11RXNdQ

11RXNdQ 11RXNdQ

public.archive
from public.archive More from this publisher
19.02.2013 Views

‘In spite of Sartre’s goal to defend Jewish “plight”’, Kritzman remarks, ‘his focusing on Jewish characteristics, and on Jewishness as a socially constructed way of being, led him to formulate a negatively conceived essentialism on what he termed the “Jewish question”’.’ 20 Kritzman intimates that the Sartrean model, which is predicated upon a dialectical relation between the anti-Semite and Jew, between self and Other, between sameness and difference, constructs Jewishness as ‘the result of the gaze of the anti- Semite’. 21 The Sartrean situation, according to Kritzman, ‘produces a sense of difference derived from the petrifying order of the same’. 22 He levels the charge against Sartre of constructing ‘the “Jew” [as] both the sight (the vision) and the site (the locus) of the anti- Semite’s existence. Within this framework, the “Jew”’ becomes the repository of absolute hatred.’ Kritzman conflates the gaze of the anti-Semite with Sartre’s analyses of the discourse of anti-Semitism which scapegoats and excludes the Jew. Kritzman is wrong to suggest that Sartre (or at least his model of analysis) ‘overdetermines Jewish subjectivity and makes it the effect of the anti-Semite’s visual prowess’. 23 Kritzman attributes to Sartre the object of his critique: anti-Semitism. Two problems marred the intervention of Sartre’s Anti-Semite and Jew: Sartre is accused of voiding Jewishness as a category of its historical and religious content; his Zionism is a thorny issue. In Black Orpheus, Sartre enlarges upon the key crucial ideas in his Anti-Semite and Jew: that the gaze of the white creates the Negro, and that these two protagonists are involved in a situation which perpetrates the racism of the former vis-à-vis the latter. According to Sartre, belonging to a given society is bound up with what he calls ‘the untranslatable elocution of its language’ which hypostatizes its specific traits. 24 Because of the diasporic character, the disciples of Négritude have to write their ‘gospel in French’. 25 French was the only medium available to them through which they could communicate. By adopting the French language, these writers found themselves in the paradoxical situation of espousing the very culture that they were bent on rejecting. 26 As Sartre points out, they speak in order to destroy the language in which the oppressor is present: their main project is to ‘de-gallicize’ its signifiers. 27 He describes the poetry of Négritude as a sort of ‘auto-holocaust’: the ‘conflagration’ of the language. Arguably, Sartre anticipates deconstruction. He argues that the moment they overthrow a language consecrating the priority of white over black, not only do they overturn the hierarchical coupling of this binary and all the conceptual oppositions which perpetrate the rhetoric of difference, but they poeticize this language. 28 Sartre warns that this poetry is racial, written not for the white, replicating in its struggle the impetus of white racism. Unlike the other oppressed minorities in white societies, whether these represent a class interest or an ethic group, the black cannot deny that he or she is black. That is to say, the black cannot lose him/herself in an ‘abstract uncolored humanity’. 29 They are no ‘avenues of escape’ for the Negro who is ‘held to authenticity’. 30 Because the white has thus far deprecated the blackness of the Negro, Négritude is the only avenue open to the Negro for freedom. Négritude is the Negro’s consciousness of race and the Negro’s coming to terms with his/her situation as black. Sartre perceives the mythopoetics of Négritude as a necessary step in a dialectical movement which will bring white and black together in a classless society. In his terms, Negritude appears as the weak stage of a dialectical progression: the theoretical

