20.02.2013 Views

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

32 A. Colombo<br />

liberal critics <strong>of</strong> realism, <strong>Schmitt</strong> does not attribute this crisis to the dissolution<br />

<strong>of</strong> politics into economics, or the state into economic globalization; on the contrary,<br />

he attributes it to the state’s inability to grasp the new current <strong>of</strong> political<br />

intensity (<strong>Schmitt</strong> 1996, 2004b). Once enmity retransforms itself from the relative<br />

into the absolute, states are ‘no longer able to integrate their own members<br />

and adherents so totally as a revolutionary party does its active fighters’ (<strong>Schmitt</strong><br />

2004b: 10). As always in <strong>Schmitt</strong>’s reflections, it is the evolution <strong>of</strong> the political<br />

that breaks up the old politico-juridical edifice <strong>of</strong> politics and war. Once the ‘old<br />

regularity’ <strong>of</strong> the state is ‘worn down to mere convention and game’, a new<br />

figure capable <strong>of</strong> restoring ‘the seriousness <strong>of</strong> war’ arises (<strong>Schmitt</strong> 2004b: 63).<br />

This figure is the partisan, not the technician or the entrepreneur, who sweeps<br />

away the state’s grip on politics and war. <strong>The</strong> inconceivability <strong>of</strong> war among<br />

states promises not peace but, rather, an outflow <strong>of</strong> violence that overcomes the<br />

state.<br />

<strong>Schmitt</strong>’s realist institutionalism reveals itself to be a philosophy <strong>of</strong> crisis.<br />

Lacking a spatial localization and an adequate bearer <strong>of</strong> order, the new international<br />

law is condemned, on the one hand, to mirror the modern utopia <strong>of</strong> malleability<br />

and social engineering and, on the other, to lose itself in modern<br />

immanence, in a historically unavoidable degenerative process that recalls the<br />

opposition between Kultur and Zivilisation, typical <strong>of</strong> German culture <strong>of</strong> the<br />

period. It is no accident that <strong>Schmitt</strong> compares the ‘generic international law’<br />

that emerges from the dissolution <strong>of</strong> the jus publicum Europaeum to other ‘generalizations’<br />

deprived <strong>of</strong> a topos: first, that <strong>of</strong> the Hellenistic age, when the polis<br />

had already been transformed into a cosmopolis (<strong>Schmitt</strong> 2003: 50); and second,<br />

to the declining stage <strong>of</strong> the concrete Christian medieval order, when the concepts<br />

<strong>of</strong> scholasticism and medieval jurisprudence were maintained while<br />

deprived <strong>of</strong> their spatial dimension (ibid.: 133–138; 181–182). In the latter case,<br />

<strong>Schmitt</strong> interestingly observes that the combination <strong>of</strong> the concepts <strong>of</strong> scholasticism<br />

and medieval jurisprudence with those <strong>of</strong> humanistic juridical science or<br />

the preceding Roman law resulted in a ‘manner <strong>of</strong> thinking and speaking reminiscent<br />

<strong>of</strong> the disorientation <strong>of</strong> many purely juridical apologists during the last<br />

world war’ (ibid.: 182).<br />

<strong>The</strong> demise <strong>of</strong> the anarchical society <strong>of</strong> states, which liberal institutionalism<br />

and democratic globalism see as paving the way towards a global society and a<br />

universalistic vision <strong>of</strong> international law and order, is reversed by <strong>Schmitt</strong> in the<br />

fall into a formless universe, the last manifestation <strong>of</strong> the ‘connection between<br />

utopia and nihilism’ (ibid.: 66). Instead <strong>of</strong> focusing on the proliferation <strong>of</strong> international<br />

regimes and organizations, so celebrated by liberal institutionalists,<br />

<strong>Schmitt</strong> shifts his attention to the new law’s inability to give war a legal answer,<br />

that is, to provide the response on which the effectiveness <strong>of</strong> international law<br />

always depends. <strong>The</strong> revival <strong>of</strong> the doctrine <strong>of</strong> the just war, in which legal globalism<br />

recognizes a return to the most ancient and sound conceptions <strong>of</strong> war,<br />

appears, according to <strong>Schmitt</strong>, as the very expression <strong>of</strong> the powerlessness and<br />

abstractness <strong>of</strong> the new law (ibid.: 119–125). In comparison to its medieval<br />

precedent, it lacks reference to a concrete institutional order, an adequate bearer

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!