23.03.2013 Views

Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? - Tom G. Palmer

Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? - Tom G. Palmer

Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? - Tom G. Palmer

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

No. 8] <strong>Are</strong> <strong>Patents</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Copyrights</strong> <strong>Morally</strong>Jus4fied? 821<br />

each of these arguments’ internal structures <strong>and</strong> then attempt<br />

to apply them to ideal objects. In part II, I will takeup the labor<br />

theory of property, <strong>and</strong> in part III, the personality theory. In<br />

part IV, I will address utilitarian concerns, but, as I have stated,<br />

only briefly. Inpart V, I will discuss the attempt to derive intellectual<br />

property rights indirectly, that is, “piggy-backing” on<br />

rights to tangible property. The concluding sections ofthe Article,<br />

parts VI <strong>and</strong> VII, present my own case for a private property<br />

system that does not recognize copyrights <strong>and</strong> patents. 8<br />

I make no claims to an exhaustive taxonomy of property<br />

rights theories. Other important theories ofproperty<strong>and</strong> other<br />

theoretical concerns are not dealt with here, because I have<br />

chosen to concentrate on those most relevant to the problem of<br />

intellectual property. Further, I will have little to say about the<br />

actual historical genesis of intellectual property; while intellectual<br />

property originated in grants of monopoly from the state<br />

<strong>and</strong> received its legitimacy from that source, the,public debate<br />

over its legitimacy shifted radically in the late Eighteenth Century.<br />

As Fritz Machiup <strong>and</strong> Edith Penrose note, “those who<br />

started using the word property in connection with inventions<br />

had a very definite purpose in mind: they wanted to substitute a<br />

wordwith a respectable connotation, ‘property,’ for a word that<br />

had an unpleasant ring, ‘privilege.’ “~ Given this shift in the<br />

popular conception ofpatents <strong>and</strong> copyrights, I intend to question<br />

whether they are legitimate forms ofproperty at all.<br />

II. LABOR AND THE NATURAL RIGHT TO PROPERTY<br />

Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner was surely one of the most remarkable<br />

American men of letters of the Nineteenth Century. He was a<br />

constitutional scholar, a fervent crusader for the abolition of<br />

slavery, an entrepreneur who succeeded through competition<br />

in forcing the American postal service to lower its rates, a philosopher,<br />

a writer on economic matters, <strong>and</strong> more,<br />

Spooner begins his book, The Law ofIntellectual Property: orAn<br />

Essay on the Right ofAuthors <strong>and</strong> Inventors to a Perpetual Property in<br />

T/zeirldea.s,’°by establishing the status of immaterial objects as<br />

8. As will be demonstrated, however, the approachI set forth would include trademarks<br />

<strong>and</strong> tradesecrets as legitimate. Trademarks <strong>and</strong> trade secrets have roots in the<br />

common law<strong>and</strong> enjoy acontractual or quasi-contractual moral grounding.<br />

9. Machlup & Penrose, The Patent Controversy in the Mneteenth Century, 10 J. ECON.<br />

HIs~r.I, 16 (1950).<br />

10. Spooner, The Law of Intellectual Property: or An Essay on the Right of Authors <strong>and</strong> In-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!