21.03.2013 Views

Ideological (Mis)Use of Human Rights - David Chandler

Ideological (Mis)Use of Human Rights - David Chandler

Ideological (Mis)Use of Human Rights - David Chandler

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

124 D. CHANDLER<br />

as an ethical challenge to law (IICK, 2000). To some<br />

commentators, using ethical arguments <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights to undermine UN Charter law against war was<br />

dangerous or an ‘abuse’ <strong>of</strong> ethics; for others, as outlined<br />

with respect <strong>of</strong> Habermas, this, on the contrary, was a<br />

valuable ‘use’ <strong>of</strong> ethics.<br />

However, the rights <strong>of</strong> the ‘human’ (<strong>of</strong> ‘human security’<br />

or <strong>of</strong> human rights) that are enforced are not the<br />

rights <strong>of</strong> legally constituted subjects, they are not the<br />

rights <strong>of</strong> states, the subjects <strong>of</strong> international law. As<br />

the rights being enforced are not those <strong>of</strong> legal subjects,<br />

the content and enforcement <strong>of</strong> human rights is dependent<br />

on the ad hoc agency <strong>of</strong> states willing to shoulder<br />

the burden <strong>of</strong> paying for and participating in intervention.<br />

Th e ad hoc nature <strong>of</strong> human rights enforcement<br />

means that the ethico-juridical undermining <strong>of</strong> UN<br />

Charter law cannot take a universal form, but is inevitably<br />

dependent on a case-by-case approach, with the<br />

decision making dictated more by the interests and concerns<br />

<strong>of</strong> the powerful than the needs <strong>of</strong> the powerless.<br />

a For some critics, such as Danilo Zolo (2002), it is the<br />

global hegemon, the United States, that is empowered<br />

by more informal and ad hoc decision making, but for<br />

others, such as Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, it<br />

is global neoliberal capitalism itself, taking the postnational<br />

form <strong>of</strong> Empire (Hardt and Negri, 2001).<br />

Whether the case <strong>of</strong> Kosovo, where human rights<br />

were held to trump sovereignty and international law<br />

(HRW, 1999), is understood as a positive step toward a<br />

more universal order or as a reactionary step toward a<br />

more hierarchical order may be a matter <strong>of</strong> normative<br />

choice. What is beyond dispute is that the existing legal<br />

order was challenged and undermined by states powerful<br />

enough to take the decision to wage war against the<br />

Serbian state. Th e US and most <strong>of</strong> the European powers,<br />

which backed the war, unilaterally decided to wage war<br />

outside the legal restrictions <strong>of</strong> the UN Charter order.<br />

In doing this they claimed that they were waging war<br />

on behalf <strong>of</strong> the rights <strong>of</strong> the Kosovo Albanians. But<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> human rights claims is that, while Kosovo<br />

Albanians were the subjects <strong>of</strong> these rights, the active<br />

agents in enforcing them were the NATO powers, who<br />

in doing so accrued or claimed the right to wage war<br />

independently <strong>of</strong> the UN.<br />

Today, human rights, the rule <strong>of</strong> law, and good<br />

governance provide the key framework <strong>of</strong> international<br />

institutional policy practices. However, when it<br />

comes to the international sphere, the lack <strong>of</strong> mechanisms<br />

to generate global consensus, the increased<br />

power inequalities, and the limited safeguards make<br />

any attempts to institutionalize human rights regimes<br />

outside the mutual agreement <strong>of</strong> sovereign states much<br />

more problematic. Th e problem with constituting<br />

frameworks <strong>of</strong> sanction, intervention, and war on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> non-socially constituted legal subjects is that<br />

it leaves wide open the problem, raised by Schmitt,<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘who decides?’ (Schmitt, 1996, 2003). Whether the<br />

intention is to (mis)use human rights ideologically or<br />

to genuinely do good in the world, the outcome is the<br />

same: ultimately, greater decision-making power and<br />

authority accrue to the states (or some would argue<br />

the USA as the sole remaining great power) that have<br />

the capacity to take on the responsibilities <strong>of</strong> deciding<br />

and enforcing.<br />

KEY POINTS<br />

The human rights-based approach has facilitated<br />

humanitarian aid being denied in some circumstances<br />

and in support for more militarized humanitarianism—for<br />

example, the NATO war over Kosovo.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights approaches appeared to directly challenge<br />

sovereignty in the 1990s, but in the 2000s have sought to<br />

redefi ne sovereignty as being compatible with international<br />

human rights protections. Central to this shift has been the<br />

ICISS report ‘The Responsibility to Protect’ (ICISS, 2001).<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights approaches tend to redefi ne war fought in<br />

the post-colonial world as a matter <strong>of</strong> human rights crimes<br />

and human rights victims; they also tend to redefi ne war<br />

fought by Western powers, seeing intervention in the cause<br />

<strong>of</strong> human rights as more akin to police action than war<br />

making.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights approaches have facilitated a more fl exible<br />

and positive framework for military intervention, shifting<br />

away from UN Charter approaches that saw war as the<br />

‘scourge <strong>of</strong> humanity’.<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 124 12/9/08 3:06:00 PM

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!