20.02.2013 Views

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

From humanized war to intervention 65<br />

into an archetypically liberal notion: the political basis <strong>of</strong> decisions to use force<br />

that was characteristic <strong>of</strong> the jus publicum Europaeum is replaced by a legalistic<br />

and moralistic account <strong>of</strong> the justification for force.<br />

This is, I believe, a quite compelling argument, and it defines the task for<br />

anyone who wishes to continue to use Just War notions in thinking about international<br />

relations, which I do; effectively one must redraw the idea <strong>of</strong> the Just<br />

War so that it neither reflects a lost medieval Christian order, nor fits into<br />

contemporary, liberal, moral reasoning. This may seem to be a tall order, but I<br />

believe it is actually much less difficult than one might imagine, because<br />

<strong>Schmitt</strong>’s way <strong>of</strong> setting up the problem excludes or devalues a line <strong>of</strong> reasoning<br />

that is the product neither <strong>of</strong> the respublica Christiana nor <strong>of</strong> contemporary liberalism,<br />

a line <strong>of</strong> reasoning <strong>of</strong>ten termed ‘neo-Aristotelian’. Such reasoning<br />

follows the Aristotelian injunction, summarized by Stephen Toulmin, that<br />

‘sound moral judgment always respects the detailed circumstances <strong>of</strong> specific<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> cases’ (1990: 32). Along with <strong>Schmitt</strong>, neo-Aristotelianism is critical <strong>of</strong><br />

the search for universal legal and/or moral rules, and, again following <strong>Schmitt</strong>,<br />

neo-Aristotelians associate this tendency with the characteristic moral theories<br />

<strong>of</strong> liberalism, in particular Kantianism and utilitarianism. However, unlike<br />

<strong>Schmitt</strong>, Toulmin at least locates the origin <strong>of</strong> this tendency not with the Anglo-<br />

American thought <strong>of</strong> the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, but much earlier –<br />

in fact, just at the point where <strong>Schmitt</strong>’s jus publicum Europaeum is first established,<br />

in the early seventeenth century.<br />

This is when, Toulmin argues, the moral insights <strong>of</strong> Renaissance humanism<br />

and the classical world were put aside. Under the influence <strong>of</strong> Descartes and<br />

Hobbes, along with many lesser talents, formal logic came to displace rhetoric,<br />

general principles and abstract axioms were privileged over particular cases and<br />

concrete diversity, and the establishment <strong>of</strong> rules (or ‘laws’) that were deemed<br />

<strong>of</strong> permanent as opposed to transitory applicability came to be seen as the task<br />

<strong>of</strong> the theorist. Toulmin suggests that at this time moral reasoning became<br />

‘theory-centered’ rather than ‘practically-minded’ (1990: 34). Moral reasoning<br />

became a matter <strong>of</strong> following a theoretically validated rule, rather than <strong>of</strong><br />

making a practical judgement, and was impoverished thereby, losing the<br />

emphasis on cultivating the facility for the making <strong>of</strong> moral judgements which,<br />

as Bernard Williams has maintained, was characteristic <strong>of</strong> older, pre-modern or<br />

classical moral philosophies (1985, 1993). Toulmin and Williams are not, <strong>of</strong><br />

course, alone in holding this position; in recent years, there has been a revival <strong>of</strong><br />

interest in Greek moral theory, and, in particular, in the notion <strong>of</strong> the ‘virtues’ –<br />

those qualities <strong>of</strong> mind that human beings can cultivate in order to enable them<br />

to be more effective moral agents. (Anscombe 1958; Nussbaum 1993: Crisp<br />

1996; Statman 1997).<br />

Neo-Aristotelian thought places Just War theory in a new light; if we return<br />

to the set <strong>of</strong> questions outlined on p. 57 we can see that they are actually not best<br />

understood as comprising a set <strong>of</strong> rules that invite a yes/no answer, a tick in a<br />

box. Rather, they invite the exercise <strong>of</strong> different kinds <strong>of</strong> political and moral<br />

judgement. <strong>The</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> a ‘just cause’ for action calls for precisely the kind

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!