21.03.2013 Views

Ideological (Mis)Use of Human Rights - David Chandler

Ideological (Mis)Use of Human Rights - David Chandler

Ideological (Mis)Use of Human Rights - David Chandler

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Ideological</strong> (<strong>Mis</strong>)<strong>Use</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong><br />

<strong>David</strong> <strong>Chandler</strong><br />

Chapter Contents<br />

Introduction 114<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and the Legal Subject 115<br />

The Rise <strong>of</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> 117<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and International Intervention 119<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and the Search for Meaning 125<br />

Conclusion 127<br />

Reader’s Guide<br />

This chapter seeks to explain why human rights claims, which assert the need to<br />

empower the poor and excluded, <strong>of</strong>ten appear to enforce the power <strong>of</strong> dominant<br />

Western states and international institutions. It will demonstrate that there is a paradox<br />

at the heart <strong>of</strong> the human rights discourse, which enables claims made on behalf<br />

<strong>of</strong> the victims, marginalized, and excluded to become a mechanism for the creation<br />

<strong>of</strong> new frameworks for the exercise <strong>of</strong> power. It will suggest that, rather than understanding<br />

human rights frameworks in the international sphere as a challenge to power<br />

relations, it would be more accurate to describe them in terms <strong>of</strong> a challenge to the<br />

existing formal international legal order. It will clarify that there is nothing progressive or<br />

empowering about human rights claims in themselves and that, if the enforcement and<br />

protection <strong>of</strong> these claims relies on external and unaccountable actors, then existing<br />

informal hierarchies <strong>of</strong> power will become increasingly formalized, while formal protections<br />

<strong>of</strong> the rights <strong>of</strong> self-determination and self-government will be undermined.<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 113 12/9/08 3:05:51 PM


114 D. CHANDLER<br />

Introduction<br />

Many commentators have observed the fact that<br />

human rights frameworks have become an integral<br />

part <strong>of</strong> a new, more hierarchical, international order,<br />

undermining UN Charter restrictions on the use <strong>of</strong><br />

military force and justifying new, more coercive forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> international regulation and intervention in the<br />

post-colonial world. To view these consequences <strong>of</strong><br />

human rights claims and discourses as the ideological<br />

‘misuse’ or ‘abuse’ <strong>of</strong> human rights would already be to<br />

approach the question <strong>of</strong> understanding human rights<br />

with a certain set <strong>of</strong> assumptions. Th ese assumptions<br />

would be based upon an idea that human rights claims<br />

necessarily challenge entrenched power relations and<br />

are an important mechanism <strong>of</strong> advocacy on behalf <strong>of</strong><br />

the victims <strong>of</strong> abuses or those excluded from traditional<br />

frameworks <strong>of</strong> representation. Th is chapter will suggest<br />

that these prior assumptions, <strong>of</strong> the ‘purity’ <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights claims and <strong>of</strong> their ‘abuse’ by powerful actors, are<br />

themselves problematic.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights claims can not in themselves be<br />

accurately seen as either enforcing or challenging the<br />

existing relations <strong>of</strong> power. Th e one thing that can be<br />

asserted with confi dence is that human rights claims<br />

confl ate an ethical or moral claim with a legal and political<br />

one. Th e discourse <strong>of</strong> the ‘human’ belongs to the<br />

sphere <strong>of</strong> abstract universal ethics, while that <strong>of</strong> ‘rights’<br />

belongs to the framework <strong>of</strong> a concretely constituted<br />

legal and political sphere. In confl ating the two spheres,<br />

human rights claims pose a challenge to rights as they<br />

are legally constituted. Th e content <strong>of</strong> this challenge,<br />

whether it has any consequences, and, if it does have<br />

consequences what these consequences are, are matters<br />

for concrete analysis. To suggest that any challenge to<br />

the framework <strong>of</strong> legally constituted rights is necessarily<br />

an eff ective one, or necessarily a good or progressive<br />

one, would clearly be naive.<br />

In fact, it was the challenge <strong>of</strong> naivety that was<br />

famously articulated by Jeremy Bentham, the utilitarian<br />

philosopher, when he denounced the idea <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights as ‘nonsense on stilts’ (see Chapter 1). He had<br />

nothing but contempt for the new-fangled universal<br />

‘rights <strong>of</strong> man’ proclaimed at the end <strong>of</strong> the eighteenth<br />

century. For Bentham, rights meant nothing unless they<br />

were enforceable with clear contractual obligations and<br />

backed by law. Declarations <strong>of</strong> the ‘rights <strong>of</strong> man’ were<br />

no more than rhetorical fancies and collections <strong>of</strong> pious<br />

wishes that were not worth the paper they were written<br />

on. Th e idea that we were born with universal equal<br />

rights simply because we were human made no sense<br />

to Bentham. Firstly, we are born into a relationship <strong>of</strong><br />

dependency rather than equality, and are not considered<br />

as moral or legal equals until we reach maturity<br />

(children are not born with criminal liability as they<br />

are not responsible for their actions). Secondly, it was<br />

clear that there could be no universal human equality:<br />

the opportunities we have depend fundamentally on<br />

the societies we live in and our position within those<br />

societies.<br />

However, few people would have the confi dence to<br />

argue in Bentham’s dismissive terms today. It would<br />

appear to be undeniable that our understandings <strong>of</strong><br />

and respect for human rights are central to the way we<br />

and our governments make policy and act in international<br />

aff airs. Yet, despite today’s consensus on the fact<br />

that ‘human rights are a good thing’, there is still the<br />

nagging sense that Bentham may have a point, that<br />

human rights may sound very nice on paper but be<br />

much more ephemeral when it comes to giving these<br />

aspirations meaning and content, and that, nice as these<br />

claims sound, they may be open to abuse.<br />

Claims to anything can be abused and all claims to<br />

rights can be misused. However, it is vital to appreciate<br />

that it is inherent within human rights claims that<br />

they are more open to abuse or misuse than other<br />

claims, those <strong>of</strong> democratic and civil rights for example.<br />

Th e reason for this, in the words <strong>of</strong> Norman Lewis, is<br />

quite simply because human rights are not derived from<br />

‘socially constituted legal subjects’ (Lewis, 1998, p. 85).<br />

Where Bentham saw abstract rights claims as merely<br />

childish or superstitious thinking, much as the ‘belief<br />

in witches or unicorns’; their abstract nature—the fact<br />

that they can refl ect radical and progressive aspirations<br />

rather than merely legally enshrined rights—is held to be<br />

a major factor in their use and support across the globe.<br />

Th is chapter is tasked with focusing on the downside<br />

<strong>of</strong> human rights claims—what is commonly understood<br />

by advocates <strong>of</strong> human rights to be the ‘misuse’ or<br />

‘abuse’ <strong>of</strong> human rights. It will be demonstrated that the<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 114 12/9/08 3:05:54 PM


ambiguous and abstract nature <strong>of</strong> human rights claims<br />

is at the same time their point <strong>of</strong> attraction but equally<br />

makes the opportunity for ‘abuse’ a constant one. Unfor-<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and the Legal Subject<br />

Th e discourse <strong>of</strong> human rights has a pre-history in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> the claims <strong>of</strong> natural rights from the Enlightenment<br />

onwards where claims <strong>of</strong> a universal human nature<br />

were an essentialist grounding for ideas <strong>of</strong> individual<br />

equality and self-determination, which challenged the<br />

aristocratic and feudal social and political hierarchies<br />

(see Box 7.1). Natural rights claims are therefore seen<br />

at the centre <strong>of</strong> the revolutionary movements <strong>of</strong> liberal<br />

modernity: the Declaration <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Rights</strong> <strong>of</strong> Man and<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Citizen <strong>of</strong> the French Revolution and the Declaration<br />

<strong>of</strong> Independence and the Bill <strong>of</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> <strong>of</strong> the<br />

American Revolution.<br />

With the development <strong>of</strong> more social and historical<br />

frameworks <strong>of</strong> thinking, expounded by theorists<br />

such as Emile Durkheim, Max Weber, and Karl Marx,<br />

the idea <strong>of</strong> natural rights was discredited (see Chapter<br />

6). In its place was a consensus <strong>of</strong> understanding that<br />

rights were social and political products, dependent<br />

Box 7.1 Sophocles’ Antigone: Ethics vs Law<br />

The conception <strong>of</strong> human rights can be dated back to<br />

ancient Greece and the work <strong>of</strong> the famous playwright<br />

Sophocles. To quote the US State Department pamphlet,<br />

‘<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and US Foreign Policy’, published in 1978:<br />

The idea <strong>of</strong> human rights is almost as old as its<br />

ancient enemy, despotism. . . . When Sophocles’<br />

heroine Antigone cries out to the autocratic King<br />

Creus: ‘all your strength is weakness itself against [t]he<br />

immortal unrecorded laws <strong>of</strong> God’ she makes a deeply<br />

revolutionary assertion. There are laws, she claims, higher<br />

than the laws made by any King; as an individual she<br />

has certain rights under those higher laws; and kings and<br />

armies—while they may violate her rights by force—can<br />

never cancel them or take them away. (Cited in Sellars,<br />

2002, p. vii.)<br />

This is an excellent example <strong>of</strong> the essence <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights claims: legal rights are equated with power and<br />

oppression and challenged in the name <strong>of</strong> a non-legally<br />

constituted rights subject.<br />

IDEOLOGICAL (MIS)USE OF HUMAN RIGHTS 115<br />

tunately, for the advocates <strong>of</strong> human rights frameworks,<br />

their openness to abuse is not incidental but is intrinsic<br />

to the concept <strong>of</strong> human rights themselves.<br />

on the state and society in which the individual lived.<br />

Concrete rights <strong>of</strong> citizenship replaced the abstract<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> natural rights.<br />

