02.03.2013 Views

Downloadable - About University

Downloadable - About University

Downloadable - About University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

108 Decision making under uncertainty<br />

0.15 probability of −$10 000. Similarly, she will have a 0.4 probability of<br />

a profit, which is equivalent to a lottery ticket offering a 0.6 probability<br />

of $60 000 and a 0.4 chance of −$10 000. Therefore the Luxuria Hotel<br />

offers her the equivalent of a 0.6 × 0.85 + 0.4 × 0.6 = 0.75 probability of<br />

the best outcome (and a 0.25 probability of the worst outcome). Note<br />

that 0.75 is the expected utility of choosing the Luxuria Hotel.<br />

Obviously, choosing the Maxima Center offers her the equivalent<br />

of only a 0.5 probability of the best outcome on the tree (and a 0.5<br />

probability of the worst outcome). Thus, as shown in Figure 5.4(b), utility<br />

allows us to express the returns of all the courses of action in terms of<br />

simple lotteries all offering the same prizes, namely the best and worst<br />

outcomes, but with different probabilities. This makes the alternatives<br />

easy to compare. The probability of winning the best outcome in these<br />

lotteries is the expected utility. It therefore seems reasonable that we<br />

should select the option offering the highest expected utility.<br />

Note that the use here of the term ‘expected’ utility is therefore<br />

somewhat misleading. It is used because the procedure for calculating<br />

expected utilities is arithmetically the same as that for calculating<br />

expected values in statistics. It does not, however, necessarily refer to an<br />

average result which would be obtained from a large number of repetitions<br />

of a course of action, nor does it mean a result or consequence<br />

which should be ‘expected’. In decision theory, an ‘expected utility’<br />

is only a ‘certainty equivalent’, that is, a single ‘certain’ figure that is<br />

equivalent in preference to the uncertain situations.<br />

Interpreting utility functions<br />

The business woman’s utility function has been plotted on a graph in<br />

Figure 5.5. If we selected any two points on this curve and drew a<br />

straight line between them then it can be seen that the curve would<br />

always be above the line. Utility functions having this concave shape<br />

provide evidence of risk aversion (which is consistent with the business<br />

woman’s avoidance of the riskiest option).<br />

This is easily demonstrated. Consider Figure 5.6, which shows a utility<br />

function with a similar shape, and suppose that the decision maker, from<br />

whom this function has been elicited, has assets of $1000. He is then<br />

offered a gamble which will give him a 50% chance of doubling his<br />

money to $2000 and a 50% chance of losing it all, so that he finishes<br />

with $0. The expected monetary value of the gamble is $1000 (i.e.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!