20.02.2013 Views

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

232 S. Prozorov<br />

such as the truth <strong>of</strong> divine law, rationality or even pragmatic utility. <strong>The</strong> only<br />

mode <strong>of</strong> subjection that <strong>Schmitt</strong>’s ontology permits is what we have referred to<br />

above as existential decisionism, a commitment to a position in spite <strong>of</strong> the<br />

impossibility <strong>of</strong> its grounding. This stance can be described in Paul Veyne’s<br />

terms as a fulfilment <strong>of</strong> nihilism. Veyne approaches nihilism as ‘a name we give<br />

to periods <strong>of</strong> history when thinkers feel that truths are without foundation’<br />

(1992: 242). In this understanding nihilism is constituted by, first, a recognition<br />

<strong>of</strong> the absence <strong>of</strong> foundations <strong>of</strong> truth, morality and politics and, second, the<br />

desire to have such foundations. <strong>The</strong> properly nihilistic response to this existential<br />

condition may consist either in the hypocritical attempts to invent new<br />

foundations for judgement (‘incomplete nihilism’ in Nietzsche’s terms) or in the<br />

passive-nihilist abandonment <strong>of</strong> all judgement due to its necessary contingency.<br />

In contrast to such critics as Michael Walzer (1986) and Nancy Fraser (1995),<br />

Veyne interprets Foucault’s work as the ‘fulfilment <strong>of</strong> nihilism’ that accepts the<br />

first assumption <strong>of</strong> nihilism but rejects the second, claiming instead that it is the<br />

very impossibility <strong>of</strong> founding norms that makes possible ethical action. Similarly,<br />

Veyne suggests that the absence <strong>of</strong> secure foundations does not disable<br />

judgement, but merely disables giving one’s judgement the force <strong>of</strong> truth or<br />

moral law. ‘What remains is to live and to want what one wants without justifying<br />

oneself and saying that one is right’ (Veyne 1992: 243).<br />

It is important to distinguish this affirmation <strong>of</strong> decisionism from the deconstructionist<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> the ‘impossibility’ <strong>of</strong> decision, highlighted in the<br />

‘ethical’ writings <strong>of</strong> the later Derrida (1992, 1996). Like <strong>Schmitt</strong>’s insistence on<br />

the decision emanating from nothingness, deconstructionist ethics affirms undecidability<br />

as the condition <strong>of</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> every decision. In Derrida’s supplementary<br />

deconstruction <strong>of</strong> <strong>Schmitt</strong>’s approach, any decisionism necessarily<br />

contains the ‘aporia <strong>of</strong> decision’, the passage through the ‘ordeal undecidable’,<br />

the experience <strong>of</strong> the ‘perhaps’ that is both traversed and effaced (but not<br />

annulled) in the act <strong>of</strong> decision (Derrida 1996: 67). It is this effacement that<br />

deconstruction seeks to restore to the decisions already taken in order to reassert<br />

their radically undecidable nature, irreducible to the procedure <strong>of</strong> derivation. As<br />

we have seen, <strong>Schmitt</strong> may be considered a devout Derridean in this aspect,<br />

given his insistence on the impossibility <strong>of</strong> grounding a genuine decision. It is<br />

rather in assessing the consequences <strong>of</strong> this originary undecidability that <strong>Schmitt</strong><br />

and Derrida part ways. In contrast to <strong>Schmitt</strong>, Derrida is characteristically hesitant<br />

to affirm the necessary effacement <strong>of</strong> undecidability in the very act <strong>of</strong><br />

making the decision. Instead, his deconstructed decisionism appears to be locked<br />

in a self-imposed suspension over the abyss <strong>of</strong> undecidability in the desire to<br />

refrain from the closure that every decision inaugurates, which makes it, in Derridean<br />

ethics, always inadequate and irresponsible.<br />

<strong>The</strong> deconstructionist ethics <strong>of</strong> (in)decision therefore remains suspended in<br />

irresolution and impotence, a deadlock which can only be broken via its supplementation<br />

with a <strong>Schmitt</strong>ian decisionism, <strong>of</strong> which it is allegedly itself a supplement.<br />

<strong>The</strong> insistence on the need to decide despite the a priori ‘ethical<br />

inadequacy’ <strong>of</strong> every decision is necessary for deconstruction not to appear, in

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!