Twentieth-Century Critiques<br />

For the leading political theorists <strong>of</strong> the twentieth<br />

century, the idea <strong>of</strong> human rights as universal claims<br />

made no more sense than it did to Jeremy Bentham.<br />

Writing in 1950, in the aft ermath <strong>of</strong> the Second World<br />

War, Hannah Arendt remarked that the Holocaust<br />

demonstrated the abstract and meaningless nature <strong>of</strong><br />

the concept <strong>of</strong> human rights (see Box 7.2). Where Jews<br />

were denied the rights <strong>of</strong> citizenship—their political<br />

status—they were forced to fall back on the abstract<br />

claims <strong>of</strong> human rights. In doing so, their status was<br />

transformed from active decision-making political subjects<br />

to objects <strong>of</strong> the charity or benevolence <strong>of</strong> others.<br />

For Arendt, what makes us human and rights-bearing<br />

subjects is not our bare humanity but our capacity to<br />

create rights-bearing and rights-giving political communities.<br />

Th e lesson <strong>of</strong> the Holocaust, for the Jews, was<br />

not the need to give more attention to human rights,<br />

but the need to ensure the political rights <strong>of</strong> citizenship,<br />

achieved through the struggle to establish and safeguard<br />

the state <strong>of</strong> Israel.<br />

Arendt makes the point here that human rights are<br />

‘fi ctional’ rights: they are rights that are not dependent<br />

on the collective agency <strong>of</strong> their subject (<strong>Chandler</strong>,<br />

2003). Individuals ‘freed’ from the political process <strong>of</strong><br />

collective decision making no longer have an active<br />

say in what their rights are or should be; at most they<br />

are lobbying or begging others for favours and place<br />

themselves in a situation <strong>of</strong> dependency. For Arendt,<br />

the rights <strong>of</strong> the ‘human’ are much less than the rights<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ‘citizen’. Th e bearer <strong>of</strong> merely ‘human’ rights is<br />

subordinate, dependent, and in a position <strong>of</strong> supplicant<br />

to others. Th e response to these rights claims is there-<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 115 12/9/08 3:05:55 PM


116 D. CHANDLER<br />

Box 7.2 Hannah Arendt and Carl Schmitt on<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong><br />

Hannah Arendt on <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong><br />

. . . the public sphere is as consistently based on the law<br />

<strong>of</strong> equality as the private sphere is based on the law<br />

<strong>of</strong> universal difference and differentiation. Equality, in<br />

contrast to all that is involved in mere existence, is not<br />

given us, but is the result <strong>of</strong> human organization ins<strong>of</strong>ar<br />

as it is guided by the principle <strong>of</strong> justice. We are not born<br />

equal; we become equal as members <strong>of</strong> a group on the<br />

strength <strong>of</strong> our decision to guarantee ourselves mutually<br />

equal rights. (Arendt, 1973, p. 301.)<br />

Carl Schmitt on <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong><br />

<strong>Human</strong>ity as such cannot wage war because it has no<br />

enemy, at least not on this planet. . . . When a state<br />

fi ghts its political enemy in the name <strong>of</strong> humanity, it is<br />

not a war for the sake <strong>of</strong> humanity, but a war wherein a<br />

particular state seeks to usurp a universal concept against<br />

a military opponent. . . . The concept <strong>of</strong> humanity is an<br />

especially useful ideological instrument <strong>of</strong> imperialist<br />

expansion, and in its ethical-humanitarian form it is<br />

a specifi c vehicle <strong>of</strong> economic imperialism. Here one<br />

is reminded <strong>of</strong> a somewhat modifi ed expression <strong>of</strong><br />

Proudhon’s: whoever invokes humanity wants to<br />

cheat. To confi scate the word humanity, to invoke<br />

and monopolize such a term probably has certain<br />

incalculable effects, such as denying the enemy the<br />

quality <strong>of</strong> being human and declaring him to be an<br />

outlaw <strong>of</strong> humanity; and a war can thereby be driven to<br />

the most extreme inhumanity. (Schmitt, 1996, p. 54.)<br />

fore an arbitrary one. Arendt argues that it may result<br />

in ‘privileges in some cases, injustices in most’ because<br />

‘blessings and doom are meted out to them [bearers <strong>of</strong><br />

human rights] according to accident and without any<br />

relation whatsoever to what they do, did, or may do.’<br />

(Arendt, 1973, p. 296.)<br />

For Arendt, human rights frameworks, in separating<br />

the rights bearer from the agent capable <strong>of</strong> enacting<br />

these rights, legitimize a framework that is in fact worse<br />

than that suggested by Bentham’s view <strong>of</strong> pious wishes<br />

and utopian dreaming. Arendt suggests that a fi eld <strong>of</strong><br />

fi ctitious ‘rights’ is opened up that is inherently open to<br />

abuse and arbitrary interpretation and enforcement.<br />

Carl Schmitt, a German legal and political theorist,<br />

writing at the same time as Arendt, was also critical <strong>of</strong><br />

the idea <strong>of</strong> universal human rights. Schmitt approached<br />

the subject from the opposite end <strong>of</strong> the spectrum (not<br />

from the viewpoint <strong>of</strong> the human rights subject—the<br />

individual claiming human rights—but that <strong>of</strong> the external<br />

actor deemed to be responsible for enforcing human<br />

rights). He argued that claiming to intervene militarily<br />

on behalf <strong>of</strong> universal human rights was an act <strong>of</strong> power<br />

rather than principle, stating famously that ‘whoever<br />

invokes humanity wants to cheat’ (see Box 7.2).<br />

Schmitt makes similar points to Arendt in arguing<br />

that the concepts <strong>of</strong> ‘humanity’ and <strong>of</strong> ‘human rights’<br />

are empty abstractions, i.e. that they do not correspond<br />

to any political reality <strong>of</strong> constituted rights and duties.<br />

Schmitt argues that the concept <strong>of</strong> human rights may<br />

well have had a useful polemical appeal at the end <strong>of</strong><br />

the eighteenth century as a rallying cry against the then<br />

existing aristocratic feudal system and the inequalities<br />

and privileges associated with it. However, this did<br />

not mean that the era <strong>of</strong> universal human rights had<br />

arrived. Th e fact that the world is divided into diff erent<br />

and distinct political societies or states means that universal<br />

rights-bearing individuals do not exist. If they<br />

did exist then we would have a universal government,<br />

giving political and legal form to those universal rights<br />

(Schmitt, 1996, p. 55).<br />

For Schmitt, in the absence <strong>of</strong> a unifi ed world government<br />

that could constitute the universal human being as<br />

a rights-bearing subject in reality, human rights claims<br />

will have no clear court <strong>of</strong> adjudication or mechanism<br />

<strong>of</strong> enforcement. Schmitt argued that humanitarian<br />

action could be unproblematic if it was based on<br />

inter-state agreement and administered through a nonpolitical<br />

body, such as the International Committee <strong>of</strong><br />

the Red Cross (ICRC). His point was that if abstract<br />

human rights claims were set against the agreed constituted<br />

rights framework then they threatened confl ict<br />

and instability. Th is was because the subject <strong>of</strong> these<br />

claims was separate from the agency enforcing them.<br />

Th e enforcement <strong>of</strong> claims <strong>of</strong> non-socially constituted<br />

legal subjects is necessarily an arbitrary one, decided<br />

by questions <strong>of</strong> power rather than principle. Schmitt<br />

feared that universal claims to judge the needs or interests<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘humanity’ were not just illegitimate acts <strong>of</strong><br />

power rather than law per se, but that they were also<br />

dangerous and destabilizing in a politically divided<br />

world (Schmitt, 1996, pp. 53–58).<br />

The Paradox <strong>of</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong><br />

Th e points made by Hannah Arendt and Carl Schmitt<br />

get to the heart <strong>of</strong> the paradox <strong>of</strong> human rights. Th eir<br />

capacity for challenging power as well as for being<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 116 12/9/08 3:05:55 PM


mechanisms <strong>of</strong> the exercise <strong>of</strong> power (unrestrained by<br />

law) stem from the fact that human rights claims are<br />

made on behalf <strong>of</strong> non-legally constituted subjects.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights claims may refl ect the immanent revolutionary<br />

overthrow <strong>of</strong> the established order or they<br />

may refl ect the oppressive use <strong>of</strong> governing power to<br />

rule beyond the limits <strong>of</strong> the law. <strong>Human</strong> rights claims,<br />

by separating the holder <strong>of</strong> rights from the agency <strong>of</strong><br />

enforcement <strong>of</strong> these claims, refl ect merely the challenge<br />

to the legal order. Without a consideration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

context in which a discourse <strong>of</strong> human rights arises,<br />

it is impossible to make a normative judgement as to<br />

whether this challenge to the legal order <strong>of</strong> constituted<br />

rights is something to be supported or opposed.<br />

The Rise <strong>of</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong><br />

Natural rights, in terms <strong>of</strong> human rights, were revived<br />

in the sphere <strong>of</strong> international politics only during the<br />

Second World War. Th e modern government-led<br />

human rights movement could be seen to have been<br />

born during the War, with US President Franklin D.<br />

Roosevelt’s famous ‘Four Freedoms’ speech <strong>of</strong> 1941 or<br />

H. G. Wells’s publication Th e <strong>Rights</strong> <strong>of</strong> Man, or, what are<br />

we fi ghting for? <strong>of</strong> 1940. Th e defence <strong>of</strong> ‘essential liberties<br />

and freedoms’ helped to cohere the Allied War eff ort<br />

against Germany and Japan, but it is important not to<br />

confuse the declaration <strong>of</strong> abstract universal values with<br />

the intention (or capability) <strong>of</strong> enforcing a framework<br />

<strong>of</strong> universal rights in the international sphere.<br />

Th e gap between human rights as abstract rhetoric<br />

and as legally constituted and enforceable rights<br />

is illustrated well by the Universal Declaration <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> (UDHR) agreed by the United Nations<br />

