02.03.2013 Views

Downloadable - About University

Downloadable - About University

Downloadable - About University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

268 Biases in probability assessment<br />

example, he would argue that assessment of the probability (in 1986)<br />

that Saddam Hussein would invade Kuwait within the next five years<br />

is not a sensible question to pose, whereas assessment of the probability<br />

that a 17-year-old motorbike rider will make an insurance claim for a<br />

road accident is, because there is historic relative frequency information<br />

on claims by such riders. Gigerenzer 40 focuses on the usefulness of a distinction<br />

between single-event probabilities and frequencies and draws<br />

on evidence from both the history of probability and from experimental<br />

work in the psychological laboratory. He argues that empirical demonstrations<br />

of errors are not stable and that observed cognitive biases<br />

can disappear when the task of assessing single-event probabilities is<br />

changed to that of assessing frequencies. In one example, he restates<br />

the famous ‘Linda’ problem which we discussed earlier. Recall that the<br />

original Linda problem was:<br />

Linda is 31 years old, single, outspoken and very bright. She majored in<br />

philosophy. As a student, she was deeply concerned with issues of discrimination<br />

and social justice, and also participated in anti-nuclear demonstrations.<br />

Which of the alternatives is more probable:<br />

(A) Linda is a bank teller;<br />

(B) Linda is a bank teller and active in the feminist movement?<br />

In the above formulation of the Linda problem, about 90% of individuals<br />

who were given it responded that (B) was more probable than (A) – a<br />

demonstration of the conjunction fallacy. However, Gigerenzer showed<br />

that if the words ‘which of the alternatives is more probable?’ are replaced<br />

by the words ‘There are 100 people who fit the description above. How<br />

many of them are (A) bank tellers?, (B) bank tellers and active in the<br />

feminist movement?’, then the percentage of individuals who violate the<br />

conjunction law drops to less than 25%. Clearly, instructions to assess<br />

a frequency (i.e. how many?) facilitates more accurate thinking than<br />

instructions to assess a subjective probability (i.e. which of the alternatives<br />

is more probable?). Consider also a gambler betting on the spin<br />

of a roulette wheel. If the roulette wheel has produced an outcome of<br />

red for the last 10 spins then the gambler may feel that her subjective<br />

probability of black on the next spin should be higher than that for<br />

red. However, ask the same gambler the relative proportions of red to<br />

black on spins of the wheel and she may well answer 50–50. Since the<br />

roulette ball has no memory, it follows that the latter, relative frequency,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!