and practical affirmation of white supremacy is the thesis; the position of Negritude as antithetical value is the moment of the negativity. But this negative moment is not sufficient in itself and the blacks who employ it well know it; they know that it serves to prepare the way for the synthesis or the realization of the human society without racism. Thus Negritude is dedicated to its own destruction, it is passage and objective, means and not the ultimate goal. 31 In response to this, Fanon writes in Black Skin, White Masks: ‘When I read that page, I felt I had been robbed of my last chance. I said to my friends, “The generation of the younger black poets had just suffered a blow that can never be forgiven.” Help had been sought from a friend of the coloured peoples, and that friend had found no better response than to point out the relativity of what they were doing.’ 32 In Fanon’s view, Black Orpheus ‘is a date in the intellectualization of the experience of being black’. According to Fanon, Sartre presents the poetry of Négritude as the source of revolutionary politics, but blocks this source of its poetic spring by abstracting the experience of being black. Fanon argues that ‘black consciousness is immanent in its own eyes’. 33 Negro consciousness must not therefore be seen as a negative term in a dialectical schema, as a lack; it is not the potential of something, but it is wholly what it is. In the concluding section of his book, however, Fanon comes round to Sartre’s way of thinking that negritude is the only means to overcome the differences of race, but that this anti-racist racism cannot be an end in itself. Fanon clearly realizes the dangers of its totalizing and racialized language and therefore refuses to ‘derive [his] basic purpose from the past of the peoples of color’. 34 Sartre envisaged the solution to the problem of racism in a Marxist eschatology: a classless society. I speculate that the absence of Sartre from the postcolonial agenda can be attributed to his tendency to reduce the colonial problematic to a notion of class struggle and to seek to resolve this problematic in a Marxist eschatology. One of the consequences of this solution in existential-humanist Marxism is the perceived reduction of difference to a negative concept: the voided character of the Jew and the negativity of Négritude. As we shall see, this would leave Sartre open to the accusation of being ethnocentric. Clearly what is at stake is his Marxism. III When Sartre moved to the Left in 1952, at the pinnacle of the Cold War, most French intellectuals distanced themselves from the PCF. As F. Dosse points out, the Rassemblement Démocratique which brought together prominent intellectuals such as André Breton, Albert Camus and Sartre disintegrated. 35 After the publication of L’Homme révolté, Sartre became embroiled with Camus in a controversy. In the summer of 1952, Merleau-Ponty left Les Temps Modernes, and in 1955 in Les Aventures de la dialectique, he dismisses Sartre’s politics as Bolshevistic. These two controversies signalled a change in the attitude of French intellectuals towards communism and political commitment. The political ground shifted: Lévi-Strauss, Louis Althusser and Michel Foucault emerged to challenge Sartreanism. To echo Dosse, the eclipse of Sartre

and practical affirmation of white supremacy is the thesis; the position of<br />

Negritude as antithetical value is the moment of the negativity. But this negative<br />

moment is not sufficient in itself and the blacks who employ it well know it;<br />

they know that it serves to prepare the way for the synthesis or the realization of<br />

the human society without racism. Thus Negritude is dedicated to its own<br />

destruction, it is passage and objective, means and not the ultimate goal. 31<br />

In response to this, Fanon writes in Black Skin, White Masks: ‘When I read that page, I<br />

felt I had been robbed of my last chance. I said to my friends, “The generation of the<br />

younger black poets had just suffered a blow that can never be forgiven.” Help had been<br />

sought from a friend of the coloured peoples, and that friend had found no better response<br />

than to point out the relativity of what they were doing.’ 32 In Fanon’s view, Black<br />

Orpheus ‘is a date in the intellectualization of the experience of being black’. According<br />

to Fanon, Sartre presents the poetry of Négritude as the source of revolutionary politics,<br />

but blocks this source of its poetic spring by abstracting the experience of being black.<br />

Fanon argues that ‘black consciousness is immanent in its own eyes’. 33 Negro<br />

consciousness must not therefore be seen as a negative term in a dialectical schema, as a<br />

lack; it is not the potential of something, but it is wholly what it is. In the concluding<br />

section of his book, however, Fanon comes round to Sartre’s way of thinking that<br />

negritude is the only means to overcome the differences of race, but that this anti-racist<br />

racism cannot be an end in itself. Fanon clearly realizes the dangers of its totalizing and<br />

racialized language and therefore refuses to ‘derive [his] basic purpose from the past of<br />

the peoples of color’. 34<br />

Sartre envisaged the solution to the problem of racism in a Marxist eschatology: a<br />

classless society. I speculate that the absence of Sartre from the postcolonial agenda can<br />

be attributed to his tendency to reduce the colonial problematic to a notion of class<br />

struggle and to seek to resolve this problematic in a Marxist eschatology. One of the<br />

consequences of this solution in existential-humanist Marxism is the perceived reduction<br />

of difference to a negative concept: the voided character of the Jew and the negativity of<br />

Négritude. As we shall see, this would leave Sartre open to the accusation of being<br />

ethnocentric. Clearly what is at stake is his Marxism.<br />

III<br />

When Sartre moved to the Left in 1952, at the pinnacle of the Cold War, most French<br />

intellectuals distanced themselves from the PCF. As F. Dosse points out, the<br />

Rassemblement Démocratique which brought together prominent intellectuals such as<br />

André Breton, Albert Camus and Sartre disintegrated. 35 After the publication of<br />

L’Homme révolté, Sartre became embroiled with Camus in a controversy. In the summer<br />

of 1952, Merleau-Ponty left Les Temps Modernes, and in 1955 in Les Aventures de la<br />

dialectique, he dismisses Sartre’s politics as Bolshevistic. These two controversies<br />

signalled a change in the attitude of French intellectuals towards communism and<br />

political commitment. The political ground shifted: Lévi-Strauss, Louis Althusser and<br />

Michel Foucault emerged to challenge Sartreanism. To echo Dosse, the eclipse of Sartre

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!