General Assembly (UNGA) in December 1948. Th ere<br />

was agreement on thirty human rights expressed as<br />

a set <strong>of</strong> abstract moral claims or aspirations; these<br />

rights were abstracted from political questions <strong>of</strong> concrete<br />

societies’ priorities and concerns and therefore<br />

could be signed up to by states with market- or stateregulated<br />

economic systems. Th ere could be common<br />

agreement precisely because the UN did not claim to<br />

be describing rights that were universally recognized in<br />

every state, nor did it attempt to enact or enforce these<br />

rights in a legal form.<br />

KEY POINTS<br />

IDEOLOGICAL (MIS)USE OF HUMAN RIGHTS 117<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights claims confl ate ethical and legal claims<br />

because the subject <strong>of</strong> rights is not a socially constituted<br />

legal subject.<br />

For this reason, human rights claims challenge the existing<br />

legal framework (whether it is authoritarian or democratic).<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights claims express a capacity gap—where the<br />

rights holder is held to lack the capability <strong>of</strong> acting on<br />

their own behalf—therefore an external agent is held to be<br />

required to enforce these rights. The dependency on an<br />

unaccountable external actor therefore makes enforcement<br />

indeterminate and contingent upon the relations (and<br />

interests) <strong>of</strong> power.<br />

The Post-War Order<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights frameworks can therefore be read back<br />

into the formative legal and political moments <strong>of</strong> the<br />

post-War international order. However, if we were to<br />

read this focus on universal human rights as a either a<br />

challenge to sovereignty or a challenge to the dominant<br />

framework <strong>of</strong> international order, we would be reading<br />

history backwards from the vantage point <strong>of</strong> today. It is<br />

important to appreciate that the Nuremberg tribunal,<br />

the UDHR, and even the 1949 Genocide Convention<br />

were seen as enforcing the framework <strong>of</strong> equal sovereign<br />

rights and the principle <strong>of</strong> non-intervention.<br />

Th e post-War order was constituted by the establishment<br />

<strong>of</strong> sovereign states as the only rights-bearing<br />

subjects <strong>of</strong> international law (see Chapter 2). Th is was<br />

made explicitly clear in the great power deliberations<br />

and international conferences in preparation <strong>of</strong> the UN<br />

Charter. Th ere was no contradiction between state sovereignty<br />

and human rights (between the rights <strong>of</strong> states<br />

and the rights <strong>of</strong> individuals) because the international<br />

order did not recognize individuals as legal subjects.<br />

Th erefore, as US Secretary <strong>of</strong> State Edward R. Stettinius<br />

stated, the legal situation was clear: ‘Th e provisions<br />

proposed in the Charter will not, <strong>of</strong> course, ensure by<br />

themselves the realization <strong>of</strong> human rights and fundamental<br />

freedoms for all the people. Th e provisions are<br />

not made enforceable by any international machinery.<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 117 12/9/08 3:05:56 PM


118 D. CHANDLER<br />

Th e responsibility rests with the member governments<br />

to carry them out.’ (Cited in Lewis, 1998, p. 88.)<br />

Secondly, natural rights were brought into international<br />

relations through the Nuremberg tribunal. Many<br />

human rights advocates argue today that the trial marked<br />

a fundamental legal break in the undermining <strong>of</strong> the<br />

rights <strong>of</strong> sovereign state authorities. Th is claim makes<br />

little sense, as with Germany’s unconditional surrender<br />

in 1945, the Allied states who organized the military<br />

tribunal at Nuremberg did this explicitly as occupying<br />

powers with sovereign authority rather than as a supranational<br />

authority (see Laughland, 2007, pp. 53–68).<br />

Where the tribunal broke new legal ground was in using<br />

natural law to overrule positivist law, to argue that the<br />

laws in force at the time in Germany were no defence<br />

against the retrospective crime <strong>of</strong> ‘waging an aggressive<br />

war’. Th is was justifi ed on the grounds that certain<br />

acts were held to be such heinous crimes that they were<br />

banned by universal principles <strong>of</strong> humanity (Douzinas,<br />

2007, pp. 21–22). <strong>Human</strong> rights frameworks were used<br />

to undermine positivist law, to cast the winners <strong>of</strong> the<br />

War as moral, not merely military, victors.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights frameworks emerged during and at<br />

the close <strong>of</strong> the Second World War in an attempt to give<br />

moral legitimacy both to the Allies’ actions during the<br />

War and to the post-War international order. While<br />

today the UDHR and the Nuremberg tribunal are<br />

understood to have raised a challenge to the rights <strong>of</strong><br />

state sovereignty, this was not the case at the time. Th e<br />

preparatory discussions for the UN Declaration and<br />

the deliberations <strong>of</strong> the Nuremberg judges both made it<br />

absolutely clear that the sovereign state was the subject<br />

<strong>of</strong> international law and that sovereignty was not challenged<br />

by any trans-national legal authority. States were<br />

held to be the upholders and enforcers <strong>of</strong> both the<br />

moral and political order.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and the Cold War<br />

Th e habit <strong>of</strong> reading the rise <strong>of</strong> human rights consciousness<br />

back to 1945 as a story <strong>of</strong> the teleological march<br />

<strong>of</strong> universal ethics and values is one that unfortunately<br />

underplays the radical shift in the importance <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights aft er the end <strong>of</strong> the Cold War. Th e strong consensus<br />

today that universal human rights are a guide to<br />

international policy making is, in fact, a relatively recent<br />

development. For the fi rst twenty years aft er the Second<br />

World War, one <strong>of</strong> the major journals on international<br />

relations, Foreign Aff airs, did not carry one article on<br />

human rights (Korey, 1999, p. 151). During the bulk <strong>of</strong><br />

the Cold War era there was little concern with the implications<br />

<strong>of</strong> the UDHR on state policy or practice. Until<br />

the 1980s, the majority <strong>of</strong> academic commentators and<br />

policy makers were not convinced that human rights<br />

concerns or ethical considerations were an appropriate<br />

subject <strong>of</strong> study when assessing a state’s foreign policy.<br />

Th is is not surprising as human rights claims were<br />

understood to be particular rather than universal. In the<br />

West, human rights claims were interpreted as largely<br />

synonymous with democracy and the free market. Th e<br />

US Government and the human rights organizations<br />

that it funded consistently played down the economic<br />

and social aspirations <strong>of</strong> the UDHR. As a propaganda<br />

weapon against the Soviet states, Western governments<br />

focused on political and civil freedoms, such as<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> movement and information and the right to<br />

leave and return to one’s country. <strong>Human</strong> rights aspirations<br />

were part <strong>of</strong> the international agenda, but they<br />

were a constituent part <strong>of</strong> the Cold War framework and<br />

understood as subordinate to the rights <strong>of</strong> sovereignty.<br />

Th eir subordination to the geo-political division <strong>of</strong><br />

the Cold War was highlighted by the lack <strong>of</strong> consensus<br />

on moving forward the aspirations <strong>of</strong> the 1948 Universal<br />

Declaration. In the 1950s, two separate UN committees<br />

were established. Th ese produced two separate international<br />

covenants in 1966, one dealing with civil and<br />

political rights and the other with economic, social,<br />

and cultural rights. Th e opposition <strong>of</strong> leading Western<br />

states to rights in the economic and social sphere was<br />

highlighted in 1986 when the UNGA adopted the Declaration<br />

on the Right to Development, and the USA, UK,<br />

Germany, and Japan either voted against or abstained<br />

(Mutua, 1996, pp. 606–607).<br />

It was through attempts to overcome divisions within<br />

the US establishment and the need to address the decline<br />

<strong>of</strong> US credibility abroad, following defeat in Vietnam<br />

and the US-backed overthrow <strong>of</strong> Salvador Allende’s<br />

government in Chile in 1973, that human rights concerns<br />

were put back on the international agenda (Sellars,<br />

2002). <strong>Human</strong> rights became the mechanism by which<br />

America’s reputation was to be redeemed. In 1974 the<br />

Congressional report ‘<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> in the World<br />

Community: A Call for US Leadership’ set the tone for<br />

Gerald Ford’s inclusion <strong>of</strong> human rights provisions into<br />

the East–West Helsinki Agreement <strong>of</strong> 1975—signed<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 118 12/9/08 3:05:56 PM


y the United States, Canada, the Soviet Union, and<br />

most European states including Turkey—and for President<br />

Carter’s declaration in his 1977 inaugural speech<br />

that ‘our commitment to human rights must be absolute’<br />

(Sellars, 2002, p. 118). <strong>Human</strong> rights were on the<br />

agenda, but there was still little understanding <strong>of</strong> these<br />

as universal norms, rather than as a weapon in Cold<br />

War geo-politics.<br />

From 1975 onwards, human rights were institutionalized<br />

as part <strong>of</strong> Cold War political exchanges through<br />

the establishment <strong>of</strong> the Organization for Security and<br />

Cooperation in Europe (OSCE). Th e Helsinki process<br />

<strong>of</strong> East–West negotiations gradually institutionalized<br />

mechanisms <strong>of</strong> human rights monitoring and<br />

information provision under the <strong>Human</strong> Dimension<br />

Mechanism—which allowed OSCE member states<br />

to raise issues <strong>of</strong> human rights concern with other<br />

member states. Th is process was used on over a hundred<br />

occasions but, on all but one (Hungary’s use against<br />

Romania over disturbances in Transylvania), the raising<br />

<strong>of</strong> human rights concerns was directly linked to geopolitical<br />

divisions (Bloed, 1993; Brett, 1993). As long as<br />

the Cold War persisted and human rights issues were<br />

used as weapons in the geo-political divide, it was clear<br />

that there would be no support for the idea that human<br />

KEY POINTS<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and International Intervention<br />

