Free Will, Moral Responsibility, and Reformed Theology - Analytic ...

Free Will, Moral Responsibility, and Reformed Theology - Analytic ... Free Will, Moral Responsibility, and Reformed Theology - Analytic ...

analytictheologye4c5.files.wordpress.com
from analytictheologye4c5.files.wordpress.com More from this publisher
06.04.2013 Views

26 Paul L. Manata © 2011 to carry it out. And he will not change it.” Now, the “execution of the plan may require means or be dependent on certain conditions, but then these means or conditions have also been determined in the decree.” And again, “the decree includes whatsoever comes to pass in the world, whether it be in the physical or in the moral realm, whether it be good or evil.” 35 These statements are representative and could be easily multiplied. They explicate the Reformed understanding of God’s decree, providence, and knowledge. Given the above, we can generalize from this to a particular, arbitrary example. Consider Bob. Bob eats Lucky Charms for cereal on some particular rainy morning. We know that God decreed this to happen (“all things”) and that Bob cannot eat grape-­‐nuts if God has decreed he will eat Lucky Charms (“unchangeable”), and that the ultimate source of Bob’s action was the decree of God (“after the counsel of his will,” “from all eternity”). 36 However, the decree is free on God’s part 37 and he just as easily could have decreed that Bob eat grape-­‐ nuts, from which it would follow that Bob certainly would eat grape-­‐nuts—it must occur given the decree. So, what Bob does is not absolutely necessary, it is contingent upon the divine decree. This explication has certain implications for free will; pretty clearly, what we have here is a kind of determinism. 3.3 A kind of determinism? What is determinism? According to Richard Taylor, “Determinism is the general 35 Louis Berkhof, Systematic Theology (Eerdmans, 1996), pp. 100-­‐105. 36 Thomas Boston writes, “Whoever may be the instruments of any good to us, of whatever sort, we must look above them, and see the hand and counsel of God in it, which is their first source,” “Important Lessons Drawn from the Decrees of God,” ibid. fn. 30. 37 I bypass the issue of God’s freedom in this paper. I do think it is a sui-­‐generis (completely unique) type of freedom. This topic is ripe for philosophical research and I leave the detailed and complicated questions to the side.

27 Paul L. Manata © 2011 philosophical thesis which states that for everything that ever happens there are conditions such that, given them, nothing else could happen.” 38 Robert Kane elaborates, In more familiar terms, we say that a determined event is inevitable or necessary (it cannot but occur), given the determining conditions. If fate decreed or God foreordained (or the laws of nature or antecedent causes determined) that John would choose at a certain time to go to Samarra, then John will choose at that time to go to Samarra. Determinism is thus a kind of necessity, but it is a conditional necessity. A determined event does not have to occur, no matter what else happens (it need not be absolutely necessary). But it must occur when the determining conditions have occurred. If the decrees of [God] had been different or the past had been different in some way, John may have been determined to go to Damascus rather than to Samarra. Historical doctrines of determinism imply that every event, or at least every human choice and action, is determined by some determining conditions in this sense. 39 On this understanding of determinism conjoined with RT, it becomes easy to see why almost everyone who has thought deeply about these matters—Reformed and non-­‐Reformed—has called Reformed theology a species of determinism. But what about Reformed theologians who have claimed Reformed theology is not deterministic, like those cited in 1.2.1? I suggest that those Reformed theologians who have said that Reformed theology is not deterministic can be understood, then, to be operating with some special sense of determinism: perhaps occasionalism, naturalistic causal determinism, absolute necessitation or logical 38 Richard Taylor, “Determinism,” in Paul Edwards ed. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, v.2 (Macmillan, 1972), p. 359. 39 Robert Kane, A Contemporary Introduction to Free Will (Oxford University Press, 2005), p. 6, emphasis original.

26<br />

Paul L. Manata © 2011<br />

to carry it out. And he will not change it.” Now, the “execution of the plan may<br />

require means or be dependent on certain conditions, but then these means or<br />

conditions have also been determined in the decree.” And again, “the decree<br />

includes whatsoever comes to pass in the world, whether it be in the physical or<br />

in the moral realm, whether it be good or evil.” 35<br />

These statements are representative <strong>and</strong> could be easily multiplied. They<br />

explicate the <strong>Reformed</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing of God’s decree, providence, <strong>and</strong><br />

knowledge. Given the above, we can generalize from this to a particular, arbitrary<br />

example. Consider Bob. Bob eats Lucky Charms for cereal on some particular<br />

rainy morning. We know that God decreed this to happen (“all things”) <strong>and</strong> that<br />

Bob cannot eat grape-­‐nuts if God has decreed he will eat Lucky Charms<br />

(“unchangeable”), <strong>and</strong> that the ultimate source of Bob’s action was the decree of<br />

God (“after the counsel of his will,” “from all eternity”). 36 However, the decree is<br />

free on God’s part 37 <strong>and</strong> he just as easily could have decreed that Bob eat grape-­‐<br />

nuts, from which it would follow that Bob certainly would eat grape-­‐nuts—it<br />

must occur given the decree. So, what Bob does is not absolutely necessary, it is<br />

contingent upon the divine decree. This explication has certain implications for<br />

free will; pretty clearly, what we have here is a kind of determinism.<br />

3.3 A kind of determinism?<br />

What is determinism? According to Richard Taylor, “Determinism is the general<br />

35 Louis Berkhof, Systematic <strong>Theology</strong> (Eerdmans, 1996), pp. 100-­‐105.<br />

36 Thomas Boston writes, “Whoever may be the instruments of any good to us, of<br />

whatever sort, we must look above them, <strong>and</strong> see the h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> counsel of God in it,<br />

which is their first source,” “Important Lessons Drawn from the Decrees of God,” ibid.<br />

fn. 30.<br />

37 I bypass the issue of God’s freedom in this paper. I do think it is a sui-­‐generis<br />

(completely unique) type of freedom. This topic is ripe for philosophical research<br />

<strong>and</strong> I leave the detailed <strong>and</strong> complicated questions to the side.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!