.S.<br />

Please print or type<br />

ORDER FORM FOR NEW SUBSCRIBERS<br />

(NOT FOR RENEWALS CURRENT SUBSCRIBERS WILL BE BILLED)<br />

I wish to subscribe to INTERPRETATION.<br />

? bill me name ? student<br />

D payment enclosed address<br />

? airmail country (if outside U.S.) .<br />

GIFT SUBSCRIPTION ORDER FORM<br />

Please enter a subscription to INTERPRETATION for<br />

address .<br />

? airmail country (if outside U.S.;<br />

C bill me from: name<br />

D payment enclosed address<br />

ZIP/postcode<br />

ZIP/postcode .<br />

ZIP/postcode .<br />

? student<br />

INTERPRETATION will send an announcement to the recipient and acknowledgment to you<br />

RECOMMENDATION TO YOUR LIBRARY<br />

to: the'<br />

Librarian,<br />

I recommend that our library subscribe to INTERPRETATION, A journal of<br />

political philosophy [ISSN 0020-9635], at the institutional rate of $34 per year<br />

(three issues).<br />

signature<br />

name<br />

date position .<br />

INTERPRETATION, Queens College, Flushing, New York 11367-0904, U.S.A.


Forthcoming<br />

Thomas Hobbes Appendix (1668) to Latin edition of Leviathan-trans\ .<br />

,<br />

Discussion<br />

introd., and notes by<br />

Michael Piatt Souls Without Longing<br />

Discussion<br />

J. Jackson Barlow<br />

Timothy Fuller<br />

George Wright<br />

George Anastaplo, The Constitution of 1787


ISSN 0020-9635 <strong>Interpretation</strong>, Inc.<br />

Flushing<br />

"0<br />

n<br />

3<br />

2<br />

o<br />

r<br />

ft;<br />

3<br />

o<br />

ft;<br />

M ~V<br />

C<br />

n<br />

13<br />

O 73 333<br />

ft:<br />

ITQ<br />

Queens College<br />

N.Y. 11367-0904<br />

03<br />

C<br />

r<br />

z<br />

o<br />

3<br />

fi-<br />

H o<br />

o > O m CfQ<br />

U.S.A.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!