With the end <strong>of</strong> the Cold War, human rights concerns<br />

shift ed from the margins to the mainstream <strong>of</strong><br />

international concerns as universal humanitarianism<br />

appeared to be a feasible possibility. Western states<br />

and international institutions had a much greater<br />

freedom to act in the international sphere with the<br />

attenuation <strong>of</strong> Cold War rivalries freeing policy from<br />

narrow geo-strategic concerns. Th e new possibilities<br />

for intervention and aspirations for a more universal<br />

framework <strong>of</strong> policy making were increasingly<br />

expressed through the expanding discourse <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights. Th ere were relatively few critical voices until<br />

the 1999 Kosovo war—waged unilaterally (without<br />

UN Security Council support) by NATO states against<br />

Serbia—brought to a head concerns about the potential<br />

misuse or abuse <strong>of</strong> concerns <strong>of</strong> humanitarianism<br />

IDEOLOGICAL (MIS)USE OF HUMAN RIGHTS 119<br />

rights concerns could undermine sovereignty. Only in<br />

the 1990s did human rights appear to be a subject <strong>of</strong><br />

concern in their own right, so important as to challenge<br />

the rights <strong>of</strong> states and existing frameworks <strong>of</strong> diplomatic<br />

relations and <strong>of</strong> policy-making priorities.<br />

Universal human rights claims could help provide moral<br />

legitimacy to international institutions, but did not<br />

undermine or challenge the state-based international<br />

order.<br />

Because human rights claims had no socially constituted<br />

legal subject they empowered nation states as their agents,<br />

deciding on the content <strong>of</strong> these rights and the means <strong>of</strong><br />

their enforcement.<br />

During the Cold War, human rights claims were heavily<br />

politicized and subordinate to the interests <strong>of</strong> power,<br />

used by both the US and the Soviet Union to achieve<br />

instrumental ends.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights were equated for ideological reasons with<br />

civil and political rights in the West and with social and<br />

economic rights by Soviet states.<br />

and human rights. In particular, there was concern<br />

about the idea <strong>of</strong> ‘humanitarian war’ tying human<br />

rights advocacy with the preponderant use <strong>of</strong> US military<br />

power. In the following sections, the relationship<br />

between human rights claims, humanitarian advocacy,<br />

international law, and military intervention will be<br />

examined with a particular focus on the ethical, legal,<br />

and political questions raised by the Kosovo war.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and <strong>Human</strong>itarianism<br />

It was in the humanitarian sphere that the shift from<br />

formal views <strong>of</strong> rights, based on rational autonomous<br />

subjects, to ethical views <strong>of</strong> rights, based on a lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> capacity and the need for external advocacy and<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 119 12/9/08 3:05:57 PM


120 D. CHANDLER<br />

intervention, became a major factor in international<br />

relations. Th e introduction <strong>of</strong> the human rights-based<br />

approach into traditional humanitarian practices<br />

refl ected two trends: fi rstly, the increased penetration<br />

<strong>of</strong> external actors and agencies into post-colonial states<br />

and societies; and secondly, the transformation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

content <strong>of</strong> traditional humanitarian principles.<br />

As Western humanitarian non-governmental organizations<br />

(NGOs) acquired greater powers and authority<br />

within post-colonial states, they redefi ned the central<br />

concepts guiding their work. Universality and neutrality<br />

came to be redefi ned, not on the basis <strong>of</strong> a universal<br />

view <strong>of</strong> humanity as being equally moral and autonomous,<br />

but on the basis <strong>of</strong> end goals or aspirations. Th is expansion<br />

<strong>of</strong> external power, through redefi ning the ‘human’<br />

as lacking autonomy, eff ectively set up a hierarchy <strong>of</strong><br />

the ‘helper’ and the ‘helpless’. Th rough the ethic <strong>of</strong><br />

responsibility to assist the ‘helpless’—those without<br />

autonomy—this discourse reframed political choices<br />

as ethical questions. In this way, external NGO actors<br />

maintained a ‘non-political’ stance <strong>of</strong> neutrality at the<br />

same time as claiming extended rights to intervene<br />

in domestic political processes. From the late 1960s<br />

onwards, international humanitarian NGOs used the<br />

discourse <strong>of</strong> human rights to rewrite the boundaries <strong>of</strong><br />

their authority through expanding the sphere <strong>of</strong> ethics<br />

into the sphere <strong>of</strong> political decision making.<br />

Th e debate within the NGO community, from the late<br />

1960s, over diff ering approaches to universal humanitarian<br />

ethics, counter-posed two views <strong>of</strong> universality.<br />

Th e former, ‘rights equality’, view espoused by the ICRC<br />

was based on the Enlightenment understanding that<br />

the recipients <strong>of</strong> aid were autonomous capable moral<br />

beings and therefore made no judgement regarding the<br />

actions or political choices <strong>of</strong> recipients (see Ignatieff ,<br />

1998, pp. 109–163). Th e human rights-based approach<br />

saw the recipients <strong>of</strong> aid in more judgemental terms:<br />

this universality was based on ends-based outcomes <strong>of</strong><br />

peace, development, justice, etc. Th e importance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

shift from a universal ‘rights equality’ approach to that<br />

<strong>of</strong> a ‘human rights-based’ approach is rarely clarifi ed;<br />

one exception is Michael Ignatieff ’s discussion <strong>of</strong> ICRC<br />

‘impartiality’ in his book Warrior’s Honor (Ignatieff ,<br />

1998) (see Box 7.3).<br />

Th e human rights-based discourse <strong>of</strong> humanitarianism<br />

enabled NGOs to blur the distinction between<br />

politics and ethics. Central to this confl ation <strong>of</strong> politics<br />

and ethics was the development <strong>of</strong> new codes <strong>of</strong><br />

Box 7.3 The Distinction Between the ICRC<br />

and MSF (Médecins Sans Frontières/<br />

Doctors Without Borders)<br />

Michael Ignatieff on <strong>Human</strong>itarianism<br />

[The ICRC’s] doctrine <strong>of</strong> neutrality is called into question<br />

by organizations like Médecines sans Frontières [Doctors<br />

without Borders], which maintains that humanitarian<br />

intervention cannot be impartial between the Serb<br />

militiaman and the Muslim civilian, or the machetewielding<br />

Hutu and the Tutsi victim. . . . [T]his leaves the<br />

ICRC wondering whether [its] insistence that all victims are<br />

equal, whatever the justice <strong>of</strong> their cause, makes sense in<br />

the bitter confl icts where one ethnic group is now seeking<br />

to obliterate the other. (Ignatieff, 1998, p. 124.)<br />

James Orbinski (MSF) on <strong>Human</strong>itarianism<br />

The moral intention <strong>of</strong> the humanitarian act must be<br />

confronted with its actual result. And it is here where<br />

any form <strong>of</strong> moral neutrality about what is good must be<br />

rejected. The result can be the use <strong>of</strong> the humanitarian<br />

in 1985 to support forced migration in Ethiopia, or the<br />

use in 1996 <strong>of</strong> the humanitarian to support a genocidal<br />

regime in the refugee camps <strong>of</strong> Goma. Abstention is<br />

sometimes necessary so that the humanitarian is not<br />

used against a population in crisis. (Orbinski, 1999.)<br />

practice based around redefi ning neutrality. Neutrality<br />

no longer meant the equal respect for parties to<br />

confl ict or for locally-instituted authorities, but was<br />

redefi ned as neutrality with respect to human rights<br />

frameworks and outcomes. In this way, NGOs claimed<br />

decision-making powers over who deserved aid and<br />

which practices <strong>of</strong> development were more appropriate.<br />

NGOs accrued more authority through the human<br />

rights discourse because they were held to be acting on<br />

behalf <strong>of</strong> rights subjects unable or incapable <strong>of</strong> acting<br />

on their own behalf.<br />

Th e extension <strong>of</strong> the power and authority <strong>of</strong> humanitarian<br />

non-state actors took place in relation to changes<br />

in approaches to both confl ict and to development.<br />

First, through the extension <strong>of</strong> assistance to victims <strong>of</strong><br />

war, there was a shift from the ICRC approach <strong>of</strong> aid to<br />

casualties and assistance to prisoners regardless <strong>of</strong> political<br />

affi liation, to a more engaged, ‘solidarity’ approach,<br />

advocated by agencies such as Doctors without Borders<br />

who argued that there was a need to discriminate<br />

between abusers and victims and to intervene in confl<br />

ict with a view to rights-based outcomes (see Box<br />

7.3). Second, there was a shift in NGO approaches to<br />

emergency relief, and an increased understanding that<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 120 12/9/08 3:05:58 PM


famines and natural disasters could be better addressed<br />

by long-term developmental approaches rather than<br />

short-term palliative ones (see further <strong>Chandler</strong>, 2001).<br />

It now appeared that humanitarian NGOs were dutybound<br />

to intervene in much more direct and lasting<br />

ways. However, this approach <strong>of</strong> solidarity and education<br />

and training meant that the relationship between<br />

NGOs and their benefi ciaries changed from one <strong>of</strong><br />

charity between ostensible equals to one <strong>of</strong> dependency<br />

and empowerment. Th e humanitarian NGOs shift ed<br />

from a traditional liberal rights-based approach <strong>of</strong><br />

equality to an ethico-political approach <strong>of</strong> human rights<br />

that facilitated the inequality <strong>of</strong> treatment. Th is has<br />

resulted in humanitarian NGOs opposing the provision<br />

<strong>of</strong> aid in cases where it was felt human rights outcomes<br />

could be undermined (Leader, 1998; Fox, 2001).<br />

By the end <strong>of</strong> the Cold War, the discourse <strong>of</strong> humanitarian<br />

