28.03.2013 Views

Joaquim da Silva Fontes, Significação e Estabilidade do Género no ...

Joaquim da Silva Fontes, Significação e Estabilidade do Género no ...

Joaquim da Silva Fontes, Significação e Estabilidade do Género no ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

postulated as the “<strong>do</strong>ctrine of signs” under the name of semeiotiké, or when, in 1764,<br />

Johann H. Lambert wrote a specific treaty called Semiotik. The term, deriving from the<br />

Greek word semeîon (sign) and sema (signal), gave rise to various others, like semeiotica<br />

or semology. The classical period was particularly fervent in terms of philosophical debates<br />

round the issues of the nature of representation. From Platonic Realism (regarding the<br />

existence of universals, i.e. the belief that forms and abstractions such as “humanity” and<br />

“truth” exist regardless of human perception in sensory terms), to Aristotelian Realism (the<br />

view that universals exist simply as types or properties and away from objects of the<br />

external world) the main belief has been that the world is as we perceive it, almost in the<br />

reductive “seeing is believing” sense. This obviously had been the subject of debate (as is<br />

the concept of “real” for that matter), as early as when John Locke stressed this idea in his<br />

Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690) when he referred to semeiotiké, as “the<br />

business whereof is to consider the nature of signs the mind makes use of for the<br />

understanding of things, or conveying its k<strong>no</strong>wledge to others” (in Deely 1994:109).<br />

It is relevant to say that Peirce states that “we think only in signs” (ibid.) as they<br />

can come with the appearance of words or sounds, images, objects, o<strong>do</strong>urs, etc. Peirce,<br />

however, also <strong>no</strong>tes that “<strong>no</strong>thing is a sign unless it is interpreted as a sign”. Therefore, a<br />

sign may be almost anything provided that we decide to attribute a certain meaning to it or<br />

understand it as signifying something, and usually representing something other than itself.<br />

Different systems of conventions are all unconsciously related to the manner we interpret<br />

signs. It is this consequential use of signs which is at the core of the concerns of semiotics.<br />

Before Saussure, the study of language had been mainly diachronic, that is, directed<br />

at its changing forms across history; Saussure distinguishes his area of concern as<br />

synchronic, how a language works at a given moment as a rule-governed system. To <strong>do</strong><br />

this he introduces a “dyatic”, two further distinctions, between langue (the system of a<br />

particular language allowing someone to generate a meaningful sentence, according to<br />

rules for word-formation and sentence structure) and parole (what a person utters, their<br />

writing or speech), between signifier (significant, the form which the sign takes) and<br />

signified (signifié, the thing or concept it represents). On challenging this commonsense<br />

<strong>no</strong>tion of “words”, Saussure reactivated the distinction between signifier and signified.<br />

Their relationship is referred to as “signification” and when the two are joined together<br />

they form a sign.<br />

253

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!