23.03.2013 Views

Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? - Tom G. Palmer

Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? - Tom G. Palmer

Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? - Tom G. Palmer

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

No. ~S] <strong>Are</strong> <strong>Patents</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Copyrights</strong> <strong>Morally</strong>Jvst!fied? S49<br />

as necessary to the realization of freedom reduce, then, to the<br />

argument of Wilhelm von Humboldt, which, as noted above,’ 24<br />

is another version of the principal argument of John Locke.<br />

And this liberty-based argument, in its primary implications, is<br />

hostile rather than friendly to intellectual property claims, for<br />

such claims represent liberty-restrictions on others in ways that<br />

tangible property rights do not.<br />

As to the droite de suite, or inalienable resale royalty right, the<br />

economic consequences of this notion havebeen explored elsewhere.’<br />

25 It should suffice to point out that this resale royalty<br />

right benefits some established artists by awarding them<br />

unearned windfall profits, while others suffer by having their<br />

freedom to negotiate over the schedule.ofpayments coercively<br />

abridged. The prospect of having to part with a share of the<br />

appreciation of a work is capitalized into the sale price, meaning<br />

that the money received at the point of sale by the artist will<br />

be less.’ 26 In addition, like inalienable personal rights over art<br />

works, such “rights” reduce the moral agency of artists by restricting<br />

their rights to make contracts with others. The terms<br />

of the contract are fixed by others, <strong>and</strong> the contracting parties<br />

are constrained from freely transferring their property by<br />

contract.<br />

IV. THE BASIC STRUCTURE OF UTILITARIAN ARGUMENTS AND<br />

INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS<br />

As noted earlier, utilitarian arguments of a certain class can<br />

cut for or against intellectual property rights claims. As dealt<br />

with in much of the economics literature, for example, ‘the utility<br />

gains from increased incentives for innovation must be<br />

weighed against the utility losses incurred from monopolization<br />

of innovations <strong>and</strong> their diminished diffusion, Some have<br />

argued that the first part of the comparison may be either nega-<br />

matter; as I havenotedelsewhere, however, purelyutilitarian claims on behalfof intellectualproperty<br />

rights are shaky, at best. See <strong>Palmer</strong>, supra note 7.<br />

124. See supra notes 69-77 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

125. See, e.g., Rottenberg, The Remuneration ofArtists, in FRONTIERS OF ECONOMICS 47-<br />

51 (K. Arrow & S. Honkapohja eds. 1985); Bolch, Damon, & Hinshaw, An Economic<br />

Analysis of the California Art Royalty Statute, 10 C0NN. L. REV. 689 (1978).<br />

126. Those who prefer paymentnow to payment later, such as the many artists who<br />

sell their work “on the street,” are harmed by such a requirement. As Ben W. Bolch<br />

remarks: “Many artists, ‘starving’or not, want their money now, not tomorrow. Otherwise,<br />

they would ‘invest’ in theart by keeping it for themselves.” Bolch, There Is NoJust<br />

Price For Art, N.Y. Times, Nov. 28, 1987, at 23, col. 4.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!