universalism had become a highly interventionist<br />

one, transformed through the modern discourse <strong>of</strong><br />

human rights values and assumptions. Once the barriers<br />

to state actors intervening were diminished, this<br />

discourse was increasingly taken over by leading states<br />

and international institutions and NGOs boomed in<br />

numbers and authority as new frameworks <strong>of</strong> intervention<br />

were instituted. According to Mark Duffi eld, the<br />

‘petty sovereignty’ <strong>of</strong> NGOs—their increasing assumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> political, decision-making powers in regions<br />

intervened in—was ‘governmentalized’ in the 1990s:<br />

integrated within a growing web <strong>of</strong> interventionist<br />

institutions and practices associated with external<br />

intervention and regulation (Duffi eld, 2007).<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and International Law<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights claims, the ethico-juridical claims <strong>of</strong> a<br />

non-constituted legal subject—the human—tend to<br />

confl ict with formal international legal frameworks,<br />

which necessarily operate on the basis <strong>of</strong> constituted<br />

legal subjects—sovereign states. Over the course <strong>of</strong> the<br />

1990s and the early 2000s the understanding <strong>of</strong> this<br />

confl ict has changed. Key to the changing nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> human rights and international law have<br />

been debates on the redefi nition <strong>of</strong> the meaning and<br />

relevance <strong>of</strong> the legal subject in international law, i.e.<br />

the meaning <strong>of</strong> sovereignty.<br />

Th e discussion <strong>of</strong> the meaning <strong>of</strong> sovereignty refl ects<br />

the discussions <strong>of</strong> neutrality and universality, high-<br />

IDEOLOGICAL (MIS)USE OF HUMAN RIGHTS 121<br />

lighted in the previous subsection. Th e universal essence<br />

<strong>of</strong> sovereign equality was not the power or capacity <strong>of</strong><br />

states, which clearly varied tremendously. Th e quality <strong>of</strong><br />

equality was that <strong>of</strong> moral and political autonomy, the<br />

equality <strong>of</strong> the right <strong>of</strong> self-government. Since the end<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Cold War, this framework <strong>of</strong> sovereign equality<br />

has been challenged through the framework <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights, which asserts that formal juridical frameworks<br />

are inadequate to address the needs <strong>of</strong> people living in<br />

many states where governments are held to be ‘unable<br />

or unwilling’ to protect their rights (ICISS, 2001).<br />

At the most basic level, sovereign autonomy or selfgovernment<br />

is seen as increasingly problematic on its<br />

own terms. Th e possession <strong>of</strong> formal democracy is no<br />

longer seen as adequate to safeguard the rights and interests<br />

<strong>of</strong> individuals. Many commentators follow Fareed<br />

Zakaria in his view <strong>of</strong> the post-Cold War rise <strong>of</strong> ‘illiberal<br />

democracies’ (Zakaria, 2003). Democracy without<br />

liberal cultures and frameworks <strong>of</strong> rights protections<br />

is held to be as likely to be a license for tyranny as for<br />

freedom. In order to prevent the ‘tyranny <strong>of</strong> the majority’<br />

or the arbitrariness <strong>of</strong> democratic mandates (Mill,<br />

1972, p. 73; Guinier, 1994), international human rights<br />

enforcements have been increasingly demanded as part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the agenda <strong>of</strong> ‘good governance’ and the ‘rule <strong>of</strong> law’.<br />

Th ere is also a second approach <strong>of</strong> human rights advocacy<br />

that undermines the rights <strong>of</strong> sovereignty, not on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> the problems <strong>of</strong> the formal political framework<br />

<strong>of</strong> citizenship rights, but on the basis <strong>of</strong> economic<br />

and social provisions. Th is is the discourse <strong>of</strong> the ‘failed’<br />

or ‘failing’ state, where it is asserted that problems with<br />

social welfare provision or with economic development<br />

indicate that many post-colonial states need external<br />

assistance to enhance their ‘functional’ sovereignty (see<br />

Ghani et al., 2005). Here the ethico-juridical framework<br />

<strong>of</strong> human rights redefi nes sovereignty on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

social and economic capacities, creating a sliding scale<br />

<strong>of</strong> sovereignty and marginalizing the importance <strong>of</strong> a<br />

juridical framework based on autonomy and sovereign<br />

equality.<br />

Critical commentators are increasingly suggesting<br />

that human rights approaches have succeeded in<br />

redefi ning sovereignty so that it lacks any distinct legal<br />

meaning and that, in this way, external intervention is<br />

no longer seen as confl icting with or as undermining<br />

<strong>of</strong> sovereignty. Mark Duffi eld suggests that sovereignty<br />

has been redefi ned in terms <strong>of</strong> the biopolitical—based<br />

on the needs <strong>of</strong> the population rather than the needs<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 121 12/9/08 3:05:58 PM


122 D. CHANDLER<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ruler or government—to justify intervention in<br />

the cause <strong>of</strong> enhancing the standards <strong>of</strong> human development<br />

or human security (Duffi eld, 2007). Graham<br />

Harrison’s work on the ‘governance state’ has highlighted<br />

how sovereign institutions <strong>of</strong> government have<br />

become transmission belts for external governance<br />

(Harrison, 2004; see also <strong>Chandler</strong>, 2006). On the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> human rights frameworks, the claims <strong>of</strong> sovereign<br />

states to legal equality have been weakened, as they<br />

have been judged to <strong>of</strong>t en be less capable <strong>of</strong> ensuring<br />

that human rights are protected than alternative human<br />

rights-based frameworks <strong>of</strong> international regulation<br />

and intervention.<br />

On the basis <strong>of</strong> the undermining <strong>of</strong> claims <strong>of</strong> sovereignty,<br />

it is increasingly argued that international<br />

law is becoming ‘domesticated’, i.e. that it is becoming<br />

more like domestic law, enshrining the individual as<br />

its legal subject. It is <strong>of</strong>t en suggested that the prioritizing<br />

<strong>of</strong> individual human rights above the rights <strong>of</strong><br />

state sovereignty can be understood as the creation <strong>of</strong><br />

a new international moral legal order, highlighted in<br />

the conviction <strong>of</strong> state leaders for war crimes through<br />

the establishment <strong>of</strong> ad hoc international tribunals<br />

for former Yugoslavia and Rwanda, the prosecution<br />

<strong>of</strong> Chilean dictator Augustus Pinochet, the establishment<br />

<strong>of</strong> the International Criminal Court (ICC), and<br />

the development <strong>of</strong> ideas <strong>of</strong> universal jurisdiction. For<br />

human rights advocates, this new international order<br />

is one that is capable <strong>of</strong> institutionalizing the legal and<br />

political equality <strong>of</strong> individuals in place <strong>of</strong> the UN<br />

Charter framework <strong>of</strong> the equality <strong>of</strong> sovereign states.<br />

It is in the area <strong>of</strong> international law, therefore, that the<br />

problematic fact that the individual subject <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights is not a legally constituted subject becomes clearly<br />

highlighted. Rather than extending international law<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> reconstituting the formal nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

international sphere, international law is being transformed<br />

into a ‘moral–legal order’, where the spheres<br />

<strong>of</strong> ethics and <strong>of</strong> law are becoming blurred (Douzinas,<br />

2007, p. 148). Th e sphere <strong>of</strong> law is formally one <strong>of</strong><br />

equality, where under equal circumstances the punishment<br />

is the same. However, the rise <strong>of</strong> human rights<br />

frameworks has introduced an ethical component into<br />

international law that, according to Costas Douzinas,<br />

‘reconstitutes the structure, subjects and core values <strong>of</strong><br />

the international system’ (Douzinas, 2007, p. 183).<br />

Th is change refl ects and institutionalizes the shift ing<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> power relations in the international sphere<br />

in the aft ermath <strong>of</strong> the end <strong>of</strong> the Cold War. During<br />

the Cold War, there was a balance <strong>of</strong> power between<br />

the US and the Soviet Union. Although the sides may<br />

not have been exactly equal, the key point is that minor<br />

disputes or confl icts risked escalating into a nuclear<br />

superpower confrontation. For this reason, smaller<br />

states found that their sovereignty and independence<br />

were safeguarded, not so much because <strong>of</strong> the letter <strong>of</strong><br />

international law, but because the maintenance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

status quo and restriction on the use <strong>of</strong> force to challenge<br />

sovereign borders was seen to be vital for world<br />

peace and international order. Weak states maintained<br />

their sovereignty against more powerful external rivals<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the constitution <strong>of</strong> the international order<br />

