02.03.2013 Views

Downloadable - About University

Downloadable - About University

Downloadable - About University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

368 Decision framing and cognitive inertia<br />

choices. Such incomplete appraisal of a decision may result in a failure<br />

to examine the risks of preferred decisions and a failure to work out<br />

contingency plans if the preferred course of action fails. A high level<br />

of group cohesiveness and a high external source of threat or stress<br />

are primary antecedents of groupthink. Overall, the consequences of<br />

groupthink will tend to magnify inertia processes.<br />

Framing effects have also been well documented in the behavioral<br />

decision literature. For example, recall the following problem called the<br />

‘Asian Disease Problem’ which we referred to in Chapter 5:<br />

Imagine that the US is preparing for the outbreak of an unusual Asian disease,<br />

which is expected to kill 600 people. Two alternative programs to combat the<br />

disease have been proposed. Assume that the exact scientific estimate of the<br />

consequences of the programs are as follows:<br />

If Program A is adopted, 200 will be saved. If Program B is adopted, there is<br />

a 1/3 probability that 600 people will be saved, and a 2/3 probability that no<br />

people will be saved.<br />

If you had to make the choice, which of the two programs would you<br />

favor? If you are like most of Tversky and Kahneman’s 27 respondents<br />

you will tend to favor Program A. Such a choice is risk averse, inthat<br />

the prospect of certainly saving 200 lives is more attractive than a risky<br />

prospect of equal expected value. However, imagine if, instead, you had<br />

been presented with the same cover story but with a different statement<br />

of the outcomes of the alternative programs, as follows:<br />

If Program C is adopted, 400 people will die.<br />

If Program D is adopted, there is a 1/3 probability that nobody will die, and<br />

a 2/3 probability that 600 people will die.<br />

In this formulation of the Asian Disease Problem, most respondents<br />

favor Program D. This option is risk taking in that the certain death of 400<br />

people is less acceptable than the two-in-three chance that 600 will die.<br />

As Tversky and Kahneman argue, choices involving gains (e.g.<br />

between Programs A and B) are often risk averse and choices involving<br />

losses (e.g. between Programs C and D) are often risk taking. Notice<br />

that the choice between A and B is identical to the choice between C and<br />

D. The only difference is that the first choice emphasizes lives saved<br />

and the second choice emphasizes lives lost. This simple change of frame<br />

produces a dramatic shift in choice.<br />

Russo and Schoemaker argue that, without realizing it, we tend to see<br />

reality through one frame at a time and that, once locked into a frame,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!