20.02.2013 Views

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

212 M. Ojakangas<br />

enemy (‘the enemy is a negated otherness’ (ibid.: 63)) and to define enmity in<br />

Hegelian terms (‘in the reciprocal recognition <strong>of</strong> recognition [Anerkennung der<br />

Anerkennung] lies the greatness <strong>of</strong> the concept’ (<strong>Schmitt</strong> 1950: 89)), the core <strong>of</strong><br />

the concept is nevertheless absolutely anti-Hegelian. This is because, for Hegel,<br />

what remains outside the concept – outside objective knowledge – is identical to<br />

nothing. In other words, what does not make a difference in terms <strong>of</strong> objective<br />

knowledge makes no difference at all (cf. Hegel 1977: 58–66). For <strong>Schmitt</strong>, the<br />

enemy is precisely something that remains outside the concept and outside objective<br />

knowledge. Certainly, for <strong>Schmitt</strong> too, the enemy is something objective, but<br />

this objectivity is not the objectivity <strong>of</strong> concept but that <strong>of</strong> power (Macht): ‘<strong>The</strong><br />

enemy is an objective power’ (<strong>Schmitt</strong> 1950: 89), not a ‘metaphor or symbol’<br />

(<strong>Schmitt</strong> 1996a: 27). As an objective power, the enemy ceases to be a mere<br />

concept and therefore a passing stage <strong>of</strong> negation, becoming a genuine interruption<br />

– not only <strong>of</strong> a dialectical development <strong>of</strong> history but also <strong>of</strong> objective knowledge.<br />

Certainly, this power can, and in <strong>Schmitt</strong>’s view must, become an object <strong>of</strong> knowledge<br />

and reflection because the self is the result <strong>of</strong> such reflection – the enemy is a<br />

‘measure <strong>of</strong> myself’ (<strong>Schmitt</strong> 2004: 72) – but this can occur only after the event,<br />

namely the appearance <strong>of</strong> the enemy, has taken place. Even then the intellect is not<br />

capable <strong>of</strong> exhausting the enemy completely, because the event is not prior to<br />

knowledge and reflection merely in a temporal sense, but also, and above all, ontologically.<br />

<strong>The</strong> enemy is the other and no amount <strong>of</strong> reflection can reduce its otherness<br />

into an immanence <strong>of</strong> the same. 6<br />

However, like all <strong>Schmitt</strong>’s central concepts, the enemy is also a constitutive<br />

concept. <strong>The</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> the enemy is the concrete precondition <strong>of</strong> the collective<br />

identity <strong>of</strong> friends. It is the enemy who brings about the ‘existential affinity’<br />

<strong>of</strong> those ‘who just happen to live together’ (<strong>Schmitt</strong> 1993b: 210). In other words,<br />

the enemy is not only a counter-concept to immanence but also a transcendent<br />

fundamental concept. Yet the enemy is not a substantial foundation <strong>of</strong> order,<br />

because the enemy has no substance but only a form, an empty form: ‘An enemy<br />

is whoever calls me into question’ (<strong>Schmitt</strong> 1988: 217). This is the reason why I<br />

cannot agree with those who argue that <strong>Schmitt</strong>’s concept <strong>of</strong> the enemy is essentialist.<br />

7 <strong>The</strong> enemy is not a natural given in <strong>Schmitt</strong>’s theory. <strong>The</strong> enemy, ‘the<br />

most extreme intensification <strong>of</strong> otherness’ (<strong>Schmitt</strong> 1992: 38), is thoroughly<br />

contingent. <strong>The</strong> enemy may be another race, speak another language, pr<strong>of</strong>ess<br />

another religion or represent another culture. Nevertheless, there exists no a<br />

priori criterion either for the enemy or for the friend in <strong>Schmitt</strong>’s theory. <strong>The</strong><br />

enemy is anyone who is concretely disclosed as a real threat, as the one who<br />

calls me into question. Moreover, the enemy calls me into question only at the<br />

moment ‘in which the enemy is, in concrete clarity, recognized as the enemy’<br />

(<strong>Schmitt</strong> 1996a: 67). <strong>The</strong> enemy is, in other words, an event – a double event <strong>of</strong><br />

appearing and recognition. It is this event that founds an order. However, this<br />

order is completely different from the totally administered Babylonian unity <strong>of</strong><br />

the world. It is an order based not on worldwide control <strong>of</strong> humanity but on the<br />

tension between separate political entities. It is a political order – and where<br />

there is the political, there is openness.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!