(see Jackson, 1990). With the end <strong>of</strong> this balance <strong>of</strong><br />

power, a new more hegemonic and ‘unipolar’ world<br />

order came into existence, which has been refl ected in<br />

the renegotiation and overcoming <strong>of</strong> Cold War formal<br />

and informal limits to external intervention.<br />

Th e human rights framework has facilitated and<br />

smoothed the transition away from the formally constituted<br />

international order <strong>of</strong> the Cold War. Th e ethical<br />

challenge <strong>of</strong> human rights has helped to legitimize the<br />

downgrading <strong>of</strong> the formal legal subjects <strong>of</strong> the previous<br />

order, equal sovereign states, and in their place<br />

sets up the more fl exible framework based upon the<br />

claims <strong>of</strong> non-constituted legal subjects. In the 1990s<br />

the contradictions between the two approaches to<br />

framing international order seemed transparent in the<br />

debate between the formal ‘right <strong>of</strong> sovereignty’ and the<br />

emerging ‘right <strong>of</strong> intervention’ on behalf <strong>of</strong> universal<br />

human rights claims. Th is polarization was highlighted<br />

in relation to the NATO war over Kosovo in 1999,<br />

where human rights were held to trump sovereignty.<br />

Th e problem was that, for many, it was clear that the<br />

agency empowered by human rights claims was not<br />

Kosovo victims as much as NATO powers who claimed<br />

the right <strong>of</strong> intervention without UN Security Council<br />

permission.<br />

Following Kosovo, the UN established an independent<br />

commission, the International Commission on<br />

Intervention and State Sovereignty, which, with some<br />

success, attempted to overcome the problem <strong>of</strong> clashing<br />

rights. In its report ‘Th e Responsibility to Protect’<br />

(ICISS, 2001), the Commission suggested reframing<br />

the meaning <strong>of</strong> sovereignty to include the respect for<br />

human rights, enabling external intervention to be presented<br />

as supporting or enhancing sovereignty, rather<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 122 12/9/08 3:05:59 PM


than undermining it. At the same time, the report<br />

advocated the revival <strong>of</strong> Just War justifi cations for military<br />

intervention if the UN Security Council was not<br />

able to agree to interventions to protect human rights.<br />

Th e Commission’s report smoothed the transition away<br />

from the formal framework <strong>of</strong> the UN Charter toward a<br />

more fl exible moral–legal framework, which inevitably<br />

gave more rights to power (Simpson, 2004).<br />

Critical commentators suggest that rights-based<br />

approaches shift sovereignty toward a new global<br />

centre, but one which is not formally or legally constituted.<br />

For many critics, the work <strong>of</strong> Carl Schmitt (1996)<br />

and the more recent work <strong>of</strong> Giorgio Agamben (2005)<br />

highlight that sovereignty, understood as the decisionmaking<br />

power over the exception, has shift ed to give<br />

Western states, specifi cally the USA, greater sovereign<br />

decision-making power, at the expense <strong>of</strong> the loss <strong>of</strong><br />

sovereignty <strong>of</strong> post-colonial states.<br />

For these critics, the key examples <strong>of</strong> the shift away<br />

from formal equality <strong>of</strong> sovereignty can be found in<br />

Box 7.4 Cosmopolitanism: A New Hierarchy<br />

or a New Universalism?<br />

Costas Douzinas on Cosmopolitanism<br />

The alleged cosmopolitan character <strong>of</strong> contemporary<br />

politics does not derive from their global subjection to<br />

universal rules. The reverse is true: universal rules are<br />

created as ideal accompaniments <strong>of</strong> global phenomena<br />

by those who can exercise world policy. Domestic<br />

considerations have always played an important role<br />

in the calculation <strong>of</strong> the great powers and determine<br />

the ways in which foreign relations are exercised. This<br />

leads to a crucial distinction between globalisation and<br />

universalisation, which has been almost totally elided<br />

in the debate on human rights. (Douzinas, 2007, pp.<br />

180–181.)<br />

Vivienne Jabri on Cosmopolitanism<br />

The consequences <strong>of</strong> what may be referred to as<br />

cosmopolitan war are pr<strong>of</strong>ound, for they suggest . . .<br />

a wholesale transformation <strong>of</strong> social and political<br />

relations both domestically and internationally . . . [and]<br />

in Foucaultian terms . . . relations <strong>of</strong> power that seek<br />

to discipline confl ict and dissent emerging from other<br />

societies. . . . What emerges from discourses that seek<br />

to modernise, civilise, or democratise, is a conception <strong>of</strong><br />

a world rendered in hierarchical terms, those that can<br />

claim the right <strong>of</strong> judgement and others who cannot,<br />

those within the law and those located beyond the law,<br />

those worthy <strong>of</strong> protection and others not so deserving;<br />

all suggesting a hierarchy <strong>of</strong> worthiness the remit <strong>of</strong><br />

which is hegemonic domination. (Jabri, 2007, pp. 96–97.)<br />

IDEOLOGICAL (MIS)USE OF HUMAN RIGHTS 123<br />

the overturning <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong> non-intervention in<br />

Kosovo and Iraq. Th ey highlight the inequalities created<br />

by this process: while the USA refuses to be bound by<br />

international treaties that are held to limit its powers <strong>of</strong><br />

sovereign decision making—for example, being the only<br />

state (apart from Somalia) not to sign up to the International<br />

Convention on the <strong>Rights</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Child, its refusal to<br />

submit to the ICC, etc.—other states have been forced<br />

to admit external intervention into their aff airs.<br />

For Douzinas, human rights discourses constitute a<br />

challenge to the UN Charter legal order, but one that<br />

seeks to constitute a hierarchy <strong>of</strong> unequal rights rather<br />

than a more universal order based on the equality <strong>of</strong><br />

rights (see Box 7.4). Th e rights <strong>of</strong> sovereignty and selfdetermination<br />

for smaller or more peripheral states<br />

have been removed: ‘Lost sovereignty has not disappeared.<br />

It has been absorbed and condensed into a<br />

super-sovereign centre.’ (Douzinas, 2007, p. 271; see also<br />

Jabri, 2007.) For Douzinas, the collapse <strong>of</strong> traditional<br />

restrictions on military intervention and the projection<br />

<strong>of</strong> Western power undermine plural relations <strong>of</strong> equal<br />

sovereignty and reveal that, ‘In a historical reversal, an<br />

emperor is emerging but the empire is still under construction.’<br />

(Douzinas, 2007, p. 257.)<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and Military Intervention<br />

Th e privileging <strong>of</strong> human rights as individual rights<br />

above the sovereign rights <strong>of</strong> states has altered traditional<br />

international practices, especially with regard<br />

to international law and the use <strong>of</strong> force. Th e human<br />

rights-based justifi cation for military intervention is<br />

<strong>of</strong>t en posed in terms <strong>of</strong> the revival <strong>of</strong> pre-modern Just<br />

War thinking, which is concerned with the moral and<br />

ethical basis <strong>of</strong> war rather than with its legal grounding.<br />

Here the clash between the universal ethics <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights and the legal framework <strong>of</strong> international society<br />

as it is currently situated comes into stark clarity.<br />

Th e Kosovo war is <strong>of</strong>t en seen as marking the highpoint<br />

for human rights internationalism. Jürgen<br />

Habermas supported the Kosovo war, despite the fact<br />

that it was illegal under UN Charter rules, on the<br />

basis that in going to war for human rights NATO was<br />

pushing the boundaries <strong>of</strong> international law into a cosmopolitan,<br />

universal direction (Habermas, 1999). Th e<br />

war, alleged to be in the ‘grey area’ between legality and<br />

morality, illustrated the essence <strong>of</strong> human rights claims<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 123 12/9/08 3:05:59 PM


124 D. CHANDLER<br />

as an ethical challenge to law (IICK, 2000). To some<br />

commentators, using ethical arguments <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights to undermine UN Charter law against war was<br />

dangerous or an ‘abuse’ <strong>of</strong> ethics; for others, as outlined<br />

with respect <strong>of</strong> Habermas, this, on the contrary, was a<br />

valuable ‘use’ <strong>of</strong> ethics.<br />

However, the rights <strong>of</strong> the ‘human’ (<strong>of</strong> ‘human security’<br />

or <strong>of</strong> human rights) that are enforced are not the<br />

rights <strong>of</strong> legally constituted subjects, they are not the<br />

rights <strong>of</strong> states, the subjects <strong>of</strong> international law. As<br />

the rights being enforced are not those <strong>of</strong> legal subjects,<br />

the content and enforcement <strong>of</strong> human rights is dependent<br />

on the ad hoc agency <strong>of</strong> states willing to shoulder<br />

the burden <strong>of</strong> paying for and participating in intervention.<br />

Th e ad hoc nature <strong>of</strong> human rights enforcement<br />

means that the ethico-juridical undermining <strong>of</strong> UN<br />

Charter law cannot take a universal form, but is inevitably<br />

dependent on a case-by-case approach, with the<br />

decision making dictated more by the interests and concerns<br />

<strong>of</strong> the powerful than the needs <strong>of</strong> the powerless.<br />

a For some critics, such as Danilo Zolo (2002), it is the<br />

global hegemon, the United States, that is empowered<br />

by more informal and ad hoc decision making, but for<br />

others, such as Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, it<br />

is global neoliberal capitalism itself, taking the postnational<br />

form <strong>of</strong> Empire (Hardt and Negri, 2001).<br />

Whether the case <strong>of</strong> Kosovo, where human rights<br />

were held to trump sovereignty and international law<br />

(HRW, 1999), is understood as a positive step toward a<br />

more universal order or as a reactionary step toward a<br />

more hierarchical order may be a matter <strong>of</strong> normative<br />

choice. What is beyond dispute is that the existing legal<br />

order was challenged and undermined by states powerful<br />

enough to take the decision to wage war against the<br />

Serbian state. Th e US and most <strong>of</strong> the European powers,<br />

which backed the war, unilaterally decided to wage war<br />

outside the legal restrictions <strong>of</strong> the UN Charter order.<br />

In doing this they claimed that they were waging war<br />

on behalf <strong>of</strong> the rights <strong>of</strong> the Kosovo Albanians. But<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> human rights claims is that, while Kosovo<br />

