20.02.2013 Views

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Introduction 7<br />

According to <strong>Schmitt</strong>, this is the major achievement <strong>of</strong> Westphalia: the interstate<br />

order which existed in Europe until 1914 had sought, through its international<br />

law, ‘to prevent wars <strong>of</strong> annihilation, i.e. to the extent that war was inevitable, to<br />

bracket it’ (ibid.: 246). It did not, on the contrary, seek to end war as such, to<br />

abolish or banish it from its international relations since it implicitly recognised<br />

that ‘any abolition <strong>of</strong> war without true bracketing resulted only in new, perhaps<br />

even worse types <strong>of</strong> war, such as reversions to civil war and other types <strong>of</strong> wars<br />

<strong>of</strong> annihilation’ (ibid.). It rather sought to find ways in which to gauge the opponent’s<br />

strength, usually by striving for appropriation <strong>of</strong> lands in the New World<br />

or by fighting limited wars on European soil, and by recognising the opponent as<br />

an enemy on equal grounds – as a justus hostis.<br />

<strong>The</strong> development <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> justus hostis was the key to such an<br />

achievement. <strong>The</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> an ‘equal and just enemy’ evolved alongside the<br />

consolidation <strong>of</strong> the modern state. With the predominance <strong>of</strong> this type <strong>of</strong> political<br />

entity and the weakening <strong>of</strong> the moral authority <strong>of</strong> the Church, war became<br />

‘non-discriminatory’, that is, divorced from substantive causes <strong>of</strong> justice or justa<br />

causa. Since war was the means by which land could change ownership status,<br />

‘war came to be judged in terms <strong>of</strong> its outcome’ and became a form <strong>of</strong> political<br />

relation among states (ibid.: 100). Any enemy that had the form <strong>of</strong> a state was a<br />

just enemy and war could be waged against it. This development enabled the<br />

avoidance <strong>of</strong> wars <strong>of</strong> conviction, creed and religion (that is, based on substantive<br />

issues <strong>of</strong> justice) which had historically caused tremendous destruction, and <strong>of</strong><br />

possible annihilation <strong>of</strong> enemies. For <strong>Schmitt</strong>, whose belief was that war was an<br />

inevitable part <strong>of</strong> political life, this regulation <strong>of</strong> war without substantive cause<br />

meant a ‘rationalization, humanization and legalization’ <strong>of</strong> war. Regarding an<br />

enemy as both a just and an equal partner meant that peace could be made with<br />

that enemy – his ultimate destruction was not sought, but conflict with him was<br />

possible and regulated.<br />

As a consequence, war became a ‘ “war in form”, une guerre en forme’ (ibid.:<br />

141) whereby the justice <strong>of</strong> war no longer had anything to do with the causes <strong>of</strong><br />

war, but was concerned only with the formal adequacy <strong>of</strong> the belligerents: they<br />

had to be justi hostes, bearer <strong>of</strong> the jus belli, that is, European sovereign states.<br />

In other words, ‘war became somewhat analogous to a duel, i.e. a conflict <strong>of</strong><br />

arms between territorially distinct personae morales’ (ibid.), part <strong>of</strong> the European<br />

‘family’ <strong>of</strong> the jus publicum Europaeum. Such wars, <strong>Schmitt</strong> suggests,<br />

were the very ‘opposite <strong>of</strong> disorder’ (ibid.: 187).<br />

<strong>The</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> the just enemy, moreover, meant that such a system <strong>of</strong> war<br />

allowed for both resistance and self-defence: given that the enemy was a priori<br />

just, its right to self-defence and to resistance was recognised, precisely because<br />

the issue <strong>of</strong> just cause was eliminated. This also allowed for the development <strong>of</strong><br />

the institution <strong>of</strong> neutrality for third-party states in international law. <strong>The</strong> only<br />

unjust war was the non-state or private war: rebels, pirates, outlaws, perturbateurs<br />

are not justi hostes but criminals and as such they have to be dealt with<br />

through punitive actions in the sense <strong>of</strong> modern criminal law.<br />

As a result, the jus publicum Europaeum allowed for the construction and

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!