Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? - Tom G. Palmer

Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? - Tom G. Palmer Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? - Tom G. Palmer

tomgpalmer.com
from tomgpalmer.com More from this publisher
23.03.2013 Views

ARE PATENTS AND COPYRIGHTS MORALLY JUSTIFIED? THE PHILOSOPHY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS AND IDEAL OBJECTS TOM G. PALMER* I. INTRODUCTION Arguments for the right ofproperty ownership are manifold. It is quite common for a single author to invoke a wide range of these arguments to support private property rights, as in John Locke’s famous chapter on property in his Second Treatise ofGovernnzent. Indeed, the convergence of varying and non-contradicting arguments on the same conclusion tends to make us more confident of that conclusion. It serves as a kind of “failsafe” device in intellectual discourse: If five different but all plausible arguments lead to the same conclusion, we are generally morejustified in accepting that conclusion than if only one of those arguments supported it. 1 Intellectual property, however, is a different matter. Interestingly, the various leading arguments that normally buttress each other and converge in support ofprivate property diverge widely when applied to the concept of intellectual property. For example, a theory wherein property is viewed as the just reward for labor (a “desert theory”) might very well support intellectual property rights, while at the same time a theory in which property is defined as the concretion of liberty might not. Most ofthe arguments discussed in this Article, both for and against intellectual property rights, emanate from staunch defenders of a private property, free market system. This is not surprising, because those who strongly favor liberty and property are apt to see the concepts a~intimately connected, and are thus more likely to be very concerned with the theory and application of property rights. With respect to intellectual property, however, one should not be surprised if they come to * Directorof Student Affairs and DirectorofEasternEuropean Outreach Program, Institute for Humane Studies, George Mason University. B.A.. St. John’s College, 1982; Ph.D. candidate, Catholic Universityof America, 1990. 1. See Barnett, ForeworS’ Of Chickens and Eggs—The Compatibility of Moral Rights and Consequenhialist Analyses, 12 H*iiv. J.L. & PUB. Pot.’v 611, 616-17 (1989).

• 818 HarvardJournal of Law & Public Policy [Vol. 13 differing conclusions. This occurs because liberty and property in this context may be irreconcilable; copyrights and patents seem to be property, but theyalso seem to restrict liberty. One would be hard-pressed, for example, to find two stronger defenders ofliberty and property in Nineteenth Century America than the abolitionist Lysander Spooner. and the Jacksonian editorialist William Leggett. Yet on the subject ofintellectual property rights, they each came to opposite conclusions: Spooner steadfastly championed intellectual property rights while Leggett advocated with equal force the unrestricted exchange of ideas. Although they came to opposite conclusions, each argued that his beliefs were consistent with his overall stance in favor of liberty, private property, and freedom of trade. 2 Sometimes the best developed arguments in support ofintellectual property rights are advanced by relatively marginal authors, like Spooner for example. This is because the great pioneers of the philosophy of property rights wrote before property rights for authors or inventors had become a popular issue; it remained for lesser figures to mold the arguments for intellectual property based on the property theories that had been developed earlier by more prominent thinkers. Consequently, while Locke, Hume, Kant, Hegel, and other philosophers will figure significantly in this Article, attention will also be devoted to later interpreters, who applied the ideas ofthese and other great philosophers in new ways. Intellectual property rights are rights in ideal objects, which are distinguished from the material substrata in which they are instantiated. 3 Much of this Article will therefore be concerned with the ontology of ideal objects. This is because the subject of intellectual property, indeed, the very idea of exercising property rights over ideas, processes, poems, and the like, 2. See, e.g., Spooner, A Letter to Scientists and inventors, on the Science offustice, and Their Right of Perpetual Property in Their Discoveries and Inventions, in 3 THE COLLECTED WORKS OF LYSANDER SPOONER 68 (C. Shively ed. 1971); W. LEOOETF, DEMOCRATICK EDITORS- AL5: ESSAYS IN JACKSONIAN POLITICAL ECONOMY 397-98 (L. White ed. 1984). 3. This catch-all category covers the subject matter of patents and copyrights, including those for algorithms, computer programs, manufacturing processes, inventions, musical or literaryworks, pictorial or other kinds of representations, sculptures, designs, and more. The relevant difference between such goods and tangible goods is that the former can be instantiated an indefinite number oftimes, that is, they arenot scarce in a staticsense, whiletangible goods arespatially circumscribed andare scarce in both the staticand the dynamic sense of the term.

ARE PATENTS AND COPYRIGHTS<br />

MORALLY JUSTIFIED?<br />

THE PHILOSOPHY OF PROPERTY<br />

RIGHTS AND IDEAL OBJECTS<br />

TOM G. PALMER*<br />

I. INTRODUCTION<br />

Arguments for the right ofproperty ownership are manifold.<br />

It is quite common for a single author to invoke a wide range of<br />

these arguments to support private property rights, as in John<br />

Locke’s famous chapter on property in his Second Treatise ofGovernnzent.<br />

Indeed, the convergence of varying <strong>and</strong> non-contradicting<br />

arguments on the same conclusion tends to make us<br />

more confident of that conclusion. It serves as a kind of “failsafe”<br />

device in intellectual discourse: If five different but all<br />

plausible arguments lead to the same conclusion, we are generally<br />

morejustified in accepting that conclusion than if only one<br />

of those arguments supported it. 1<br />

Intellectual property, however, is a different matter. Interestingly,<br />

the various leading arguments that normally buttress<br />

each other <strong>and</strong> converge in support ofprivate property diverge<br />

widely when applied to the concept of intellectual property.<br />

For example, a theory wherein property is viewed as the just<br />

reward for labor (a “desert theory”) might very well support<br />

intellectual property rights, while at the same time a theory in<br />

which property is defined as the concretion of liberty might<br />

not.<br />

Most ofthe arguments discussed in this Article, both for <strong>and</strong><br />

against intellectual property rights, emanate from staunch defenders<br />

of a private property, free market system. This is not<br />

surprising, because those who strongly favor liberty <strong>and</strong> property<br />

are apt to see the concepts a~intimately connected, <strong>and</strong><br />

are thus more likely to be very concerned with the theory <strong>and</strong><br />

application of property rights. With respect to intellectual<br />

property, however, one should not be surprised if they come to<br />

* Directorof Student Affairs <strong>and</strong> DirectorofEasternEuropean Outreach Program,<br />

Institute for Humane Studies, George Mason University. B.A.. St. John’s College,<br />

1982; Ph.D. c<strong>and</strong>idate, Catholic Universityof America, 1990.<br />

1. See Barnett, ForeworS’ Of Chickens <strong>and</strong> Eggs—The Compatibility of Moral Rights <strong>and</strong><br />

Consequenhialist Analyses, 12 H*iiv. J.L. & PUB. Pot.’v 611, 616-17 (1989).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!