Albanians were the subjects <strong>of</strong> these rights, the active<br />

agents in enforcing them were the NATO powers, who<br />

in doing so accrued or claimed the right to wage war<br />

independently <strong>of</strong> the UN.<br />

Today, human rights, the rule <strong>of</strong> law, and good<br />

governance provide the key framework <strong>of</strong> international<br />

institutional policy practices. However, when it<br />

comes to the international sphere, the lack <strong>of</strong> mechanisms<br />

to generate global consensus, the increased<br />

power inequalities, and the limited safeguards make<br />

any attempts to institutionalize human rights regimes<br />

outside the mutual agreement <strong>of</strong> sovereign states much<br />

more problematic. Th e problem with constituting<br />

frameworks <strong>of</strong> sanction, intervention, and war on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> non-socially constituted legal subjects is that<br />

it leaves wide open the problem, raised by Schmitt,<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘who decides?’ (Schmitt, 1996, 2003). Whether the<br />

intention is to (mis)use human rights ideologically or<br />

to genuinely do good in the world, the outcome is the<br />

same: ultimately, greater decision-making power and<br />

authority accrue to the states (or some would argue<br />

the USA as the sole remaining great power) that have<br />

the capacity to take on the responsibilities <strong>of</strong> deciding<br />

and enforcing.<br />

KEY POINTS<br />

The human rights-based approach has facilitated<br />

humanitarian aid being denied in some circumstances<br />

and in support for more militarized humanitarianism—for<br />

example, the NATO war over Kosovo.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights approaches appeared to directly challenge<br />

sovereignty in the 1990s, but in the 2000s have sought to<br />

redefi ne sovereignty as being compatible with international<br />

human rights protections. Central to this shift has been the<br />

ICISS report ‘The Responsibility to Protect’ (ICISS, 2001).<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights approaches tend to redefi ne war fought in<br />

the post-colonial world as a matter <strong>of</strong> human rights crimes<br />

and human rights victims; they also tend to redefi ne war<br />

fought by Western powers, seeing intervention in the cause<br />

<strong>of</strong> human rights as more akin to police action than war<br />

making.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights approaches have facilitated a more fl exible<br />

and positive framework for military intervention, shifting<br />

away from UN Charter approaches that saw war as the<br />

‘scourge <strong>of</strong> humanity’.<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 124 12/9/08 3:06:00 PM


<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and the Search for Meaning<br />

Michael Ignatieff has emphasized that the universalism<br />

<strong>of</strong> human rights and humanitarianism represents<br />

a very diff erent type <strong>of</strong> universalism than that traditionally<br />

associated with human rights as a progressive<br />

demand based upon human rationality, autonomy, and<br />

self-determination. Rather than expressing human<br />

aspirations for a better future, the modern universal<br />

ethic <strong>of</strong> human rights tends to view humanity itself as<br />

problematic. Here, what draws humanity together as a<br />

universal is our capacity to commit crime and to suff er<br />

it. He argues that, ‘Modern moral universalism is built<br />

upon the experience <strong>of</strong> a new kind <strong>of</strong> crime: the crime<br />

against humanity.’ (Ignatieff , 1998, p. 19.) Th e universal<br />

human subject is the victim: ‘genocide and famine<br />

create a new human subject—the pure victim stripped<br />

<strong>of</strong> social identity’ (Ignatieff , 1998, p. 20).<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and Political<br />

Disillusionment<br />

Rather than universal discourses <strong>of</strong> human rights<br />

expressing a new progressive political era, Ignatieff<br />

highlights that the focus on human rights expresses<br />

disillusionment with political engagement and social<br />

change: the concern that ‘there are no good causes<br />

left —only victims <strong>of</strong> bad causes’ (Ignatieff , 1998, p.<br />

23). He notes (Ignatieff , 1998, p. 250) the danger <strong>of</strong> this<br />

modern moral universalism, which ‘has taken the form<br />

<strong>of</strong> an anti-ideological and anti-political ethic <strong>of</strong> siding<br />

with the victim; the moral risk entailed by this ethic is<br />

misanthropy.’<br />

Th ere is a danger that our modern anti-political sentiments<br />

and disillusionment with progress and collective<br />

aspirations may take the form <strong>of</strong> a misanthropic view <strong>of</strong><br />

humanity rather than a critique <strong>of</strong> economic and social<br />

relations in which our political lives are constructed<br />

and constrained. Th is misanthropic view is universalist,<br />

but also extremely divisive and self-comforting. Ignatieff<br />

(1998, p. 95) suggests that in seeking to rationalize<br />

the problems <strong>of</strong> the world, a depoliticized human rights<br />

perspective fi nds it easy to blame non-Western societies<br />

and governments and, in so doing, portray better<br />

<strong>of</strong>f Western society as blameless and morally superior.<br />

IDEOLOGICAL (MIS)USE OF HUMAN RIGHTS 125<br />

In fact, it is <strong>of</strong>t en diffi cult to separate our concern for<br />

others and the construction <strong>of</strong> our own self-image or<br />

identity. As people and politicians in the West lack a<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> mission and purpose and strong shared or<br />

collective self-image, there is a danger that we seek personal<br />

and collective affi rmation in our relationship to<br />

the non-Western world: ‘. . . when policy was driven by<br />

moral motives, it was <strong>of</strong>t en driven by narcissism. We<br />

intervened not only to save others, but to save ourselves,<br />

or rather an image <strong>of</strong> ourselves as defenders <strong>of</strong><br />

universal decencies. We wanted to show that the West<br />

“meant” something.’<br />

Th e view that the shift toward framing international<br />

politics through the lens <strong>of</strong> human rights refl ects the<br />

fact that major Western states and societies lack positive<br />

political goals or a strong sense <strong>of</strong> their own social<br />

cohesion, gives a diff erent angle to the (mis)use <strong>of</strong><br />

human rights than that discussed above. Rather than<br />

an assertion <strong>of</strong> Western (or neo-imperial) interests and<br />

power and global aspirations <strong>of</strong> domination, the human<br />

rights discourse expresses a post-Cold War loss <strong>of</strong> confi<br />

dence and lack <strong>of</strong> clear aims among leading Western<br />

and international policy actors.<br />

Alain Badiou (2001, p. 31) suggests that citizen rights<br />

and the domestic political process no longer provide<br />

individuals or societies with a sense <strong>of</strong> meaning or<br />

purpose: ‘Parliamentary politics as practiced today<br />

does not in any way consist <strong>of</strong> setting objectives<br />

inspired by principles and <strong>of</strong> inventing the means to<br />

attain them.’ Rather than representing a new social<br />

collectivity, for Badiou, the focus on consensual ethics<br />

refl ects the ‘end <strong>of</strong> ideology’ and political contestation<br />

and the lack <strong>of</strong> instrumental aims or social goals <strong>of</strong><br />

state leaders (see Box 7.5).<br />

<strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and the Lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> a Political Project<br />

Th e work <strong>of</strong> Zaki Laïdi (1998) provides some valuable<br />

insights into how to tie together the themes <strong>of</strong> loss <strong>of</strong><br />

instrumental goals and collective meaning with the<br />

search for social cohesion and legitimating ‘mission’<br />

through the international discourse <strong>of</strong> human rights<br />

activism. Ethics and moral values can be seen to have<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 125 12/9/08 3:06:00 PM


126 D. CHANDLER<br />

Box 7.5 The Pessimism <strong>of</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong><br />

Michael Ignatieff on Universal <strong>Human</strong>itarianism<br />

In the twentieth century, the idea <strong>of</strong> human universality<br />

rests less on hope than on fear, less on optimism about<br />

the human capacity for good than on dread <strong>of</strong> human<br />

capacity for evil, less on a vision <strong>of</strong> man as maker <strong>of</strong><br />

his history than <strong>of</strong> man the wolf toward his own kind.<br />

(Ignatieff, 1998, p. 18.)<br />

Alain Badiou on Ethics<br />

Whether we think <strong>of</strong> it as the consensual representation<br />

<strong>of</strong> Evil or as concern for the other, ethics designates<br />

above all the incapacity, so typical <strong>of</strong> the contemporary<br />

world, to name and strive for a Good. . . . For from the<br />

beginning it confi rms the absence <strong>of</strong> any project, <strong>of</strong><br />

any emancipatory politics, or any genuinely collective<br />

cause . . . ‘concern for the other’ signifi es that it is not a<br />

matter—that it is never a matter—<strong>of</strong> prescribing hitherto<br />

unexplored possibilities for our situation, and ultimately<br />

for ourselves. (Badiou, 2001, pp. 30, 33.)<br />

displaced instrumental national interests because<br />

governments have little sense <strong>of</strong> themselves as representatives<br />

<strong>of</strong> a collective social project. <strong>Human</strong> rights claims,<br />

because <strong>of</strong> their ungrounded and abstract nature, fi ll the<br />

vacuum by providing an ethical purpose or set <strong>of</strong> ‘values’<br />

that no longer need to be strategically acted upon. Th e<br />

lack <strong>of</strong> clear instrumental or strategic political goals<br />

becomes repackaged as an asset rather than a problem.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights abuses (like the threat <strong>of</strong> terrorism) are<br />

held to be issues <strong>of</strong> urgency, crisis, or emergency, where<br />

strategic thinking and long-term planning are no longer<br />

called for (see <strong>Chandler</strong>, 2007b).<br />

Th e shift from national or collective political interests<br />

to global or ethical values indicates a fundamental<br />

shift in both the meaning and practice <strong>of</strong> politics. Th e<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> this shift is indicated in Max Weber’s<br />

essay on ‘Politics as a Vocation’. Here he argued that<br />

there were ‘two fundamentally diff erent, irredeemably<br />

incompatible maxims’, the ‘ethics <strong>of</strong> conviction’<br />

and the ‘ethics <strong>of</strong> responsibility’ (Weber, 2004, p. 83).<br />

Th e former is about being judged on intention, the<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> values as a statement about oneself; the<br />

latter is about being judged on outcomes, the expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> political action as a strategic and instrumental<br />

engagement in the world. It would appear that, in the<br />

framework discussed in this section, the shift from<br />

strategic interests to ethical values is not primarily<br />

about the recasting <strong>of</strong> interests in an ideological form,<br />

but more a rejection <strong>of</strong> the responsibilities <strong>of</strong> power.<br />

In the new world order <strong>of</strong> human rights and universal<br />

humanity it would seem, states Laïdi, that ‘there is no<br />

longer any distance between what one does and what<br />

one aspires to’, with human rights acting as the discursive<br />

framework through which political programmes<br />

and long-term projects can be side-stepped.<br />

Ironically, the search for values and meaning in the<br />

discursive frameworks <strong>of</strong> human rights and humanitarianism<br />

exposes the lack <strong>of</strong> strategic interests behind<br />

military interventions and other forms <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights conditionality and regulation. Acting on behalf<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ‘ethics <strong>of</strong> conviction’ exposes the lack <strong>of</strong> genuine<br />

conviction or strategic concern behind international<br />

interventions under the banner <strong>of</strong> ‘human rights’, and,<br />

for that matter, the ‘war on terror’. Interventions and the<br />

use <strong>of</strong> the international arena to fi nd a sense <strong>of</strong> mission<br />

and shared values exposes Western intervention as<br />

merely an act <strong>of</strong> power without meaning (Laïdi, 1998, p.<br />

109). For Laïdi, attempts by Western states and, through<br />

them, international institutions, to project their power<br />

in order to generate meaning are doomed to failure.<br />

Th is can be understood as a failure in a double sense.<br />

Firstly, because the intervention itself is not primarily<br />

concerned with the object <strong>of</strong> intervention there is, therefore,<br />

little strategic or instrumental concern with regard<br />

to fi nal outcomes. Secondly, there is failure with regard<br />

to the attempt to use intervention, or the international<br />

sphere more broadly, to generate meaning and purpose.<br />

Th is is because the problem <strong>of</strong> meaning is an internal<br />

one, based on the lack <strong>of</strong> connection between governing<br />

elites and their societies (see <strong>Chandler</strong>, 2007a, 2007b).<br />

KEY POINTS<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights discourses and practices <strong>of</strong> intervention<br />

do not necessarily have to be understood as the narrow<br />

projection <strong>of</strong> traditional great power or imperial interests.<br />

The asymmetries <strong>of</strong> power, <strong>of</strong> Western domination, allow<br />

the international sphere to be used as an arena for the<br />

creation <strong>of</strong> meaning or purpose, for both governments and<br />

individuals.<br />

The use <strong>of</strong> the international sphere to generate a sense <strong>of</strong><br />

‘mission’ leads to the projection <strong>of</strong> Western power with<br />

little strategic or instrumental consideration. This can be<br />

highly destabilizing.<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 126 12/9/08 3:06:01 PM


Conclusion<br />

Th ere can be no clear line <strong>of</strong> demarcation between the<br />

ideological use and (mis)use <strong>of</strong> human rights frameworks<br />

in international politics. Because human rights<br />

involve a separation between the agent <strong>of</strong> protection<br />

and the rights subject, there is no formal legal and<br />

political framework to judge whether claims <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights at an international level are abused. Th e question<br />

is a normative one. Where there can be a greater level<br />

<strong>of</strong> consensus is at the empirical level: the rise <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights approaches refl ects the declining importance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the UN Charter order <strong>of</strong> international law, and the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> more ad hoc and informal mechanisms<br />

<strong>of</strong> international regulation and intervention.<br />

It has been argued above that the demand to forward<br />

claims in the terminology <strong>of</strong> human rights refl ects a<br />

world in which the international legal order orientated<br />

around the constitutive rights <strong>of</strong> sovereign states<br />

is under challenge. Th is challenge takes the form <strong>of</strong> a<br />

shift from rights taking a purely legal form, the ‘black<br />

and white’ wording <strong>of</strong> the UN Charter, to an ethicojuridical<br />

form. Th is shift away from formal legal rights<br />

to more informal expressions <strong>of</strong> rights and duties could<br />

be described as a shift toward the dominance <strong>of</strong> human<br />

rights above the rights <strong>of</strong> states, or as emerging cosmo-<br />

QUESTIONS<br />

INDIVIDUAL STUDY QUESTIONS<br />

IDEOLOGICAL (MIS)USE OF HUMAN RIGHTS 127<br />

politan legal norms. Th e shift away from legal rights,<br />

framed in terms <strong>of</strong> autonomy, self-determination, and<br />

non-intervention, to ethico-juridical rights refl ects a<br />

more hierarchical and interventionist order, in which<br />

issues that were considered to be the domestic aff airs<br />

<strong>of</strong> states have become internationalized—from peace<br />

processes to issues <strong>of</strong> internal governance.<br />

<strong>Human</strong> rights provide the framework for this internationalization.<br />

As considered above, the dynamic<br />

behind intervention and internationalization is not<br />

straightforward, whether this is seen as a matter<br />

<strong>of</strong> reasserting imperialist power or as a refl ection<br />

<strong>of</strong> domestic concerns <strong>of</strong> self-identity, mission, and<br />

purpose—or positively as a confl uence <strong>of</strong> self-interest<br />

and altruism, or even an act <strong>of</strong> selfl ess altruism—the<br />

fact remains that human rights frameworks refl ect<br />

a world in which the enforcement <strong>of</strong> rights is an<br />

unequal and contingent one and where international<br />

relations are more open to ad hoc and arbitrary policy<br />

responses. However we choose to understand the<br />

drive behind growing human rights regimes <strong>of</strong> regulation<br />

and intervention, it would be wrong to see the<br />

abuse or misuse <strong>of</strong> power as being an exception rather<br />

than the rule.<br />

1. What is the difference between the subject <strong>of</strong> human rights and the subject <strong>of</strong> democratic and civil<br />

rights? Does it make a difference whether we claim rights as ‘humans’ or as ‘citizens’?<br />

2. How do human rights claims challenge the framework <strong>of</strong> law? Does this make these claims<br />

progressive? If not, why not?<br />

3. How did the framework <strong>of</strong> human rights help to legitimize the post-Second World War order based<br />

on state sovereignty? Did human rights clash with sovereignty during the Cold War? If not, why not?<br />

4. Why do human rights approaches challenge the legitimacy <strong>of</strong> state sovereignty and <strong>of</strong> international<br />

law?<br />

5. How has the debate on the relation between human rights and sovereignty changed between the<br />

1990s and the 2000s?<br />

6. What happens when state sovereignty is undermined? Does sovereignty go elsewhere? If so, where?<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 127 12/9/08 3:06:01 PM


128 DAVID CHANDLER<br />

7. In what ways do human rights approaches challenge traditional understandings <strong>of</strong> war? Is war more<br />

or less permissible under human rights frameworks?<br />

8. Are human rights interventions subject to the same strategic and instrumental processes <strong>of</strong> guidance<br />

as more interest-based or traditional policy interventions?<br />

GROUP DISCUSSION QUESTIONS<br />

1. How can we explain the rise <strong>of</strong> human rights frameworks and understandings? Is this purely the<br />

exercise <strong>of</strong> power interests? Does it refl ect the congruence <strong>of</strong> interests and ethical outlooks?<br />

2. Will human rights approaches result in a more ethical or a more peaceful or a more equal world?<br />

3. Do human rights constrain power or facilitate power?<br />

FURTHER READING<br />

<strong>Chandler</strong>, D. (2006). From Kosovo to Kabul: <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and International Intervention (2nd edn). London:<br />

Pluto.<br />

A study <strong>of</strong> human rights approaches as a challenge to universal frameworks <strong>of</strong> formal rights protection.<br />

Douzinas, C. (2007). <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong> and Empire: The Political Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Cosmopolitanism. London: Routledge<br />

Cavendish.<br />

An analysis <strong>of</strong> the double-edged nature <strong>of</strong> human rights as a tool both to challenge power and to enforce it.<br />

Duffi eld, M. (2007). Development, Security and Unending War: Governing the World <strong>of</strong> Peoples. Cambridge:<br />

Polity.<br />

An analysis <strong>of</strong> human rights frameworks in relation to the use <strong>of</strong> development interventions as mechanisms <strong>of</strong><br />

international domination.<br />

Ignatieff, M. (1998). The Warrior’s Honor: Ethnic War and the Modern Conscience. New York: Chatto & Windus.<br />

A study <strong>of</strong> the challenge that human rights approaches pose for the traditional humanitarianism <strong>of</strong> the ICRC.<br />

Laïdi, Z. (1998). A World without Meaning: The Crisis <strong>of</strong> Meaning in International Relations. London: Routledge.<br />

An analysis <strong>of</strong> the problems that Western governments have in developing clear foreign policy goals and the<br />

shift from interests to ethics.<br />

Sellars, K. (2002). The Rise and Rise <strong>of</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Rights</strong>. Stroud: Sutton.<br />

A history <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> human rights approaches during the Second World War and the US-led revival<br />

<strong>of</strong> human rights concerns in the 1970s.<br />

Zolo, D. (2002). Invoking <strong>Human</strong>ity: War, Law and Global Order. London: Continuum.<br />

An analysis <strong>of</strong> the challenge that human rights approaches pose to international law and the restrictions on war.<br />

WEB LINKS<br />

http://www.counterpunch.org CounterPunch. An online newsletter <strong>of</strong> critical journalism and comment.<br />

http://www.dissentmagazine.org Dissent. A quarterly magazine <strong>of</strong> politics and culture.<br />

http://www.newleftreview.org New Left Review. A bi-monthly independent journal.<br />

http://www.spiked-online.com Spiked. An independent website with journalistic commentary and analysis.<br />

http://www.zmag.org/zmag Z Magazine. An independent monthly magazine with critical analysis.<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 128 12/9/08 3:06:02 PM


NOTES<br />

IDEOLOGICAL (MIS)USE OF HUMAN RIGHTS 129<br />

1. Note the defence <strong>of</strong> case-by-case approaches in the work <strong>of</strong> normative theorists, such as Chris Brown<br />

(2007) and Richard Devetak (2007); for a critique, see <strong>Chandler</strong> (2008).<br />

ONLINE RESOURCE CENTRE<br />

Visit the Online Resource Centre that accompanies this book for updates and a range <strong>of</strong> other<br />

resources:<br />

http://www.oxfordtextbooks.co.uk/orc/goodhart/<br />

08-goodhart-chap07.indd 129 12/9/08 3:06:02 PM


08-goodhart-chap07.indd 130 12/9/08 3:06:04 PM

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!